HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 46 of 133)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 4501-4600   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremtfisi 4501* A transfinite induction scheme in "implicit" form where the induction is done on an object derived from the object of interest. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Aug-2015.)
(𝜑𝐴𝑉)    &   (𝜑𝑇 ∈ On)    &   ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑅 ∈ On ∧ 𝑅𝑇) ∧ ∀𝑦(𝑆𝑅𝜒)) → 𝜓)    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓𝜃))    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦𝑅 = 𝑆)    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴𝑅 = 𝑇)       (𝜑𝜃)
 
2.6  IZF Set Theory - add the Axiom of Infinity
 
2.6.1  Introduce the Axiom of Infinity
 
Axiomax-iinf 4502* Axiom of Infinity. Axiom 5 of [Crosilla] p. "Axioms of CZF and IZF". (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Nov-2018.)
𝑥(∅ ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦(𝑦𝑥 → suc 𝑦𝑥))
 
Theoremzfinf2 4503* A standard version of the Axiom of Infinity, using definitions to abbreviate. Axiom Inf of [BellMachover] p. 472. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.)
𝑥(∅ ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦𝑥 suc 𝑦𝑥)
 
2.6.2  The natural numbers (i.e. finite ordinals)
 
Syntaxcom 4504 Extend class notation to include the class of natural numbers.
class ω
 
Definitiondf-iom 4505* Define the class of natural numbers as the smallest inductive set, which is valid provided we assume the Axiom of Infinity. Definition 6.3 of [Eisenberg] p. 82.

Note: the natural numbers ω are a subset of the ordinal numbers df-on 4290. Later, when we define complex numbers, we will be able to also define a subset of the complex numbers with analogous properties and operations, but they will be different sets. (Contributed by NM, 6-Aug-1994.) Use its alias dfom3 4506 instead for naming consistency with set.mm. (New usage is discouraged.)

ω = {𝑥 ∣ (∅ ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦𝑥 suc 𝑦𝑥)}
 
Theoremdfom3 4506* Alias for df-iom 4505. Use it instead of df-iom 4505 for naming consistency with set.mm. (Contributed by NM, 6-Aug-1994.)
ω = {𝑥 ∣ (∅ ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦𝑥 suc 𝑦𝑥)}
 
Theoremomex 4507 The existence of omega (the class of natural numbers). Axiom 7 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 43. (Contributed by NM, 6-Aug-1994.)
ω ∈ V
 
2.6.3  Peano's postulates
 
Theorempeano1 4508 Zero is a natural number. One of Peano's five postulates for arithmetic. Proposition 7.30(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 42. (Contributed by NM, 15-May-1994.)
∅ ∈ ω
 
Theorempeano2 4509 The successor of any natural number is a natural number. One of Peano's five postulates for arithmetic. Proposition 7.30(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 42. (Contributed by NM, 3-Sep-2003.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → suc 𝐴 ∈ ω)
 
Theorempeano3 4510 The successor of any natural number is not zero. One of Peano's five postulates for arithmetic. Proposition 7.30(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 42. (Contributed by NM, 3-Sep-2003.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → suc 𝐴 ≠ ∅)
 
Theorempeano4 4511 Two natural numbers are equal iff their successors are equal, i.e. the successor function is one-to-one. One of Peano's five postulates for arithmetic. Proposition 7.30(4) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 43. (Contributed by NM, 3-Sep-2003.)
((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (suc 𝐴 = suc 𝐵𝐴 = 𝐵))
 
Theorempeano5 4512* The induction postulate: any class containing zero and closed under the successor operation contains all natural numbers. One of Peano's five postulates for arithmetic. Proposition 7.30(5) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 43. The more traditional statement of mathematical induction as a theorem schema, with a basis and an induction step, is derived from this theorem as theorem findes 4517. (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2004.)
((∅ ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝑥𝐴 → suc 𝑥𝐴)) → ω ⊆ 𝐴)
 
2.6.4  Finite induction (for finite ordinals)
 
Theoremfind 4513* The Principle of Finite Induction (mathematical induction). Corollary 7.31 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 43. The simpler hypothesis shown here was suggested in an email from "Colin" on 1-Oct-2001. The hypothesis states that 𝐴 is a set of natural numbers, zero belongs to 𝐴, and given any member of 𝐴 the member's successor also belongs to 𝐴. The conclusion is that every natural number is in 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 22-Feb-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 27-Aug-2011.)
(𝐴 ⊆ ω ∧ ∅ ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴 suc 𝑥𝐴)       𝐴 = ω
 
Theoremfinds 4514* Principle of Finite Induction (inference schema), using implicit substitutions. The first four hypotheses establish the substitutions we need. The last two are the basis and the induction step. Theorem Schema 22 of [Suppes] p. 136. This is Metamath 100 proof #74. (Contributed by NM, 14-Apr-1995.)
(𝑥 = ∅ → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜒))    &   (𝑥 = suc 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜃))    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜏))    &   𝜓    &   (𝑦 ∈ ω → (𝜒𝜃))       (𝐴 ∈ ω → 𝜏)
 
Theoremfinds2 4515* Principle of Finite Induction (inference schema), using implicit substitutions. The first three hypotheses establish the substitutions we need. The last two are the basis and the induction step. Theorem Schema 22 of [Suppes] p. 136. (Contributed by NM, 29-Nov-2002.)
(𝑥 = ∅ → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜒))    &   (𝑥 = suc 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜃))    &   (𝜏𝜓)    &   (𝑦 ∈ ω → (𝜏 → (𝜒𝜃)))       (𝑥 ∈ ω → (𝜏𝜑))
 
Theoremfinds1 4516* Principle of Finite Induction (inference schema), using implicit substitutions. The first three hypotheses establish the substitutions we need. The last two are the basis and the induction step. Theorem Schema 22 of [Suppes] p. 136. (Contributed by NM, 22-Mar-2006.)
(𝑥 = ∅ → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜒))    &   (𝑥 = suc 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜃))    &   𝜓    &   (𝑦 ∈ ω → (𝜒𝜃))       (𝑥 ∈ ω → 𝜑)
 
Theoremfindes 4517 Finite induction with explicit substitution. The first hypothesis is the basis and the second is the induction step. Theorem Schema 22 of [Suppes] p. 136. This is an alternative for Metamath 100 proof #74. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 9-Jul-2003.)
[∅ / 𝑥]𝜑    &   (𝑥 ∈ ω → (𝜑[suc 𝑥 / 𝑥]𝜑))       (𝑥 ∈ ω → 𝜑)
 
2.6.5  The Natural Numbers (continued)
 
Theoremnn0suc 4518* A natural number is either 0 or a successor. Similar theorems for arbitrary sets or real numbers will not be provable (without the law of the excluded middle), but equality of natural numbers is decidable. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1998.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐴 = ∅ ∨ ∃𝑥 ∈ ω 𝐴 = suc 𝑥))
 
Theoremelnn 4519 A member of a natural number is a natural number. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1998.)
((𝐴𝐵𝐵 ∈ ω) → 𝐴 ∈ ω)
 
Theoremordom 4520 Omega is ordinal. Theorem 7.32 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 43. (Contributed by NM, 18-Oct-1995.)
Ord ω
 
Theoremomelon2 4521 Omega is an ordinal number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Jan-2013.)
(ω ∈ V → ω ∈ On)
 
Theoremomelon 4522 Omega is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 10-May-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Jan-2013.)
ω ∈ On
 
Theoremnnon 4523 A natural number is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 27-Jun-1994.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → 𝐴 ∈ On)
 
Theoremnnoni 4524 A natural number is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 27-Jun-1994.)
𝐴 ∈ ω       𝐴 ∈ On
 
Theoremnnord 4525 A natural number is ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 17-Oct-1995.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → Ord 𝐴)
 
Theoremomsson 4526 Omega is a subset of On. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jun-1994.)
ω ⊆ On
 
Theoremlimom 4527 Omega is a limit ordinal. Theorem 2.8 of [BellMachover] p. 473. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-1995.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 5-Jan-2019.)
Lim ω
 
Theorempeano2b 4528 A class belongs to omega iff its successor does. (Contributed by NM, 3-Dec-1995.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω ↔ suc 𝐴 ∈ ω)
 
Theoremnnsuc 4529* A nonzero natural number is a successor. (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2004.)
((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑥 ∈ ω 𝐴 = suc 𝑥)
 
Theoremnnsucpred 4530 The successor of the precedessor of a nonzero natural number. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jul-2022.)
((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → suc 𝐴 = 𝐴)
 
Theoremnndceq0 4531 A natural number is either zero or nonzero. Decidable equality for natural numbers is a special case of the law of the excluded middle which holds in most constructive set theories including ours. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Jan-2019.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → DECID 𝐴 = ∅)
 
Theorem0elnn 4532 A natural number is either the empty set or has the empty set as an element. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Aug-2019.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐴 = ∅ ∨ ∅ ∈ 𝐴))
 
Theoremnn0eln0 4533 A natural number is nonempty iff it contains the empty set. Although in constructive mathematics it is generally more natural to work with inhabited sets and ignore the whole concept of nonempty sets, in the specific case of natural numbers this theorem may be helpful in converting proofs which were written assuming excluded middle. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Aug-2019.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → (∅ ∈ 𝐴𝐴 ≠ ∅))
 
Theoremnnregexmid 4534* If inhabited sets of natural numbers always have minimal elements, excluded middle follows. The argument is essentially the same as regexmid 4450 and the larger lesson is that although natural numbers may behave "non-constructively" even in a constructive set theory (for example see nndceq 6395 or nntri3or 6389), sets of natural numbers are a different animal. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 6-Sep-2019.)
((𝑥 ⊆ ω ∧ ∃𝑦 𝑦𝑥) → ∃𝑦(𝑦𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑧(𝑧𝑦 → ¬ 𝑧𝑥)))       (𝜑 ∨ ¬ 𝜑)
 
Theoremomsinds 4535* Strong (or "total") induction principle over ω. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 17-Jul-2015.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜒))    &   (𝑥 ∈ ω → (∀𝑦𝑥 𝜓𝜑))       (𝐴 ∈ ω → 𝜒)
 
Theoremnnpredcl 4536 The predecessor of a natural number is a natural number. This theorem is most interesting when the natural number is a successor (as seen in theorems like onsucuni2 4479) but also holds when it is by uni0 3763. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jul-2022.)
(𝐴 ∈ ω → 𝐴 ∈ ω)
 
2.6.6  Relations
 
Syntaxcxp 4537 Extend the definition of a class to include the cross product.
class (𝐴 × 𝐵)
 
Syntaxccnv 4538 Extend the definition of a class to include the converse of a class.
class 𝐴
 
Syntaxcdm 4539 Extend the definition of a class to include the domain of a class.
class dom 𝐴
 
Syntaxcrn 4540 Extend the definition of a class to include the range of a class.
class ran 𝐴
 
Syntaxcres 4541 Extend the definition of a class to include the restriction of a class. (Read: The restriction of 𝐴 to 𝐵.)
class (𝐴𝐵)
 
Syntaxcima 4542 Extend the definition of a class to include the image of a class. (Read: The image of 𝐵 under 𝐴.)
class (𝐴𝐵)
 
Syntaxccom 4543 Extend the definition of a class to include the composition of two classes. (Read: The composition of 𝐴 and 𝐵.)
class (𝐴𝐵)
 
Syntaxwrel 4544 Extend the definition of a wff to include the relation predicate. (Read: 𝐴 is a relation.)
wff Rel 𝐴
 
Definitiondf-xp 4545* Define the cross product of two classes. Definition 9.11 of [Quine] p. 64. For example, ( { 1 , 5 } × { 2 , 7 } ) = ( { 1 , 2 , 1 , 7 } { 5 , 2 , 5 , 7 } ) . Another example is that the set of rational numbers are defined in using the cross-product ( Z × N ) ; the left- and right-hand sides of the cross-product represent the top (integer) and bottom (natural) numbers of a fraction. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.)
(𝐴 × 𝐵) = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐵)}
 
Definitiondf-rel 4546 Define the relation predicate. Definition 6.4(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 23. For alternate definitions, see dfrel2 4989 and dfrel3 4996. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.)
(Rel 𝐴𝐴 ⊆ (V × V))
 
Definitiondf-cnv 4547* Define the converse of a class. Definition 9.12 of [Quine] p. 64. The converse of a binary relation swaps its arguments, i.e., if 𝐴 ∈ V and 𝐵 ∈ V then (𝐴𝑅𝐵𝐵𝑅𝐴), as proven in brcnv 4722 (see df-br 3930 and df-rel 4546 for more on relations). For example, { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } = { 6 , 2 , 9 , 3 } . We use Quine's breve accent (smile) notation. Like Quine, we use it as a prefix, which eliminates the need for parentheses. Many authors use the postfix superscript "to the minus one." "Converse" is Quine's terminology; some authors call it "inverse," especially when the argument is a function. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.)
𝐴 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ 𝑦𝐴𝑥}
 
Definitiondf-co 4548* Define the composition of two classes. Definition 6.6(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. Note that Definition 7 of [Suppes] p. 63 reverses 𝐴 and 𝐵, uses a slash instead of , and calls the operation "relative product." (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.)
(𝐴𝐵) = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ∃𝑧(𝑥𝐵𝑧𝑧𝐴𝑦)}
 
Definitiondf-dm 4549* Define the domain of a class. Definition 3 of [Suppes] p. 59. For example, F = { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } dom F = { 2 , 3 } . Contrast with range (defined in df-rn 4550). For alternate definitions see dfdm2 5073, dfdm3 4726, and dfdm4 4731. The notation "dom " is used by Enderton; other authors sometimes use script D. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.)
dom 𝐴 = {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦}
 
Definitiondf-rn 4550 Define the range of a class. For example, F = { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } -> ran F = { 6 , 9 } . Contrast with domain (defined in df-dm 4549). For alternate definitions, see dfrn2 4727, dfrn3 4728, and dfrn4 4999. The notation "ran " is used by Enderton; other authors sometimes use script R or script W. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.)
ran 𝐴 = dom 𝐴
 
Definitiondf-res 4551 Define the restriction of a class. Definition 6.6(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. For example ( F = { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } B = { 1 , 2 } ) -> ( F B ) = { 2 , 6 } . (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.)
(𝐴𝐵) = (𝐴 ∩ (𝐵 × V))
 
Definitiondf-ima 4552 Define the image of a class (as restricted by another class). Definition 6.6(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. For example, ( F = { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } /\ B = { 1 , 2 } ) -> ( F B ) = { 6 } . Contrast with restriction (df-res 4551) and range (df-rn 4550). For an alternate definition, see dfima2 4883. (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.)
(𝐴𝐵) = ran (𝐴𝐵)
 
Theoremxpeq1 4553 Equality theorem for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.)
(𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝐴 × 𝐶) = (𝐵 × 𝐶))
 
Theoremxpeq2 4554 Equality theorem for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jul-1994.)
(𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝐶 × 𝐴) = (𝐶 × 𝐵))
 
Theoremelxpi 4555* Membership in a cross product. Uses fewer axioms than elxp 4556. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.)
(𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) → ∃𝑥𝑦(𝐴 = ⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∧ (𝑥𝐵𝑦𝐶)))
 
Theoremelxp 4556* Membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.)
(𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) ↔ ∃𝑥𝑦(𝐴 = ⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∧ (𝑥𝐵𝑦𝐶)))
 
Theoremelxp2 4557* Membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 23-Feb-2004.)
(𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) ↔ ∃𝑥𝐵𝑦𝐶 𝐴 = ⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩)
 
Theoremxpeq12 4558 Equality theorem for cross product. (Contributed by FL, 31-Aug-2009.)
((𝐴 = 𝐵𝐶 = 𝐷) → (𝐴 × 𝐶) = (𝐵 × 𝐷))
 
Theoremxpeq1i 4559 Equality inference for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 21-Dec-2008.)
𝐴 = 𝐵       (𝐴 × 𝐶) = (𝐵 × 𝐶)
 
Theoremxpeq2i 4560 Equality inference for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 21-Dec-2008.)
𝐴 = 𝐵       (𝐶 × 𝐴) = (𝐶 × 𝐵)
 
Theoremxpeq12i 4561 Equality inference for cross product. (Contributed by FL, 31-Aug-2009.)
𝐴 = 𝐵    &   𝐶 = 𝐷       (𝐴 × 𝐶) = (𝐵 × 𝐷)
 
Theoremxpeq1d 4562 Equality deduction for cross product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 17-Jun-2010.)
(𝜑𝐴 = 𝐵)       (𝜑 → (𝐴 × 𝐶) = (𝐵 × 𝐶))
 
Theoremxpeq2d 4563 Equality deduction for cross product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 17-Jun-2010.)
(𝜑𝐴 = 𝐵)       (𝜑 → (𝐶 × 𝐴) = (𝐶 × 𝐵))
 
Theoremxpeq12d 4564 Equality deduction for Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2013.)
(𝜑𝐴 = 𝐵)    &   (𝜑𝐶 = 𝐷)       (𝜑 → (𝐴 × 𝐶) = (𝐵 × 𝐷))
 
Theoremsqxpeqd 4565 Equality deduction for a Cartesian square, see Wikipedia "Cartesian product", https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cartesian_product#n-ary_Cartesian_power. (Contributed by AV, 13-Jan-2020.)
(𝜑𝐴 = 𝐵)       (𝜑 → (𝐴 × 𝐴) = (𝐵 × 𝐵))
 
Theoremnfxp 4566 Bound-variable hypothesis builder for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.)
𝑥𝐴    &   𝑥𝐵       𝑥(𝐴 × 𝐵)
 
Theorem0nelxp 4567 The empty set is not a member of a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 2-May-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
¬ ∅ ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵)
 
Theorem0nelelxp 4568 A member of a cross product (ordered pair) doesn't contain the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 15-Dec-2008.)
(𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) → ¬ ∅ ∈ 𝐶)
 
Theoremopelxp 4569 Ordered pair membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
(⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (𝐶 × 𝐷) ↔ (𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷))
 
Theorembrxp 4570 Binary relation on a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-2004.)
(𝐴(𝐶 × 𝐷)𝐵 ↔ (𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷))
 
Theoremopelxpi 4571 Ordered pair membership in a cross product (implication). (Contributed by NM, 28-May-1995.)
((𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷) → ⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (𝐶 × 𝐷))
 
Theoremopelxpd 4572 Ordered pair membership in a Cartesian product, deduction form. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 3-Mar-2021.)
(𝜑𝐴𝐶)    &   (𝜑𝐵𝐷)       (𝜑 → ⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (𝐶 × 𝐷))
 
Theoremopelxp1 4573 The first member of an ordered pair of classes in a cross product belongs to first cross product argument. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
(⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (𝐶 × 𝐷) → 𝐴𝐶)
 
Theoremopelxp2 4574 The second member of an ordered pair of classes in a cross product belongs to second cross product argument. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
(⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (𝐶 × 𝐷) → 𝐵𝐷)
 
Theoremotelxp1 4575 The first member of an ordered triple of classes in a cross product belongs to first cross product argument. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-2008.)
(⟨⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩, 𝐶⟩ ∈ ((𝑅 × 𝑆) × 𝑇) → 𝐴𝑅)
 
Theoremrabxp 4576* Membership in a class builder restricted to a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 20-Feb-2014.)
(𝑥 = ⟨𝑦, 𝑧⟩ → (𝜑𝜓))       {𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∣ 𝜑} = {⟨𝑦, 𝑧⟩ ∣ (𝑦𝐴𝑧𝐵𝜓)}
 
Theorembrrelex12 4577 A true binary relation on a relation implies the arguments are sets. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
((Rel 𝑅𝐴𝑅𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝐵 ∈ V))
 
Theorembrrelex1 4578 A true binary relation on a relation implies the first argument is a set. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by NM, 18-May-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
((Rel 𝑅𝐴𝑅𝐵) → 𝐴 ∈ V)
 
Theorembrrelex 4579 A true binary relation on a relation implies the first argument is a set. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by NM, 18-May-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
((Rel 𝑅𝐴𝑅𝐵) → 𝐴 ∈ V)
 
Theorembrrelex2 4580 A true binary relation on a relation implies the second argument is a set. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
((Rel 𝑅𝐴𝑅𝐵) → 𝐵 ∈ V)
 
Theorembrrelex12i 4581 Two classes that are related by a binary relation are sets. (An artifact of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by BJ, 3-Oct-2022.)
Rel 𝑅       (𝐴𝑅𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝐵 ∈ V))
 
Theorembrrelex1i 4582 The first argument of a binary relation exists. (An artifact of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by NM, 4-Jun-1998.)
Rel 𝑅       (𝐴𝑅𝐵𝐴 ∈ V)
 
Theorembrrelex2i 4583 The second argument of a binary relation exists. (An artifact of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
Rel 𝑅       (𝐴𝑅𝐵𝐵 ∈ V)
 
Theoremnprrel 4584 No proper class is related to anything via any relation. (Contributed by Roy F. Longton, 30-Jul-2005.)
Rel 𝑅    &    ¬ 𝐴 ∈ V        ¬ 𝐴𝑅𝐵
 
Theorem0nelrel 4585 A binary relation does not contain the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 15-Nov-2021.)
(Rel 𝑅 → ∅ ∉ 𝑅)
 
Theoremfconstmpt 4586* Representation of a constant function using the mapping operation. (Note that 𝑥 cannot appear free in 𝐵.) (Contributed by NM, 12-Oct-1999.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2013.)
(𝐴 × {𝐵}) = (𝑥𝐴𝐵)
 
Theoremvtoclr 4587* Variable to class conversion of transitive relation. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
Rel 𝑅    &   ((𝑥𝑅𝑦𝑦𝑅𝑧) → 𝑥𝑅𝑧)       ((𝐴𝑅𝐵𝐵𝑅𝐶) → 𝐴𝑅𝐶)
 
Theoremopelvvg 4588 Ordered pair membership in the universal class of ordered pairs. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.)
((𝐴𝑉𝐵𝑊) → ⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (V × V))
 
Theoremopelvv 4589 Ordered pair membership in the universal class of ordered pairs. (Contributed by NM, 22-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   𝐵 ∈ V       𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (V × V)
 
Theoremopthprc 4590 Justification theorem for an ordered pair definition that works for any classes, including proper classes. This is a possible definition implied by the footnote in [Jech] p. 78, which says, "The sophisticated reader will not object to our use of a pair of classes." (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2003.)
(((𝐴 × {∅}) ∪ (𝐵 × {{∅}})) = ((𝐶 × {∅}) ∪ (𝐷 × {{∅}})) ↔ (𝐴 = 𝐶𝐵 = 𝐷))
 
Theorembrel 4591 Two things in a binary relation belong to the relation's domain. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
𝑅 ⊆ (𝐶 × 𝐷)       (𝐴𝑅𝐵 → (𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷))
 
Theorembrab2a 4592* Ordered pair membership in an ordered pair class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Nov-2015.)
((𝑥 = 𝐴𝑦 = 𝐵) → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝑅 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥𝐶𝑦𝐷) ∧ 𝜑)}       (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ↔ ((𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷) ∧ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelxp3 4593* Membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 5-Mar-1995.)
(𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) ↔ ∃𝑥𝑦(⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ = 𝐴 ∧ ⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶)))
 
Theoremopeliunxp 4594 Membership in a union of cross products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Jan-2017.)
(⟨𝑥, 𝐶⟩ ∈ 𝑥𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵) ↔ (𝑥𝐴𝐶𝐵))
 
Theoremxpundi 4595 Distributive law for cross product over union. Theorem 103 of [Suppes] p. 52. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-2004.)
(𝐴 × (𝐵𝐶)) = ((𝐴 × 𝐵) ∪ (𝐴 × 𝐶))
 
Theoremxpundir 4596 Distributive law for cross product over union. Similar to Theorem 103 of [Suppes] p. 52. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2002.)
((𝐴𝐵) × 𝐶) = ((𝐴 × 𝐶) ∪ (𝐵 × 𝐶))
 
Theoremxpiundi 4597* Distributive law for cross product over indexed union. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Apr-2014.)
(𝐶 × 𝑥𝐴 𝐵) = 𝑥𝐴 (𝐶 × 𝐵)
 
Theoremxpiundir 4598* Distributive law for cross product over indexed union. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Apr-2014.)
( 𝑥𝐴 𝐵 × 𝐶) = 𝑥𝐴 (𝐵 × 𝐶)
 
Theoremiunxpconst 4599* Membership in a union of cross products when the second factor is constant. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Dec-2014.)
𝑥𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵) = (𝐴 × 𝐵)
 
Theoremxpun 4600 The cross product of two unions. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-2004.)
((𝐴𝐵) × (𝐶𝐷)) = (((𝐴 × 𝐶) ∪ (𝐴 × 𝐷)) ∪ ((𝐵 × 𝐶) ∪ (𝐵 × 𝐷)))
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13250
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >