Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 6101-6200 *Has distinct variable
group(s)
Type | Label | Description |
Statement |
|
Theorem | df2o2 6101 |
Expanded value of the ordinal number 2. (Contributed by NM,
29-Jan-2004.)
|
⊢ 2𝑜 = {∅,
{∅}} |
|
Theorem | 1n0 6102 |
Ordinal one is not equal to ordinal zero. (Contributed by NM,
26-Dec-2004.)
|
⊢ 1𝑜 ≠
∅ |
|
Theorem | xp01disj 6103 |
Cartesian products with the singletons of ordinals 0 and 1 are disjoint.
(Contributed by NM, 2-Jun-2007.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 × {∅}) ∩ (𝐶 ×
{1𝑜})) = ∅ |
|
Theorem | ordgt0ge1 6104 |
Two ways to express that an ordinal class is positive. (Contributed by
NM, 21-Dec-2004.)
|
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → (∅ ∈ 𝐴 ↔ 1𝑜 ⊆ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | ordge1n0im 6105 |
An ordinal greater than or equal to 1 is nonzero. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 26-Jun-2019.)
|
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → (1𝑜 ⊆
𝐴 → 𝐴 ≠ ∅)) |
|
Theorem | el1o 6106 |
Membership in ordinal one. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-2005.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 1𝑜 ↔ 𝐴 = ∅) |
|
Theorem | dif1o 6107 |
Two ways to say that 𝐴 is a nonzero number of the set 𝐵.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 21-May-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ∖ 1𝑜) ↔
(𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅)) |
|
Theorem | 2oconcl 6108 |
Closure of the pair swapping function on 2𝑜. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 27-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 2𝑜 →
(1𝑜 ∖ 𝐴) ∈
2𝑜) |
|
Theorem | 0lt1o 6109 |
Ordinal zero is less than ordinal one. (Contributed by NM,
5-Jan-2005.)
|
⊢ ∅ ∈
1𝑜 |
|
Theorem | oafnex 6110 |
The characteristic function for ordinal addition is defined everywhere.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ suc 𝑥) Fn V |
|
Theorem | sucinc 6111* |
Successor is increasing. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑧 ∈ V ↦ suc 𝑧) ⇒ ⊢ ∀𝑥 𝑥 ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥) |
|
Theorem | sucinc2 6112* |
Successor is increasing. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑧 ∈ V ↦ suc 𝑧) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ On ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝐹‘𝐴) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | fnoa 6113 |
Functionality and domain of ordinal addition. (Contributed by NM,
26-Aug-1995.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ +𝑜 Fn (On ×
On) |
|
Theorem | oaexg 6114 |
Ordinal addition is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | omfnex 6115* |
The characteristic function for ordinal multiplication is defined
everywhere. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑥 +𝑜 𝐴)) Fn V) |
|
Theorem | fnom 6116 |
Functionality and domain of ordinal multiplication. (Contributed by NM,
26-Aug-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ·𝑜 Fn (On ×
On) |
|
Theorem | omexg 6117 |
Ordinal multiplication is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | fnoei 6118 |
Functionality and domain of ordinal exponentiation. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 29-May-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ↑𝑜 Fn (On ×
On) |
|
Theorem | oeiexg 6119 |
Ordinal exponentiation is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ↑𝑜 𝐵) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | oav 6120* |
Value of ordinal addition. (Contributed by NM, 3-May-1995.) (Revised
by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) = (rec((𝑥 ∈ V ↦ suc 𝑥), 𝐴)‘𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | omv 6121* |
Value of ordinal multiplication. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1995.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 23-Aug-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) = (rec((𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑥 +𝑜 𝐴)), ∅)‘𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | oeiv 6122* |
Value of ordinal exponentiation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
9-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ↑𝑜 𝐵) = (rec((𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑥 ·𝑜 𝐴)),
1𝑜)‘𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | oa0 6123 |
Addition with zero. Proposition 8.3 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 57.
(Contributed by NM, 3-May-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝐴 +𝑜 ∅) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | om0 6124 |
Ordinal multiplication with zero. Definition 8.15 of [TakeutiZaring]
p. 62. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝐴 ·𝑜 ∅) =
∅) |
|
Theorem | oei0 6125 |
Ordinal exponentiation with zero exponent. Definition 8.30 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 67.
(Contributed by NM, 31-Dec-2004.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝐴 ↑𝑜 ∅) =
1𝑜) |
|
Theorem | oacl 6126 |
Closure law for ordinal addition. Proposition 8.2 of [TakeutiZaring]
p. 57. (Contributed by NM, 5-May-1995.) (Constructive proof by Jim
Kingdon, 26-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) ∈ On) |
|
Theorem | omcl 6127 |
Closure law for ordinal multiplication. Proposition 8.16 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 57.
(Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-2004.) (Constructive
proof by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) ∈ On) |
|
Theorem | oeicl 6128 |
Closure law for ordinal exponentiation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
26-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ↑𝑜 𝐵) ∈ On) |
|
Theorem | oav2 6129* |
Value of ordinal addition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim
Kingdon, 12-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) = (𝐴 ∪ ∪
𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 suc (𝐴 +𝑜 𝑥))) |
|
Theorem | oasuc 6130 |
Addition with successor. Definition 8.1 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 56.
(Contributed by NM, 3-May-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 +𝑜 suc 𝐵) = suc (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | omv2 6131* |
Value of ordinal multiplication. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
23-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) = ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝑥) +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | onasuc 6132 |
Addition with successor. Theorem 4I(A2) of [Enderton] p. 79.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 +𝑜 suc 𝐵) = suc (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | oa1suc 6133 |
Addition with 1 is same as successor. Proposition 4.34(a) of [Mendelson]
p. 266. (Contributed by NM, 29-Oct-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
16-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝐴 +𝑜
1𝑜) = suc 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | o1p1e2 6134 |
1 + 1 = 2 for ordinal numbers. (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2004.)
|
⊢ (1𝑜 +𝑜
1𝑜) = 2𝑜 |
|
Theorem | oawordi 6135 |
Weak ordering property of ordinal addition. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 27-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On ∧ 𝐶 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐴) ⊆ (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | oawordriexmid 6136* |
A weak ordering property of ordinal addition which implies excluded
middle. The property is proposition 8.7 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 59.
Compare with oawordi 6135. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-May-2022.)
|
⊢ ((𝑎 ∈ On ∧ 𝑏 ∈ On ∧ 𝑐 ∈ On) → (𝑎 ⊆ 𝑏 → (𝑎 +𝑜 𝑐) ⊆ (𝑏 +𝑜 𝑐))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ∨ ¬ 𝜑) |
|
Theorem | oaword1 6137 |
An ordinal is less than or equal to its sum with another. Part of
Exercise 5 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 62.
(Contributed by NM, 6-Dec-2004.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → 𝐴 ⊆ (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | omsuc 6138 |
Multiplication with successor. Definition 8.15 of [TakeutiZaring]
p. 62. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 suc 𝐵) = ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | onmsuc 6139 |
Multiplication with successor. Theorem 4J(A2) of [Enderton] p. 80.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
14-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 suc 𝐵) = ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
2.6.23 Natural number arithmetic
|
|
Theorem | nna0 6140 |
Addition with zero. Theorem 4I(A1) of [Enderton] p. 79. (Contributed by
NM, 20-Sep-1995.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐴 +𝑜 ∅) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | nnm0 6141 |
Multiplication with zero. Theorem 4J(A1) of [Enderton] p. 80.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐴 ·𝑜 ∅) =
∅) |
|
Theorem | nnasuc 6142 |
Addition with successor. Theorem 4I(A2) of [Enderton] p. 79.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
14-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 +𝑜 suc 𝐵) = suc (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nnmsuc 6143 |
Multiplication with successor. Theorem 4J(A2) of [Enderton] p. 80.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
14-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 suc 𝐵) = ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nna0r 6144 |
Addition to zero. Remark in proof of Theorem 4K(2) of [Enderton] p. 81.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
14-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (∅
+𝑜 𝐴) =
𝐴) |
|
Theorem | nnm0r 6145 |
Multiplication with zero. Exercise 16 of [Enderton] p. 82.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (∅
·𝑜 𝐴) = ∅) |
|
Theorem | nnacl 6146 |
Closure of addition of natural numbers. Proposition 8.9 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 59.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Proof
shortened by Andrew Salmon, 22-Oct-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) ∈ ω) |
|
Theorem | nnmcl 6147 |
Closure of multiplication of natural numbers. Proposition 8.17 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 63.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Proof
shortened by Andrew Salmon, 22-Oct-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) ∈
ω) |
|
Theorem | nnacli 6148 |
ω is closed under addition. Inference form of nnacl 6146.
(Contributed by Scott Fenton, 20-Apr-2012.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ ω & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
ω ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) ∈ ω |
|
Theorem | nnmcli 6149 |
ω is closed under multiplication. Inference form
of nnmcl 6147.
(Contributed by Scott Fenton, 20-Apr-2012.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ ω & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
ω ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) ∈
ω |
|
Theorem | nnacom 6150 |
Addition of natural numbers is commutative. Theorem 4K(2) of [Enderton]
p. 81. (Contributed by NM, 6-May-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) = (𝐵 +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nnaass 6151 |
Addition of natural numbers is associative. Theorem 4K(1) of [Enderton]
p. 81. (Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → ((𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) +𝑜 𝐶) = (𝐴 +𝑜 (𝐵 +𝑜 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | nndi 6152 |
Distributive law for natural numbers (left-distributivity). Theorem
4K(3) of [Enderton] p. 81.
(Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-1995.) (Revised
by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 (𝐵 +𝑜 𝐶)) = ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) +𝑜 (𝐴 ·𝑜
𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | nnmass 6153 |
Multiplication of natural numbers is associative. Theorem 4K(4) of
[Enderton] p. 81. (Contributed by NM,
20-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario
Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) ·𝑜
𝐶) = (𝐴 ·𝑜 (𝐵 ·𝑜
𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | nnmsucr 6154 |
Multiplication with successor. Exercise 16 of [Enderton] p. 82.
(Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-1995.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon,
22-Oct-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (suc 𝐴 ·𝑜
𝐵) = ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) +𝑜 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nnmcom 6155 |
Multiplication of natural numbers is commutative. Theorem 4K(5) of
[Enderton] p. 81. (Contributed by NM,
21-Sep-1995.) (Proof shortened
by Andrew Salmon, 22-Oct-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) = (𝐵 ·𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nndir 6156 |
Distributive law for natural numbers (right-distributivity). (Contributed
by Jim Kingdon, 3-Dec-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → ((𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) ·𝑜 𝐶) = ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐶) +𝑜 (𝐵 ·𝑜
𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | nnsucelsuc 6157 |
Membership is inherited by successors. The reverse direction holds for
all ordinals, as seen at onsucelsucr 4281, but the forward direction, for
all ordinals, implies excluded middle as seen as onsucelsucexmid 4302.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ ω → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ suc 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nnsucsssuc 6158 |
Membership is inherited by successors. The reverse direction holds for
all ordinals, as seen at onsucsssucr 4282, but the forward direction, for
all ordinals, implies excluded middle as seen as onsucsssucexmid 4299.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ suc 𝐴 ⊆ suc 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nntri3or 6159 |
Trichotomy for natural numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
25-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nntri2 6160 |
A trichotomy law for natural numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
28-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ ¬ (𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | nnsucuniel 6161 |
Given an element 𝐴 of the union of a natural number
𝐵,
suc 𝐴 is an element of 𝐵 itself.
The reverse direction holds
for all ordinals (sucunielr 4283). The forward direction for all
ordinals implies excluded middle (ordsucunielexmid 4303). (Contributed
by Jim Kingdon, 13-Mar-2022.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ ω → (𝐴 ∈ ∪ 𝐵 ↔ suc 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nntri1 6162 |
A trichotomy law for natural numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
28-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ ¬ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nntri3 6163 |
A trichotomy law for natural numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
15-May-2020.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 = 𝐵 ↔ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ¬ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | nntri2or2 6164 |
A trichotomy law for natural numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
15-Sep-2021.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nndceq 6165 |
Equality of natural numbers is decidable. Theorem 7.2.6 of [HoTT], p.
(varies). For the specific case where 𝐵 is zero, see nndceq0 4386.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) →
DECID 𝐴 =
𝐵) |
|
Theorem | nndcel 6166 |
Set membership between two natural numbers is decidable. (Contributed by
Jim Kingdon, 6-Sep-2019.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) →
DECID 𝐴
∈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | nnsseleq 6167 |
For natural numbers, inclusion is equivalent to membership or equality.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Sep-2021.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | dcdifsnid 6168* |
If we remove a single element from a set with decidable equality then
put it back in, we end up with the original set. This strengthens
difsnss 3552 from subset to equality but the proof relies
on equality being
decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Jun-2022.)
|
⊢ ((∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 DECID 𝑥 = 𝑦 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ((𝐴 ∖ {𝐵}) ∪ {𝐵}) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | nndifsnid 6169 |
If we remove a single element from a natural number then put it back in,
we end up with the original natural number. This strengthens difsnss 3552
from subset to equality but the proof relies on equality being
decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Aug-2021.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ((𝐴 ∖ {𝐵}) ∪ {𝐵}) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | nnaordi 6170 |
Ordering property of addition. Proposition 8.4 of [TakeutiZaring]
p. 58, limited to natural numbers. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-1996.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐴) ∈ (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | nnaord 6171 |
Ordering property of addition. Proposition 8.4 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 58,
limited to natural numbers, and its converse. (Contributed by NM,
7-Mar-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐴) ∈ (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | nnaordr 6172 |
Ordering property of addition of natural numbers. (Contributed by NM,
9-Nov-2002.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐶) ∈ (𝐵 +𝑜 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | nnaword 6173 |
Weak ordering property of addition. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1995.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐴) ⊆ (𝐶 +𝑜 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | nnacan 6174 |
Cancellation law for addition of natural numbers. (Contributed by NM,
27-Oct-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → ((𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵) = (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐶) ↔ 𝐵 = 𝐶)) |
|
Theorem | nnaword1 6175 |
Weak ordering property of addition. (Contributed by NM, 9-Nov-2002.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → 𝐴 ⊆ (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nnaword2 6176 |
Weak ordering property of addition. (Contributed by NM, 9-Nov-2002.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → 𝐴 ⊆ (𝐵 +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nnawordi 6177 |
Adding to both sides of an inequality in ω
(Contributed by Scott
Fenton, 16-Apr-2012.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-May-2012.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐶) ⊆ (𝐵 +𝑜 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | nnmordi 6178 |
Ordering property of multiplication. Half of Proposition 8.19 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 63, limited to
natural numbers. (Contributed by NM,
18-Sep-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (((𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) ∧ ∅ ∈ 𝐶) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐶 ·𝑜 𝐴) ∈ (𝐶 ·𝑜 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | nnmord 6179 |
Ordering property of multiplication. Proposition 8.19 of [TakeutiZaring]
p. 63, limited to natural numbers. (Contributed by NM, 22-Jan-1996.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) → ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ∅ ∈ 𝐶) ↔ (𝐶 ·𝑜 𝐴) ∈ (𝐶 ·𝑜 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | nnmword 6180 |
Weak ordering property of ordinal multiplication. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 17-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) ∧ ∅ ∈ 𝐶) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐶 ·𝑜 𝐴) ⊆ (𝐶 ·𝑜 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | nnmcan 6181 |
Cancellation law for multiplication of natural numbers. (Contributed by
NM, 26-Oct-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ω) ∧ ∅ ∈ 𝐴) → ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) = (𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐶) ↔ 𝐵 = 𝐶)) |
|
Theorem | 1onn 6182 |
One is a natural number. (Contributed by NM, 29-Oct-1995.)
|
⊢ 1𝑜 ∈
ω |
|
Theorem | 2onn 6183 |
The ordinal 2 is a natural number. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 2𝑜 ∈
ω |
|
Theorem | 3onn 6184 |
The ordinal 3 is a natural number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
5-Jan-2016.)
|
⊢ 3𝑜 ∈
ω |
|
Theorem | 4onn 6185 |
The ordinal 4 is a natural number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
5-Jan-2016.)
|
⊢ 4𝑜 ∈
ω |
|
Theorem | nnm1 6186 |
Multiply an element of ω by 1𝑜. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 17-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐴 ·𝑜
1𝑜) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | nnm2 6187 |
Multiply an element of ω by 2𝑜 (Contributed by Scott Fenton,
18-Apr-2012.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐴 ·𝑜
2𝑜) = (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nn2m 6188 |
Multiply an element of ω by 2𝑜 (Contributed by Scott Fenton,
16-Apr-2012.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω →
(2𝑜 ·𝑜 𝐴) = (𝐴 +𝑜 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | nnaordex 6189* |
Equivalence for ordering. Compare Exercise 23 of [Enderton] p. 88.
(Contributed by NM, 5-Dec-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ ω (∅ ∈ 𝑥 ∧ (𝐴 +𝑜 𝑥) = 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | nnawordex 6190* |
Equivalence for weak ordering of natural numbers. (Contributed by NM,
8-Nov-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐴 +𝑜 𝑥) = 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nnm00 6191 |
The product of two natural numbers is zero iff at least one of them is
zero. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Nov-2004.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → ((𝐴 ·𝑜 𝐵) = ∅ ↔ (𝐴 = ∅ ∨ 𝐵 = ∅))) |
|
2.6.24 Equivalence relations and
classes
|
|
Syntax | wer 6192 |
Extend the definition of a wff to include the equivalence predicate.
|
wff 𝑅 Er 𝐴 |
|
Syntax | cec 6193 |
Extend the definition of a class to include equivalence class.
|
class [𝐴]𝑅 |
|
Syntax | cqs 6194 |
Extend the definition of a class to include quotient set.
|
class (𝐴 / 𝑅) |
|
Definition | df-er 6195 |
Define the equivalence relation predicate. Our notation is not standard.
A formal notation doesn't seem to exist in the literature; instead only
informal English tends to be used. The present definition, although
somewhat cryptic, nicely avoids dummy variables. In dfer2 6196 we derive a
more typical definition. We show that an equivalence relation is
reflexive, symmetric, and transitive in erref 6215, ersymb 6209, and ertr 6210.
(Contributed by NM, 4-Jun-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
2-Nov-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝑅 Er 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝑅 ∧ dom 𝑅 = 𝐴 ∧ (◡𝑅 ∪ (𝑅 ∘ 𝑅)) ⊆ 𝑅)) |
|
Theorem | dfer2 6196* |
Alternate definition of equivalence predicate. (Contributed by NM,
3-Jan-1997.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝑅 Er 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝑅 ∧ dom 𝑅 = 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧((𝑥𝑅𝑦 → 𝑦𝑅𝑥) ∧ ((𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∧ 𝑦𝑅𝑧) → 𝑥𝑅𝑧)))) |
|
Definition | df-ec 6197 |
Define the 𝑅-coset of 𝐴. Exercise 35 of [Enderton] p. 61. This
is called the equivalence class of 𝐴 modulo 𝑅 when 𝑅 is an
equivalence relation (i.e. when Er 𝑅; see dfer2 6196). In this case,
𝐴 is a representative (member) of the
equivalence class [𝐴]𝑅,
which contains all sets that are equivalent to 𝐴. Definition of
[Enderton] p. 57 uses the notation [𝐴]
(subscript) 𝑅, although
we simply follow the brackets by 𝑅 since we don't have subscripted
expressions. For an alternate definition, see dfec2 6198. (Contributed by
NM, 23-Jul-1995.)
|
⊢ [𝐴]𝑅 = (𝑅 “ {𝐴}) |
|
Theorem | dfec2 6198* |
Alternate definition of 𝑅-coset of 𝐴. Definition 34 of
[Suppes] p. 81. (Contributed by NM,
3-Jan-1997.) (Proof shortened by
Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → [𝐴]𝑅 = {𝑦 ∣ 𝐴𝑅𝑦}) |
|
Theorem | ecexg 6199 |
An equivalence class modulo a set is a set. (Contributed by NM,
24-Jul-1995.)
|
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ 𝐵 → [𝐴]𝑅 ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | ecexr 6200 |
An inhabited equivalence class implies the representative is a set.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ [𝐵]𝑅 → 𝐵 ∈ V) |