Users' Mathboxes Mathbox for Alan Sare < Previous   Next >
Nearby theorems
Mirrors  >  Home  >  MPE Home  >  Th. List  >   Mathboxes  >  sucidALTVD Structured version   Visualization version   GIF version

Theorem sucidALTVD 41211
Description: A set belongs to its successor. Alternate proof of sucid 6272. The following User's Proof is a Virtual Deduction proof completed automatically by the tools program completeusersproof.cmd, which invokes Mel L. O'Cat's mmj2 and Norm Megill's Metamath Proof Assistant. sucidALT 41212 is sucidALTVD 41211 without virtual deductions and was automatically derived from sucidALTVD 41211. This proof illustrates that completeusersproof.cmd will generate a Metamath proof from any User's Proof which is "conventional" in the sense that no step is a virtual deduction, provided that all necessary unification theorems and transformation deductions are in set.mm. completeusersproof.cmd automatically converts such a conventional proof into a Virtual Deduction proof for which each step happens to be a 0-virtual hypothesis virtual deduction. The user does not need to search for reference theorem labels or deduction labels nor does he(she) need to use theorems and deductions which unify with reference theorems and deductions in set.mm. All that is necessary is that each theorem or deduction of the User's Proof unifies with some reference theorem or deduction in set.mm or is a semantic variation of some theorem or deduction which unifies with some reference theorem or deduction in set.mm. The definition of "semantic variation" has not been precisely defined. If it is obvious that a theorem or deduction has the same meaning as another theorem or deduction, then it is a semantic variation of the latter theorem or deduction. For example, step 4 of the User's Proof is a semantic variation of the definition (axiom) suc 𝐴 = (𝐴 ∪ {𝐴}), which unifies with df-suc 6199, a reference definition (axiom) in set.mm. Also, a theorem or deduction is said to be a semantic variation of another theorem or deduction if it is obvious upon cursory inspection that it has the same meaning as a weaker form of the latter theorem or deduction. For example, the deduction Ord 𝐴 infers 𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐴(𝑥𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦𝑥) is a semantic variation of the theorem (Ord 𝐴 ↔ (Tr 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴 𝑦𝐴(𝑥𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦𝑦𝑥))), which unifies with the set.mm reference definition (axiom) dford2 9085.
h1:: 𝐴 ∈ V
2:1: 𝐴 ∈ {𝐴}
3:2: 𝐴 ∈ ({𝐴} ∪ 𝐴)
4:: suc 𝐴 = ({𝐴} ∪ 𝐴)
qed:3,4: 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐴
(Contributed by Alan Sare, 18-Feb-2012.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
Hypothesis
Ref Expression
sucidALTVD.1 𝐴 ∈ V
Assertion
Ref Expression
sucidALTVD 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐴

Proof of Theorem sucidALTVD
StepHypRef Expression
1 sucidALTVD.1 . . . 4 𝐴 ∈ V
21snid 4603 . . 3 𝐴 ∈ {𝐴}
3 elun1 4154 . . 3 (𝐴 ∈ {𝐴} → 𝐴 ∈ ({𝐴} ∪ 𝐴))
42, 3e0a 41113 . 2 𝐴 ∈ ({𝐴} ∪ 𝐴)
5 df-suc 6199 . . 3 suc 𝐴 = (𝐴 ∪ {𝐴})
65equncomi 4133 . 2 suc 𝐴 = ({𝐴} ∪ 𝐴)
74, 6eleqtrri 2914 1 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐴
Colors of variables: wff setvar class
Syntax hints:  wcel 2114  Vcvv 3496  cun 3936  {csn 4569  suc csuc 6195
This theorem was proved from axioms:  ax-mp 5  ax-1 6  ax-2 7  ax-3 8  ax-gen 1796  ax-4 1810  ax-5 1911  ax-6 1970  ax-7 2015  ax-8 2116  ax-9 2124  ax-10 2145  ax-11 2161  ax-12 2177  ax-ext 2795
This theorem depends on definitions:  df-bi 209  df-an 399  df-or 844  df-tru 1540  df-ex 1781  df-nf 1785  df-sb 2070  df-clab 2802  df-cleq 2816  df-clel 2895  df-nfc 2965  df-v 3498  df-un 3943  df-in 3945  df-ss 3954  df-sn 4570  df-suc 6199
This theorem is referenced by: (None)
  Copyright terms: Public domain W3C validator