Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 444 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29181) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29182-30704) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30705-46395) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | aistbisfiaxb 44301 | Given a is equivalent to T., Given b is equivalent to F. there exists a proof for a-xor-b. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 31-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | aisfbistiaxb 44302 | Given a is equivalent to F., Given b is equivalent to T., there exists a proof for a-xor-b. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 31-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | aifftbifffaibif 44303 | Given a is equivalent to T., Given b is equivalent to F., there exists a proof for that a implies b is false. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | aifftbifffaibifff 44304 | Given a is equivalent to T., Given b is equivalent to F., there exists a proof for that a iff b is false. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | atnaiana 44305 | Given a, it is not the case a implies a self contradiction. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ¬ (𝜑 → (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | ainaiaandna 44306 | Given a, a implies it is not the case a implies a self contradiction. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ (𝜑 → (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | abcdta 44307 | Given (((a and b) and c) and d), there exists a proof for a. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 3-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | abcdtb 44308 | Given (((a and b) and c) and d), there exists a proof for b. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 3-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | abcdtc 44309 | Given (((a and b) and c) and d), there exists a proof for c. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 3-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜒 | ||
Theorem | abcdtd 44310 | Given (((a and b) and c) and d), there exists a proof for d. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 3-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜃 | ||
Theorem | abciffcbatnabciffncba 44311 | Operands in a biconditional expression converted negated. Additionally biconditional converted to show antecedent implies sequent. Closed form. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (¬ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) → ¬ ((𝜒 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | abciffcbatnabciffncbai 44312 | Operands in a biconditional expression converted negated. Additionally biconditional converted to show antecedent implies sequent. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜒 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜑)) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) → ¬ ((𝜒 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | nabctnabc 44313 | not ( a -> ( b /\ c ) ) we can show: not a implies ( b /\ c ). (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ¬ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | jabtaib 44314 | For when pm3.4 lacks a pm3.4i. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 9-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | onenotinotbothi 44315 | From one negated implication it is not the case its nonnegated form and a random others are both true. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 11-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ¬ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ¬ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ∧ (𝜒 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | twonotinotbothi 44316 | From these two negated implications it is not the case their nonnegated forms are both true. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 11-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ¬ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ ¬ (𝜒 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ¬ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ∧ (𝜒 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | clifte 44317 | show d is the same as an if-else involving a,b. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 20-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜒) & ⊢ 𝜃 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | cliftet 44318 | show d is the same as an if-else involving a,b. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 20-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) & ⊢ 𝜃 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | clifteta 44319 | show d is the same as an if-else involving a,b. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 20-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) & ⊢ 𝜃 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | cliftetb 44320 | show d is the same as an if-else involving a,b. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 20-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜒)) & ⊢ 𝜃 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | confun 44321 | Given the hypotheses there exists a proof for (c implies ( d iff a ) ). (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | confun2 44322 | Confun simplified to two propositions. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ¬ (𝜓 → (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜓))) & ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝜑) → ((𝜓 → 𝜑) → 𝜑)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (¬ (𝜓 → (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜓)) ↔ (𝜓 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | confun3 44323 | Confun's more complex form where both a,d have been "defined". (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ¬ (𝜒 → (𝜒 ∧ ¬ 𝜒))) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → ¬ (𝜒 → (𝜒 ∧ ¬ 𝜒))) & ⊢ ((𝜒 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → 𝜓) → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (¬ (𝜒 → (𝜒 ∧ ¬ 𝜒)) ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | confun4 44324 | An attempt at derivative. Resisted simplest path to a proof. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ ((𝜒 → 𝜃) → ((𝜑 → 𝜃) ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ¬ (𝜒 → (𝜒 ∧ ¬ 𝜒))) & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | confun5 44325 | An attempt at derivative. Resisted simplest path to a proof. Interesting that ch, th, ta, et were all provable. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ ((𝜒 → 𝜃) → ((𝜑 → 𝜃) ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ¬ (𝜒 → (𝜒 ∧ ¬ 𝜒))) & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | plcofph 44326 | Given, a,b and a "definition" for c, c is demonstrated. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 8-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ((((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ 𝜑) → (𝜑 ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑))) ∧ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)))) & ⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜒 | ||
Theorem | pldofph 44327 | Given, a,b c, d, "definition" for e, e is demonstrated. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 8-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ((𝜒 → 𝜃) ∧ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) ∧ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)))) & ⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ 𝜃 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜏 | ||
Theorem | plvcofph 44328 | Given, a,b,d, and "definitions" for c, e, f: f is demonstrated. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 8-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ((((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ 𝜑) → (𝜑 ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑))) ∧ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)))) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ((𝜒 → 𝜃) ∧ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) ∧ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)))) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜏)) & ⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ 𝜃 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜂 | ||
Theorem | plvcofphax 44329 | Given, a,b,d, and "definitions" for c, e, f, g: g is demonstrated. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 8-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ((((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ 𝜑) → (𝜑 ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑))) ∧ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)))) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ((𝜒 → 𝜃) ∧ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) ∧ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)))) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜏)) & ⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ 𝜃 & ⊢ (𝜁 ↔ ¬ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜁 | ||
Theorem | plvofpos 44330 | rh is derivable because ONLY one of ch, th, ta, et is implied by mu. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 11-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜒 ↔ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜁 ↔ (((((¬ ((𝜇 → 𝜒) ∧ (𝜇 → 𝜃)) ∧ ¬ ((𝜇 → 𝜒) ∧ (𝜇 → 𝜏))) ∧ ¬ ((𝜇 → 𝜒) ∧ (𝜒 → 𝜂))) ∧ ¬ ((𝜇 → 𝜃) ∧ (𝜇 → 𝜏))) ∧ ¬ ((𝜇 → 𝜃) ∧ (𝜇 → 𝜂))) ∧ ¬ ((𝜇 → 𝜏) ∧ (𝜇 → 𝜂)))) & ⊢ (𝜎 ↔ (((𝜇 → 𝜒) ∨ (𝜇 → 𝜃)) ∨ ((𝜇 → 𝜏) ∨ (𝜇 → 𝜂)))) & ⊢ (𝜌 ↔ (𝜁 ∧ 𝜎)) & ⊢ 𝜁 & ⊢ 𝜎 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜌 | ||
Theorem | mdandyv0 44331 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv1 44332 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv2 44333 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv3 44334 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv4 44335 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv5 44336 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv6 44337 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv7 44338 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv8 44339 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv9 44340 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv10 44341 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv11 44342 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv12 44343 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv13 44344 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv14 44345 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyv15 44346 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ph, ps accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr0 44347 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr1 44348 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr2 44349 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr3 44350 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr4 44351 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr5 44352 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr6 44353 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr7 44354 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr8 44355 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr9 44356 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr10 44357 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr11 44358 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr12 44359 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr13 44360 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr14 44361 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvr15 44362 | Given the equivalences set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et match ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ↔ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx0 44363 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx1 44364 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx2 44365 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx3 44366 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx4 44367 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx5 44368 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx6 44369 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx7 44370 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx8 44371 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx9 44372 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx10 44373 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx11 44374 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx12 44375 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx13 44376 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜁)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx14 44377 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜁) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | mdandyvrx15 44378 | Given the exclusivities set in the hypotheses, there exist a proof where ch, th, ta, et exclude ze, si accordingly. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 7-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜁) & ⊢ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜎) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝜒 ⊻ 𝜎) ∧ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜏 ⊻ 𝜎)) ∧ (𝜂 ⊻ 𝜎)) | ||
Theorem | H15NH16TH15IH16 44379 | Given 15 hypotheses and a 16th hypothesis, there exists a proof the 15 imply the 16th. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 8-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ 𝜃 & ⊢ 𝜏 & ⊢ 𝜂 & ⊢ 𝜁 & ⊢ 𝜎 & ⊢ 𝜌 & ⊢ 𝜇 & ⊢ 𝜆 & ⊢ 𝜅 & ⊢ jph & ⊢ jps & ⊢ jch & ⊢ jth ⇒ ⊢ (((((((((((((((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) ∧ 𝜏) ∧ 𝜂) ∧ 𝜁) ∧ 𝜎) ∧ 𝜌) ∧ 𝜇) ∧ 𝜆) ∧ 𝜅) ∧ jph) ∧ jps) ∧ jch) → jth) | ||
Theorem | dandysum2p2e4 44380 |
CONTRADICTION PROVED AT 1 + 1 = 2 .
Given the right hypotheses we can prove a dandysum of 2+2=4. The qed step is the value '4' in Decimal BEING IMPLIED by the hypotheses. Note: Values that when added would exceed a 4bit value are not supported. Note: Digits begin from left (least) to right (greatest). E.g., 1000 would be '1', 0100 would be '2', 0010 would be '4'. How to perceive the hypotheses' bits in order: ( th <-> F. ), ( ta <-> F. ) Would be input value X's first bit, and input value Y's first bit. ( et <-> F ), ( ze <-> F. ) would be input value X's second bit, and input value Y's second bit. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜂 ∧ 𝜁)) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ (𝜎 ∧ 𝜌)) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜁 ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜎 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜌 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜇 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜆 ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (𝜅 ↔ ((𝜃 ⊻ 𝜏) ⊻ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏))) & ⊢ (jph ↔ ((𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁) ∨ 𝜑)) & ⊢ (jps ↔ ((𝜎 ⊻ 𝜌) ∨ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (jch ↔ ((𝜇 ⊻ 𝜆) ∨ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ ((((((((((((((((𝜑 ↔ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏)) ∧ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜂 ∧ 𝜁))) ∧ (𝜒 ↔ (𝜎 ∧ 𝜌))) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤)) ∧ (𝜁 ↔ ⊤)) ∧ (𝜎 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜌 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜇 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜆 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜅 ↔ ((𝜃 ⊻ 𝜏) ⊻ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏)))) ∧ (jph ↔ ((𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁) ∨ 𝜑))) ∧ (jps ↔ ((𝜎 ⊻ 𝜌) ∨ 𝜓))) ∧ (jch ↔ ((𝜇 ⊻ 𝜆) ∨ 𝜒))) → ((((𝜅 ↔ ⊥) ∧ (jph ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (jps ↔ ⊤)) ∧ (jch ↔ ⊥))) | ||
Theorem | mdandysum2p2e4 44381 |
CONTRADICTION PROVED AT 1 + 1 = 2 . Luckily Mario Carneiro did a
successful version of his own.
See Mario's Relevant Work: Half adder and full adder in propositional calculus. Given the right hypotheses we can prove a dandysum of 2+2=4. The qed step is the value '4' in Decimal BEING IMPLIED by the hypotheses. Note: Values that when added would exceed a 4bit value are not supported. Note: Digits begin from left (least) to right (greatest). E.g., 1000 would be '1', 0100 would be '2'. 0010 would be '4'. How to perceive the hypotheses' bits in order: ( th <-> F. ), ( ta <-> F. ) Would be input value X's first bit, and input value Y's first bit. ( et <-> F. ), ( ze <-> F. ) would be input value X's second bit, and input value Y's second bit. In mdandysum2p2e4, one might imagine what jth or jta could be then do the math with their truths. Also limited to the restriction jth, jta are having opposite truths equivalent to the stated truth constants. (Contributed by Jarvin Udandy, 6-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (jth ↔ ⊥) & ⊢ (jta ↔ ⊤) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜂 ∧ 𝜁)) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ (𝜎 ∧ 𝜌)) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ jth) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ jth) & ⊢ (𝜂 ↔ jta) & ⊢ (𝜁 ↔ jta) & ⊢ (𝜎 ↔ jth) & ⊢ (𝜌 ↔ jth) & ⊢ (𝜇 ↔ jth) & ⊢ (𝜆 ↔ jth) & ⊢ (𝜅 ↔ ((𝜃 ⊻ 𝜏) ⊻ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏))) & ⊢ (jph ↔ ((𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁) ∨ 𝜑)) & ⊢ (jps ↔ ((𝜎 ⊻ 𝜌) ∨ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (jch ↔ ((𝜇 ⊻ 𝜆) ∨ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ ((((((((((((((((𝜑 ↔ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏)) ∧ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜂 ∧ 𝜁))) ∧ (𝜒 ↔ (𝜎 ∧ 𝜌))) ∧ (𝜃 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜏 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜂 ↔ ⊤)) ∧ (𝜁 ↔ ⊤)) ∧ (𝜎 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜌 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜇 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜆 ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (𝜅 ↔ ((𝜃 ⊻ 𝜏) ⊻ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏)))) ∧ (jph ↔ ((𝜂 ⊻ 𝜁) ∨ 𝜑))) ∧ (jps ↔ ((𝜎 ⊻ 𝜌) ∨ 𝜓))) ∧ (jch ↔ ((𝜇 ⊻ 𝜆) ∨ 𝜒))) → ((((𝜅 ↔ ⊥) ∧ (jph ↔ ⊥)) ∧ (jps ↔ ⊤)) ∧ (jch ↔ ⊥))) | ||
Theorem | adh-jarrsc 44382 | Replacement of a nested antecedent with an outer antecedent. Commuted simplificated form of elimination of a nested antecedent. Also holds intuitionistically. Polish prefix notation: CCCpqrCsCqr . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → (𝜃 → (𝜓 → 𝜒))) | ||
Minimal implicational calculus, or intuitionistic implicational calculus, or positive implicational calculus, is the implicational fragment of minimal calculus (which is also the implicational fragment of intuitionistic calculus and of positive calculus). It is sometimes called "C-pure intuitionism" since the letter C is used to denote implication in Polish prefix notation. It can be axiomatized by the inference rule of modus ponens ax-mp 5 together with the axioms { ax-1 6, ax-2 7 } (sometimes written KS), or with { imim1 83, ax-1 6, pm2.43 56 } (written B'KW), or with { imim2 58, pm2.04 90, ax-1 6, pm2.43 56 } (written BCKW), or with the single axiom adh-minim 44383, or with the single axiom adh-minimp 44395. This section proves first adh-minim 44383 from { ax-1 6, ax-2 7 }, followed by the converse, due to Ivo Thomas; and then it proves adh-minimp 44395 from { ax-1 6, ax-2 7 }, also followed by the converse, also due to Ivo Thomas. Sources for this section are * Carew Arthur Meredith, A single axiom of positive logic, The Journal of Computing Systems, volume 1, issue 3, July 1953, pages 169--170; * Ivo Thomas, On Meredith's sole positive axiom, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, volume XV, number 3, July 1974, page 477, in which the derivations of { ax-1 6, ax-2 7 } from adh-minim 44383 are shortened (compared to Meredith's derivations in the aforementioned paper); * Carew Arthur Meredith and Arthur Norman Prior, Notes on the axiomatics of the propositional calculus, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, volume IV, number 3, July 1963, pages 171--187; and * the webpage https://web.ics.purdue.edu/~dulrich/C-pure-intuitionism-page.htm 44383 on Dolph Edward "Ted" Ulrich's website, where these and other single axioms for the minimal implicational calculus are listed. This entire section also holds intuitionistically. Users of the Polish prefix notation also often use a compact notation for proof derivations known as the D-notation where "D" stands for "condensed Detachment". For instance, "D21" means detaching ax-1 6 from ax-2 7, that is, using modus ponens ax-mp 5 with ax-1 6 as minor premise and ax-2 7 as major premise. When the numbered lemmas surpass 10, dots are added between the numbers. D-strings are accepted by the grammar Dundotted := digit | "D" Dundotted Dundotted ; Ddotted := digit + | "D" Ddotted "." Ddotted ; Dstr := Dundotted | Ddotted . (Contributed by BJ, 11-Apr-2021.) (Revised by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim 44383 | A single axiom for minimal implicational calculus, due to Meredith. Other single axioms of the same length are known, but it is thought to be the minimal length. This is the axiom from Carew Arthur Meredith, A single axiom of positive logic, The Journal of Computing Systems, volume 1, issue 3, July 1953, pages 169--170. A two-line review by Alonzo Church of this article can be found in The Journal of Symbolic Logic, volume 19, issue 2, June 1954, page 144, https://doi.org/10.2307/2268914. Known as "HI-1" on Dolph Edward "Ted" Ulrich's web page. In the next 6 lemmas and 3 theorems, ax-1 6 and ax-2 7 are derived from this single axiom in 16 detachments (instances of ax-mp 5) in total. Polish prefix notation: CCCpqrCsCCqCrtCqt . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → (𝜃 → ((𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) → (𝜓 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax1-ax2-lem1 44384 | First lemma for the derivation of ax-1 6 and ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CpCCqCCrCCsCqtCstuCqu . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → ((𝜒 → ((𝜃 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)) → (𝜃 → 𝜏))) → 𝜂)) → (𝜓 → 𝜂))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax1-ax2-lem2 44385 | Second lemma for the derivation of ax-1 6 and ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCpCCqCCrCpsCrstCpt . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ((𝜓 → ((𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)) → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) → 𝜏)) → (𝜑 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax1-ax2-lem3 44386 | Third lemma for the derivation of ax-1 6 and ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCpCqrCqCsCpr . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax1-ax2-lem4 44387 | Fourth lemma for the derivation of ax-1 6 and ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCCpqrCCqCrsCqs . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → ((𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax1 44388 | Derivation of ax-1 6 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Carew Arthur Meredith derived ax-1 6 in A single axiom of positive logic, The Journal of Computing Systems, volume 1, issue 3, July 1953, pages 169--170. However, here we follow the shortened derivation by Ivo Thomas, On Meredith's sole positive axiom, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, volume XV, number 3, July 1974, page 477. Polish prefix notation: CpCqp . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax2-lem5 44389 | Fifth lemma for the derivation of ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CpCCCqrsCCrCstCrt . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (((𝜓 → 𝜒) → 𝜃) → ((𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) → (𝜒 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax2-lem6 44390 | Sixth lemma for the derivation of ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCpCCCCqrsCCrCstCrtuCpu . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ((((𝜓 → 𝜒) → 𝜃) → ((𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) → (𝜒 → 𝜏))) → 𝜂)) → (𝜑 → 𝜂)) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax2c 44391 | Derivation of a commuted form of ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCpqCCpCqrCpr . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-ax2 44392 | Derivation of ax-2 7 from adh-minim 44383 and ax-mp 5. Carew Arthur Meredith derived ax-2 7 in A single axiom of positive logic, The Journal of Computing Systems, volume 1, issue 3, July 1953, pages 169--170. However, here we follow the shortened derivation by Ivo Thomas, On Meredith's sole positive axiom, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, volume XV, number 3, July 1974, page 477. Polish prefix notation: CCpCqrCCpqCpr . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-idALT 44393 | Derivation of id 22 (reflexivity of implication, PM *2.08 WhiteheadRussell p. 101) from adh-minim-ax1 44388, adh-minim-ax2 44392, and ax-mp 5. It uses the derivation written DD211 in D-notation. (See head comment for an explanation.) Polish prefix notation: Cpp . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | adh-minim-pm2.43 44394 | Derivation of pm2.43 56 WhiteheadRussell p. 106 (also called "hilbert" or "W") from adh-minim-ax1 44388, adh-minim-ax2 44392, and ax-mp 5. It uses the derivation written DD22D21 in D-notation. (See head comment for an explanation.) (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | adh-minimp 44395 | Another single axiom for minimal implicational calculus, due to Meredith. Other single axioms of the same length are known, but it is thought to be the minimal length. Among single axioms of this length, it is the one with simplest antecedents (i.e., in the corresponding ordering of binary trees which first compares left subtrees, it is the first one). Known as "HI-2" on Dolph Edward "Ted" Ulrich's web page. In the next 4 lemmas and 5 theorems, ax-1 6 and ax-2 7 are derived from this other single axiom in 20 detachments (instances of ax-mp 5) in total. Polish prefix notation: CpCCqrCCCsqCrtCqt ; or CtCCpqCCCspCqrCpr in Carew Arthur Meredith and Arthur Norman Prior, Notes on the axiomatics of the propositional calculus, Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, volume IV, number 3, July 1963, pages 171--187, on page 180. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Apr-2021.) (Revised by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (((𝜃 → 𝜓) → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) → (𝜓 → 𝜏)))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minimp-jarr-imim1-ax2c-lem1 44396 | First lemma for the derivation of jarr 106, imim1 83, and a commuted form of ax-2 7, and indirectly ax-1 6 and ax-2 7, from adh-minimp 44395 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCpqCCCrpCqsCps . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (((𝜒 → 𝜑) → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) → (𝜑 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | adh-minimp-jarr-lem2 44397 | Second lemma for the derivation of jarr 106, and indirectly ax-1 6, a commuted form of ax-2 7, and ax-2 7 proper, from adh-minimp 44395 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCCpqCCCrsCCCtrCsuCruvCqv . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (((𝜒 → 𝜃) → (((𝜏 → 𝜒) → (𝜃 → 𝜂)) → (𝜒 → 𝜂))) → 𝜁)) → (𝜓 → 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | adh-minimp-jarr-ax2c-lem3 44398 | Third lemma for the derivation of jarr 106 and a commuted form of ax-2 7, and indirectly ax-1 6 and ax-2 7 proper , from adh-minimp 44395 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCCCpqCCCrpCqsCpstt . (Contributed by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (((𝜒 → 𝜑) → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) → (𝜑 → 𝜃))) → 𝜏) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | adh-minimp-sylsimp 44399 | Derivation of jarr 106 (also called "syll-simp") from minimp 1625 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CCCpqrCqr . (Contributed by BJ, 4-Apr-2021.) (Revised by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | adh-minimp-ax1 44400 | Derivation of ax-1 6 from adh-minimp 44395 and ax-mp 5. Polish prefix notation: CpCqp . (Contributed by BJ, 4-Apr-2021.) (Revised by ADH, 10-Nov-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜑)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |