Metamath Proof Explorer |
< Previous
Next >
Nearby theorems |
||
Mirrors > Home > MPE Home > Th. List > df-clab | Structured version Visualization version GIF version |
Description: Define class
abstractions, that is, classes of the form {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑},
which is read "the class of sets 𝑦 such that 𝜑(𝑦)".
A few remarks are in order: 1. The axiomatic statement df-clab 2716 does not define the class abstraction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} itself, that is, it does not have the form ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} = ... that a standard definition should have (for a good reason: equality itself has not yet been defined or axiomatized for class abstractions; it is defined later in df-cleq 2730). Instead, df-clab 2716 has the form ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ ...), meaning that it only defines what it means for a setvar to be a member of a class abstraction. As a consequence, one can say that df-clab 2716 defines class abstractions if and only if a class abstraction is completely determined by which elements belong to it, which is the content of the axiom of extensionality ax-ext 2709. Therefore, df-clab 2716 can be considered a definition only in systems that can prove ax-ext 2709 (and the necessary first-order logic). 2. As in all definitions, the definiendum (the left-hand side of the biconditional) has no disjoint variable conditions. In particular, the setvar variables 𝑥 and 𝑦 need not be distinct, and the formula 𝜑 may depend on both 𝑥 and 𝑦. This is necessary, as with all definitions, since if there was for instance a disjoint variable condition on 𝑥, 𝑦, then one could not do anything with expressions like 𝑥 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} which are sometimes useful to shorten proofs (because of abid 2719). Most often, however, 𝑥 does not occur in {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} and 𝑦 is free in 𝜑. 3. Remark 1 stresses that df-clab 2716 does not have the standard form of a definition for a class, but one could be led to think it has the standard form of a definition for a formula. However, it also fails that test since the membership predicate ∈ has already appeared earlier (e.g., in the non-syntactic statement ax-8 2108). Indeed, the definiendum extends, or "overloads", the membership predicate ∈ from formulas of the form "setvar ∈ setvar" to formulas of the form "setvar ∈ class abstraction". This is possible because of wcel 2106 and cab 2715, and it can be called an "extension" of the membership predicate because of wel 2107, whose proof uses cv 1538. An a posteriori justification for cv 1538 is given by cvjust 2732, stating that every setvar can be written as a class abstraction (though conversely not every class abstraction is a set, as illustrated by Russell's paradox ru 3715). 4. Proof techniques. Because class variables can be substituted with compound expressions and setvar variables cannot, it is often useful to convert a theorem containing a free setvar variable to a more general version with a class variable. This is done with theorems such as vtoclg 3505 which is used, for example, to convert elirrv 9355 to elirr 9356. 5. Definition or axiom? The question arises with the three axiomatic statements introducing classes, df-clab 2716, df-cleq 2730, and df-clel 2816, to decide if they qualify as definitions or if they should be called axioms. Under the strict definition of "definition" (see conventions 28764), they are not definitions (see Remarks 1 and 3 above, and similarly for df-cleq 2730 and df-clel 2816). One could be less strict and decide to call "definition" every axiomatic statement which provides an eliminable and conservative extension of the considered axiom system. But the notion of conservativity may be given two different meanings in set.mm, due to the difference between the "scheme level" of set.mm and the "object level" of classical treatments. For a proof that these three axiomatic statements yield an eliminable and weakly (that is, object-level) conservative extension of FOL= plus ax-ext 2709, see Appendix of [Levy] p. 357. 6. References and history. The concept of class abstraction dates back to at least Frege, and is used by Whitehead and Russell. This definition is Definition 2.1 of [Quine] p. 16 and Axiom 4.3.1 of [Levy] p. 12. It is called the "axiom of class comprehension" by [Levy] p. 358, who treats the theory of classes as an extralogical extension to predicate logic and set theory axioms. He calls the construction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} a "class term". For a full description of how classes are introduced and how to recover the primitive language, see the books of Quine and Levy (and the comment of abeq2 2872 for a quick overview). For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see mmset.html#class 2872. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 19-Aug-2023.) |
Ref | Expression |
---|---|
df-clab | ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Step | Hyp | Ref | Expression |
---|---|---|---|
1 | vx | . . . 4 setvar 𝑥 | |
2 | 1 | cv 1538 | . . 3 class 𝑥 |
3 | wph | . . . 4 wff 𝜑 | |
4 | vy | . . . 4 setvar 𝑦 | |
5 | 3, 4 | cab 2715 | . . 3 class {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
6 | 2, 5 | wcel 2106 | . 2 wff 𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
7 | 3, 4, 1 | wsb 2067 | . 2 wff [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑 |
8 | 6, 7 | wb 205 | 1 wff (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Colors of variables: wff setvar class |
This definition is referenced by: eleq1ab 2717 abid 2719 vexwt 2720 vexw 2721 nfsab1 2723 hbab1OLD 2725 hbab 2726 hbabg 2727 cvjust 2732 abbi1 2806 abbi 2810 cbvabv 2811 cbvabw 2812 cbvabwOLD 2813 cbvab 2814 abeq2w 2815 abbi2dv 2877 clelab 2883 clelabOLD 2884 nfabdw 2930 nfabdwOLD 2931 nfabd 2932 rabrabi 3427 abv 3443 abvALT 3444 elab6g 3600 elrabi 3618 ralab 3628 dfsbcq2 3719 sbc8g 3724 sbcimdv 3790 sbcg 3795 csbied 3870 ss2abdv 3997 ss2abdvALT 3998 unabw 4231 unab 4232 inab 4233 difab 4234 notabw 4237 noel 4264 noelOLD 4265 vn0 4272 eq0 4277 ab0w 4307 ab0OLD 4309 ab0orv 4312 eq0rdv 4338 csbab 4371 disj 4381 rzal 4439 ralf0 4444 exss 5378 iotaeq 6404 abrexex2g 7807 opabex3d 7808 opabex3rd 7809 opabex3 7810 xpab 33677 eliminable1 35043 eliminable-velab 35049 bj-ab0 35093 bj-elabd2ALT 35113 bj-gabima 35128 bj-snsetex 35153 wl-clabv 35746 wl-clabtv 35748 wl-clabt 35749 elabgw 40165 scottabf 41858 |
Copyright terms: Public domain | W3C validator |