Metamath Proof Explorer |
< Previous
Next >
Nearby theorems |
||
Mirrors > Home > MPE Home > Th. List > df-clab | Structured version Visualization version GIF version |
Description: Define class
abstractions, that is, classes of the form {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑},
which is read "the class of sets 𝑦 such that 𝜑(𝑦)".
A few remarks are in order: 1. The axiomatic statement df-clab 2717 does not define the class abstraction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} itself, that is, it does not have the form ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} = ... that a standard definition should have (for a good reason: equality itself has not yet been defined or axiomatized for class abstractions; it is defined later in df-cleq 2731). Instead, df-clab 2717 has the form ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ ...), meaning that it only defines what it means for a setvar to be a member of a class abstraction. As a consequence, one can say that df-clab 2717 defines class abstractions if and only if a class abstraction is completely determined by which elements belong to it, which is the content of the axiom of extensionality ax-ext 2710. Therefore, df-clab 2717 can be considered a definition only in systems that can prove ax-ext 2710 (and the necessary first-order logic). 2. As in all definitions, the definiendum (the left-hand side of the biconditional) has no disjoint variable conditions. In particular, the setvar variables 𝑥 and 𝑦 need not be distinct, and the formula 𝜑 may depend on both 𝑥 and 𝑦. This is necessary, as with all definitions, since if there was for instance a disjoint variable condition on 𝑥, 𝑦, then one could not do anything with expressions like 𝑥 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} which are sometimes useful to shorten proofs (because of abid 2720). Most often, however, 𝑥 does not occur in {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} and 𝑦 is free in 𝜑. 3. Remark 1 stresses that df-clab 2717 does not have the standard form of a definition for a class, but one could be led to think it has the standard form of a definition for a formula. However, it also fails that test since the membership predicate ∈ has already appeared earlier (e.g., in the non-syntactic statement ax-8 2114). Indeed, the definiendum extends, or "overloads", the membership predicate ∈ from formulas of the form "setvar ∈ setvar" to formulas of the form "setvar ∈ class abstraction". This is possible because of wcel 2112 and cab 2716, and it can be called an "extension" of the membership predicate because of wel 2113, whose proof uses cv 1542. An a posteriori justification for cv 1542 is given by cvjust 2733, stating that every setvar can be written as a class abstraction (though conversely not every class abstraction is a set, as illustrated by Russell's paradox ru 3711). 4. Proof techniques. Because class variables can be substituted with compound expressions and setvar variables cannot, it is often useful to convert a theorem containing a free setvar variable to a more general version with a class variable. This is done with theorems such as vtoclg 3496 which is used, for example, to convert elirrv 9260 to elirr 9261. 5. Definition or axiom? The question arises with the three axiomatic statements introducing classes, df-clab 2717, df-cleq 2731, and df-clel 2818, to decide if they qualify as definitions or if they should be called axioms. Under the strict definition of "definition" (see conventions 28640), they are not definitions (see Remarks 1 and 3 above, and similarly for df-cleq 2731 and df-clel 2818). One could be less strict and decide to call "definition" every axiomatic statement which provides an eliminable and conservative extension of the considered axiom system. But the notion of conservativity may be given two different meanings in set.mm, due to the difference between the "scheme level" of set.mm and the "object level" of classical treatments. For a proof that these three axiomatic statements yield an eliminable and weakly (that is, object-level) conservative extension of FOL= plus ax-ext 2710, see Appendix of [Levy] p. 357. 6. References and history. The concept of class abstraction dates back to at least Frege, and is used by Whitehead and Russell. This definition is Definition 2.1 of [Quine] p. 16 and Axiom 4.3.1 of [Levy] p. 12. It is called the "axiom of class comprehension" by [Levy] p. 358, who treats the theory of classes as an extralogical extension to predicate logic and set theory axioms. He calls the construction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} a "class term". For a full description of how classes are introduced and how to recover the primitive language, see the books of Quine and Levy (and the comment of abeq2 2872 for a quick overview). For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see mmset.html#class 2872. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 19-Aug-2023.) |
Ref | Expression |
---|---|
df-clab | ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Step | Hyp | Ref | Expression |
---|---|---|---|
1 | vx | . . . 4 setvar 𝑥 | |
2 | 1 | cv 1542 | . . 3 class 𝑥 |
3 | wph | . . . 4 wff 𝜑 | |
4 | vy | . . . 4 setvar 𝑦 | |
5 | 3, 4 | cab 2716 | . . 3 class {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
6 | 2, 5 | wcel 2112 | . 2 wff 𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
7 | 3, 4, 1 | wsb 2072 | . 2 wff [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑 |
8 | 6, 7 | wb 209 | 1 wff (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Colors of variables: wff setvar class |
This definition is referenced by: eleq1ab 2718 abid 2720 vexwt 2721 vexw 2722 nfsab1 2724 hbab1OLD 2726 hbab 2727 hbabg 2728 cvjust 2733 abbi1 2808 abbi 2812 cbvabv 2813 cbvabw 2814 cbvabwOLD 2815 cbvab 2816 abeq2w 2817 abbi2dv 2877 clelab 2883 clelabOLD 2884 nfabdw 2930 nfabdwOLD 2931 nfabd 2932 rabrabi 3418 abv 3434 abvALT 3435 elab6g 3594 elrabi 3612 ralab 3622 dfsbcq2 3715 sbc8g 3720 sbcimdv 3787 sbcg 3792 csbied 3867 ss2abdv 3994 ss2abdvALT 3995 unabw 4229 unab 4230 inab 4231 difab 4232 notabw 4235 noel 4262 noelOLD 4263 vn0 4270 eq0 4275 ab0w 4305 ab0OLD 4307 ab0orv 4310 eq0rdv 4336 csbab 4369 disj 4379 rzal 4437 ralf0 4442 exss 5371 iotaeq 6386 abrexex2g 7777 opabex3d 7778 opabex3rd 7779 opabex3 7780 xpab 33554 eliminable1 34945 eliminable-velab 34951 bj-ab0 34995 bj-elabd2ALT 35015 bj-gabima 35030 bj-snsetex 35055 wl-clabv 35652 wl-clabtv 35654 wl-clabt 35655 elabgw 40065 scottabf 41720 |
Copyright terms: Public domain | W3C validator |