![]() |
Metamath Proof Explorer |
< Previous
Next >
Nearby theorems |
|
Mirrors > Home > MPE Home > Th. List > df-clab | Structured version Visualization version GIF version |
Description: Define class
abstractions, that is, classes of the form {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑},
which is read "the class of sets 𝑦 such that 𝜑(𝑦)".
A few remarks are in order: 1. The axiomatic statement df-clab 2716 does not define the class abstraction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} itself, that is, it does not have the form ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} = ... that a standard definition should have (for a good reason: equality itself has not yet been defined or axiomatized for class abstractions; it is defined later in df-cleq 2730). Instead, df-clab 2716 has the form ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ ...), meaning that it only defines what it means for a setvar to be a member of a class abstraction. As a consequence, one can say that df-clab 2716 defines class abstractions if and only if a class abstraction is completely determined by which elements belong to it, which is the content of the axiom of extensionality ax-ext 2709. Therefore, df-clab 2716 can be considered a definition only in systems that can prove ax-ext 2709 (and the necessary first-order logic). 2. As in all definitions, the definiendum (the left-hand side of the biconditional) has no disjoint variable conditions. In particular, the setvar variables 𝑥 and 𝑦 need not be distinct, and the formula 𝜑 may depend on both 𝑥 and 𝑦. This is necessary, as with all definitions, since if there was for instance a disjoint variable condition on 𝑥, 𝑦, then one could not do anything with expressions like 𝑥 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} which are sometimes useful to shorten proofs (because of abid 2719). Most often, however, 𝑥 does not occur in {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} and 𝑦 is free in 𝜑. 3. Remark 1 stresses that df-clab 2716 does not have the standard form of a definition for a class, but one could be led to think it has the standard form of a definition for a formula. However, it also fails that test since the membership predicate ∈ has already appeared earlier (e.g., in the non-syntactic statement ax-8 2109). Indeed, the definiendum extends, or "overloads", the membership predicate ∈ from formulas of the form "setvar ∈ setvar" to formulas of the form "setvar ∈ class abstraction". This is possible because of wcel 2107 and cab 2715, and it can be called an "extension" of the membership predicate because of wel 2108, whose proof uses cv 1541. An a posteriori justification for cv 1541 is given by cvjust 2732, stating that every setvar can be written as a class abstraction (though conversely not every class abstraction is a set, as illustrated by Russell's paradox ru 3737). 4. Proof techniques. Because class variables can be substituted with compound expressions and setvar variables cannot, it is often useful to convert a theorem containing a free setvar variable to a more general version with a class variable. This is done with theorems such as vtoclg 3524 which is used, for example, to convert elirrv 9491 to elirr 9492. 5. Definition or axiom? The question arises with the three axiomatic statements introducing classes, df-clab 2716, df-cleq 2730, and df-clel 2816, to decide if they qualify as definitions or if they should be called axioms. Under the strict definition of "definition" (see conventions 29173), they are not definitions (see Remarks 1 and 3 above, and similarly for df-cleq 2730 and df-clel 2816). One could be less strict and decide to call "definition" every axiomatic statement which provides an eliminable and conservative extension of the considered axiom system. But the notion of conservativity may be given two different meanings in set.mm, due to the difference between the "scheme level" of set.mm and the "object level" of classical treatments. For a proof that these three axiomatic statements yield an eliminable and weakly (that is, object-level) conservative extension of FOL= plus ax-ext 2709, see Appendix of [Levy] p. 357. 6. References and history. The concept of class abstraction dates back to at least Frege, and is used by Whitehead and Russell. This definition is Definition 2.1 of [Quine] p. 16 and Axiom 4.3.1 of [Levy] p. 12. It is called the "axiom of class comprehension" by [Levy] p. 358, who treats the theory of classes as an extralogical extension to predicate logic and set theory axioms. He calls the construction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} a "class term". For a full description of how classes are introduced and how to recover the primitive language, see the books of Quine and Levy (and the comment of abeq2 2872 for a quick overview). For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see mmset.html#class 2872. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 19-Aug-2023.) |
Ref | Expression |
---|---|
df-clab | ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Step | Hyp | Ref | Expression |
---|---|---|---|
1 | vx | . . . 4 setvar 𝑥 | |
2 | 1 | cv 1541 | . . 3 class 𝑥 |
3 | wph | . . . 4 wff 𝜑 | |
4 | vy | . . . 4 setvar 𝑦 | |
5 | 3, 4 | cab 2715 | . . 3 class {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
6 | 2, 5 | wcel 2107 | . 2 wff 𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
7 | 3, 4, 1 | wsb 2068 | . 2 wff [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑 |
8 | 6, 7 | wb 205 | 1 wff (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Colors of variables: wff setvar class |
This definition is referenced by: eleq1ab 2717 abid 2719 vexwt 2720 vexw 2721 nfsab1 2723 hbab1OLD 2725 hbab 2726 hbabg 2727 cvjust 2732 abbi1 2806 abbi 2810 cbvabv 2811 cbvabw 2812 cbvabwOLD 2813 cbvab 2814 abeq2w 2815 abbi2dv 2877 clelab 2882 clelabOLD 2883 nfabdw 2929 nfabdwOLD 2930 nfabd 2931 rabrabi 3424 abv 3455 abvALT 3456 elab6g 3620 elrabi 3638 ralab 3648 dfsbcq2 3741 sbc8g 3746 sbcimdv 3812 sbcg 3817 csbied 3892 ss2abdv 4019 ss2abdvALT 4020 unabw 4256 unab 4257 inab 4258 difab 4259 notabw 4262 noel 4289 noelOLD 4290 vn0 4297 eq0 4302 ab0w 4332 ab0OLD 4334 ab0orv 4337 eq0rdv 4363 csbab 4396 disj 4406 rzal 4465 ralf0 4470 exss 5419 iotaeq 6459 abrexex2g 7890 opabex3d 7891 opabex3rd 7892 opabex3 7893 xpab 34103 eliminable1 35257 eliminable-velab 35263 bj-ab0 35307 bj-elabd2ALT 35327 bj-gabima 35342 bj-snsetex 35366 wl-clabv 35979 wl-clabtv 35981 wl-clabt 35982 elabgw 40549 ss2ab1 40572 scottabf 42425 |
Copyright terms: Public domain | W3C validator |