![]() |
Metamath Proof Explorer |
< Previous
Next >
Nearby theorems |
|
Mirrors > Home > MPE Home > Th. List > df-clab | Structured version Visualization version GIF version |
Description: Define class
abstractions, that is, classes of the form {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑},
which is read "the class of sets 𝑦 such that 𝜑(𝑦)".
A few remarks are in order: 1. The axiomatic statement df-clab 2718 does not define the class abstraction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} itself, that is, it does not have the form ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} = ... that a standard definition should have (for a good reason: equality itself has not yet been defined or axiomatized for class abstractions; it is defined later in df-cleq 2732). Instead, df-clab 2718 has the form ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ ...), meaning that it only defines what it means for a setvar to be a member of a class abstraction. As a consequence, one can say that df-clab 2718 defines class abstractions if and only if a class abstraction is completely determined by which elements belong to it, which is the content of the axiom of extensionality ax-ext 2711. Therefore, df-clab 2718 can be considered a definition only in systems that can prove ax-ext 2711 (and the necessary first-order logic). 2. As in all definitions, the definiendum (the left-hand side of the biconditional) has no disjoint variable conditions. In particular, the setvar variables 𝑥 and 𝑦 need not be distinct, and the formula 𝜑 may depend on both 𝑥 and 𝑦. This is necessary, as with all definitions, since if there was for instance a disjoint variable condition on 𝑥, 𝑦, then one could not do anything with expressions like 𝑥 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} which are sometimes useful to shorten proofs (because of abid 2721). Most often, however, 𝑥 does not occur in {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} and 𝑦 is free in 𝜑. 3. Remark 1 stresses that df-clab 2718 does not have the standard form of a definition for a class, but one could be led to think it has the standard form of a definition for a formula. However, it also fails that test since the membership predicate ∈ has already appeared earlier (outside of syntax e.g. in ax-8 2110). Indeed, the definiendum extends, or "overloads", the membership predicate ∈ from formulas of the form "setvar ∈ setvar" to formulas of the form "setvar ∈ class abstraction". This is possible because of wcel 2108 and cab 2717, and it can be called an "extension" of the membership predicate because of wel 2109, whose proof uses cv 1536. An a posteriori justification for cv 1536 is given by cvjust 2734, stating that every setvar can be written as a class abstraction (though conversely not every class abstraction is a set, as illustrated by Russell's paradox ru 3802). 4. Proof techniques. Because class variables can be substituted with compound expressions and setvar variables cannot, it is often useful to convert a theorem containing a free setvar variable to a more general version with a class variable. This is done with theorems such as vtoclg 3566 which is used, for example, to convert elirrv 9665 to elirr 9666. 5. Definition or axiom? The question arises with the three axiomatic statements introducing classes, df-clab 2718, df-cleq 2732, and df-clel 2819, to decide if they qualify as definitions or if they should be called axioms. Under the strict definition of "definition" (see conventions 30432), they are not definitions (see Remarks 1 and 3 above, and similarly for df-cleq 2732 and df-clel 2819). One could be less strict and decide to call "definition" every axiomatic statement which provides an eliminable and conservative extension of the considered axiom system. But the notion of conservativity may be given two different meanings in set.mm, due to the difference between the "scheme level" of set.mm and the "object level" of classical treatments. For a proof that these three axiomatic statements yield an eliminable and weakly (that is, object-level) conservative extension of FOL= plus ax-ext 2711, see Appendix of [Levy] p. 357. 6. References and history. The concept of class abstraction dates back to at least Frege, and is used by Whitehead and Russell. This definition is Definition 2.1 of [Quine] p. 16 and Axiom 4.3.1 of [Levy] p. 12. It is called the "axiom of class comprehension" by [Levy] p. 358, who treats the theory of classes as an extralogical extension to predicate logic and set theory axioms. He calls the construction {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} a "class term". For a full description of how classes are introduced and how to recover the primitive language, see the books of Quine and Levy (and the comment of eqabb 2884 for a quick overview). For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see mmset.html#class 2884. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 19-Aug-2023.) |
Ref | Expression |
---|---|
df-clab | ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Step | Hyp | Ref | Expression |
---|---|---|---|
1 | vx | . . . 4 setvar 𝑥 | |
2 | 1 | cv 1536 | . . 3 class 𝑥 |
3 | wph | . . . 4 wff 𝜑 | |
4 | vy | . . . 4 setvar 𝑦 | |
5 | 3, 4 | cab 2717 | . . 3 class {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
6 | 2, 5 | wcel 2108 | . 2 wff 𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} |
7 | 3, 4, 1 | wsb 2064 | . 2 wff [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑 |
8 | 6, 7 | wb 206 | 1 wff (𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ [𝑥 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
Colors of variables: wff setvar class |
This definition is referenced by: eleq1ab 2719 abid 2721 vexwt 2722 vexw 2723 nfsab1 2725 hbab1OLD 2727 hbab 2728 hbabg 2729 cvjust 2734 abbi 2810 abbib 2814 cbvabv 2815 cbvabw 2816 cbvab 2817 eqabbw 2818 eqabdv 2878 clelab 2890 nfaba1 2916 nfabdw 2932 nfabdwOLD 2933 nfabd 2934 rabrabi 3463 abv 3500 abvALT 3501 elab6g 3682 elabgw 3692 elrabi 3703 ralab 3713 dfsbcq2 3807 sbc8g 3812 sbcimdv 3878 sbcg 3883 csbied 3959 dfss2 3994 ss2abdv 4089 unabw 4326 unab 4327 inab 4328 difab 4329 notabw 4332 noel 4360 noelOLD 4361 vn0 4368 eq0 4373 ab0w 4401 ab0OLD 4403 ab0orv 4406 eq0rdv 4430 csbab 4463 disj 4473 rzal 4532 ralf0 4537 exss 5483 iotaeq 6538 abrexex2g 8005 opabex3d 8006 opabex3rd 8007 opabex3 8008 xpab 35688 in-ax8 36190 ss-ax8 36191 cbvabdavw 36222 eliminable1 36825 eliminable-velab 36831 bj-ab0 36874 bj-elabd2ALT 36891 bj-gabima 36906 bj-snsetex 36929 wl-clabv 37549 wl-clabtv 37551 wl-clabt 37552 ss2ab1 42212 scottabf 44209 |
Copyright terms: Public domain | W3C validator |