MPE Home Metamath Proof Explorer < Previous   Next >
Nearby theorems
Mirrors  >  Home  >  MPE Home  >  Th. List  >  df-sb Structured version   Visualization version   GIF version

Definition df-sb 2065
Description: Define proper substitution. For our notation, we use [𝑡 / 𝑥]𝜑 to mean "the wff that results from the proper substitution of 𝑡 for 𝑥 in the wff 𝜑". That is, 𝑡 properly replaces 𝑥. For example, [𝑡 / 𝑥]𝑧𝑥 is the same as 𝑧𝑡 (when 𝑥 and 𝑧 are distinct), as shown in elsb2 2120.

Our notation was introduced in Haskell B. Curry's Foundations of Mathematical Logic (1977), p. 316 and is frequently used in textbooks of lambda calculus and combinatory logic. This notation improves the common but ambiguous notation, "𝜑(𝑡) is the wff that results when 𝑡 is properly substituted for 𝑥 in 𝜑(𝑥)". For example, if the original 𝜑(𝑥) is 𝑥 = 𝑡, then 𝜑(𝑡) is 𝑡 = 𝑡, from which we obtain that 𝜑(𝑥) is 𝑥 = 𝑥. So what exactly does 𝜑(𝑥) mean? Curry's notation solves this problem.

A very similar notation, namely (𝑦𝑥)𝜑, was introduced in Bourbaki's Set Theory (Chapter 1, Description of Formal Mathematic, 1953).

In most books, proper substitution has a somewhat complicated recursive definition with multiple cases based on the occurrences of free and bound variables in the wff. Instead, we use a single formula that is exactly equivalent and gives us a direct definition. We later prove that our definition has the properties we expect of proper substitution (see Theorems sbequ 2083, sbcom2 2158 and sbid2v 2510).

Note that our definition is valid even when 𝑥 and 𝑡 are replaced with the same variable, as sbid 2245 shows. We achieve this by applying twice Tarski's definition sb6 2085 which is valid for disjoint variables, and introducing a dummy variable 𝑦 which isolates 𝑥 from 𝑡, as in dfsb7 2273 with respect to sb5 2265. We can also achieve this by having 𝑥 free in the first conjunct and bound in the second, as the alternate definition dfsb1 2482 shows. Another version that mixes free and bound variables is dfsb3 2495. When 𝑥 and 𝑡 are distinct, we can express proper substitution with the simpler expressions of sb5 2265 and sb6 2085.

Note that the occurrences of a given variable in the definiens are either all bound (𝑥, 𝑦) or all free (𝑡). Also note that the definiens uses only primitive symbols.

This double level definition will make several proofs using it appear as doubled. Alternately, one could often first prove as a lemma the same theorem with a disjoint variable condition on the substitute and the substituted variables, and then prove the original theorem by applying this lemma twice in a row. (Contributed by NM, 10-May-1993.) Revised from the original definition dfsb1 2482. (Revised by BJ, 22-Dec-2020.)

Assertion
Ref Expression
df-sb ([𝑡 / 𝑥]𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦(𝑦 = 𝑡 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
Distinct variable groups:   𝑥,𝑦   𝑦,𝑡   𝜑,𝑦
Allowed substitution hints:   𝜑(𝑥,𝑡)

Detailed syntax breakdown of Definition df-sb
StepHypRef Expression
1 wph . . 3 wff 𝜑
2 vx . . 3 setvar 𝑥
3 vt . . 3 setvar 𝑡
41, 2, 3wsb 2064 . 2 wff [𝑡 / 𝑥]𝜑
5 vy . . . . 5 setvar 𝑦
65, 3weq 1963 . . . 4 wff 𝑦 = 𝑡
72, 5weq 1963 . . . . . 6 wff 𝑥 = 𝑦
87, 1wi 4 . . . . 5 wff (𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)
98, 2wal 1536 . . . 4 wff 𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)
106, 9wi 4 . . 3 wff (𝑦 = 𝑡 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))
1110, 5wal 1536 . 2 wff 𝑦(𝑦 = 𝑡 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))
124, 11wb 205 1 wff ([𝑡 / 𝑥]𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦(𝑦 = 𝑡 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
Colors of variables: wff setvar class
This definition is referenced by:  sbt  2066  stdpc4  2068  sbi1  2071  spsbe  2082  sbequ  2083  sb6  2085  sbal  2156  hbsbw  2166  sbequ1  2237  sbequ2  2238  sbequ2OLD  2239  dfsb7  2273  sbn  2274  sbrim  2298  nfsbvOLD  2322  sbievg  2358  sb4b  2472  sb4bOLD  2473  bj-ssbeq  34841  bj-ssbid2ALT  34851  bj-ssbid1ALT  34853
  Copyright terms: Public domain W3C validator