Users' Mathboxes Mathbox for BJ < Previous   Next >
Nearby theorems
Mirrors  >  Home  >  MPE Home  >  Th. List  >   Mathboxes  >  df-bj-nnf Structured version   Visualization version   GIF version

Definition df-bj-nnf 36690
Description: Definition of the nonfreeness quantifier. The formula Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 has the intended meaning that the variable 𝑥 is semantically nonfree in the formula 𝜑. The motivation for this quantifier is to have a condition expressible in the logic which is as close as possible to the non-occurrence condition DV (𝑥, 𝜑) (in Metamath files, "$d x ph $."), which belongs to the metalogic.

The standard syntactic nonfreeness condition, also expressed in the metalogic, is intermediate between these two notions: semantic nonfreeness implies syntactic nonfreeness, which implies non-occurrence. Both implications are strict; for the first, note that Ⅎ'𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥, that is, 𝑥 is semantically (but not syntactically) nonfree in the formula 𝑥 = 𝑥; for the second, note that 𝑥 is syntactically nonfree in the formula 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥 although it occurs in it.

We now prove two metatheorems which make precise the above fact that, as far as proving power is concerned, the nonfreeness condition Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 is very close to the non-occurrence condition DV (𝑥, 𝜑).

Let S be a Metamath system with the FOL-syntax of (i)set.mm, containing intuitionistic positive propositional calculus and ax-5 1909 and ax5e 1911.

Theorem 1. If the scheme

(Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 & PHI1 & ... & PHIn PHI0, DV)

is provable in S, then so is the scheme

(PHI1 & ... & PHIn PHI0, DV ∪ {{𝑥, 𝜑}}).

Proof: By bj-nnfv 36720, we can prove (Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑, {{𝑥, 𝜑}}), from which the theorem follows. QED

Theorem 2. Suppose that S also contains (the FOL version of) modal logic KB and commutation of quantifiers alcom 2160 and excom 2163 (possibly weakened by a DV condition on the quantifying variables), and that S can be axiomatized such that the only axioms with a DV condition involving a formula variable are among ax-5 1909, ax5e 1911, ax5ea 1912. If the scheme

(PHI1 & ... & PHIn PHI0, DV)

is provable in S, then so is the scheme

(Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 & PHI1 & ... & PHIn PHI0, DV ∖ {{𝑥, 𝜑}}).

More precisely, if S contains modal 45 and if the variables quantified over in PHI0, ..., PHIn are among 𝑥1, ..., 𝑥m, then the scheme

(PHI1 & ... & PHIn (antecedent PHI0), DV ∖ {{𝑥, 𝜑}})

is provable in S, where the antecedent is a finite conjunction of formulas of the form 𝑥i1 ...∀𝑥ip Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 where the 𝑥ij's are among the 𝑥i's.

Lemma: If 𝑥 OC(PHI), then S proves the scheme

(Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 ⇒ Ⅎ'𝑥 PHI, {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PHI) ∖ {𝜑}}).

More precisely, if the variables quantified over in PHI are among 𝑥1, ..., 𝑥m, then

((antecedent → Ⅎ'𝑥 PHI), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PHI) ∖ {𝜑}})

is provable in S, with the same form of antecedent as above.

Proof: By induction on the height of PHI. We first note that by bj-nnfbi 36691 we can assume that PHI contains only primitive (as opposed to defined) symbols. For the base case, atomic formulas are either 𝜑, in which case the scheme to prove is an instance of id 22, or have variables all in OC(PHI) ∖ {𝜑}, so (Ⅎ'𝑥 PHI, {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PHI) ∖ {𝜑}}) by bj-nnfv 36720, hence ((Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ'𝑥 PHI), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PHI) ∖ {𝜑}}) by a1i 11. For the induction step, PHI is either an implication, a negation, a conjunction, a disjunction, a biconditional, a universal or an existential quantification of formulas where 𝑥 does not occur. We use respectively bj-nnfim 36712, bj-nnfnt 36706, bj-nnfan 36714, bj-nnfor 36716, bj-nnfbit 36718, bj-nnfalt 36732, bj-nnfext 36733. For instance, in the implication case, if we have by induction hypothesis

((∀𝑥1 ...∀𝑥m Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ'𝑥 PHI), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PHI) ∖ {𝜑}}) and ((∀𝑦1 ...∀𝑦n Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ'𝑥 PSI), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PSI) ∖ {𝜑}}),

then bj-nnfim 36712 yields

(((∀𝑥1 ...∀𝑥m Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦1 ...∀𝑦n Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑) → Ⅎ'𝑥 (PHI PSI)), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PHI PSI) ∖ {𝜑}})

and similarly for antecedents which are conjunctions as in the statement of the lemma.

In the universal quantification case, say quantification over 𝑦, if we have by induction hypothesis

((∀𝑥1 ...∀𝑥m Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ'𝑥 PHI), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PHI) ∖ {𝜑}}),

then bj-nnfalt 36732 yields

((∀𝑦𝑥1 ...∀𝑥m Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ'𝑥𝑦 PHI), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(𝑦 PHI) ∖ {𝜑}})

and similarly for antecedents which are conjunctions as in the statement of the lemma.

Note bj-nnfalt 36732 and bj-nnfext 36733 are proved from positive propositional calculus with alcom 2160 and excom 2163 (possibly weakened by a DV condition on the quantifying variables), and modalB (via bj-19.12 36727). QED

Proof of the theorem: Consider a proof of that scheme directly from the axioms. Consider a step where a DV condition involving 𝜑 is used. By hypothesis, that step is an instance of ax-5 1909 or ax5e 1911 or ax5ea 1912. It has the form (PSI → ∀𝑥 PSI) where PSI has the form of the lemma and the DV conditions of the proof contain {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PSI) }. Therefore, one has

((∀𝑥1 ...∀𝑥m Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ'𝑥 PSI), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PSI) ∖ {𝜑}})

for appropriate 𝑥i's, and by bj-nnfa 36694 we obtain

((∀𝑥1 ...∀𝑥m Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 (PSI → ∀𝑥 PSI)), {{𝑥, 𝑎} ∣ 𝑎 OC(PSI) ∖ {𝜑}})

and similarly for antecedents which are conjunctions as in the statement of the theorem. Similarly if the step is using ax5e 1911 or ax5ea 1912, we would use bj-nnfe 36697 or bj-nnfea 36700 respectively.

Therefore, taking as antecedent of the theorem to prove the conjunction of all the antecedents at each of these steps, we obtain a proof by "carrying the context over", which is possible, as in the deduction theorem when the step uses ax-mp 5, and when the step uses ax-gen 1793, by bj-nnf-alrim 36721 and bj-nnfa1 36725 (which requires modal 45). The condition DV (𝑥, 𝜑) is not required by the resulting proof.

Finally, there may be in the global antecedent thus constructed some dummy variables, which can be removed by spvw 1980. QED

Compared with df-nf 1782, the present definition is stricter on positive propositional calculus (bj-nnfnfTEMP 36704) and equivalent on core FOL plus sp 2184 (bj-nfnnfTEMP 36724). While being stricter, it still holds for non-occurring variables (bj-nnfv 36720), which is the basic requirement for this quantifier. In particular, it translates more closely the associated variable disjointness condition. Since the nonfreeness quantifier is a means to translate a variable disjointness condition from the metalogic to the logic, it seems preferable. Also, since nonfreeness is mainly used as a hypothesis, this definition would allow more theorems, notably the 19.xx theorems, to be proved from the core axioms, without needing a 19.xxv variant.

One can devise infinitely many definitions increasingly close to the non-occurring condition, like ((∃𝑥𝜑𝜑) ∧ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)) ∧ 𝑥((∃𝑥𝜑𝜑) ∧ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)) ∧ ∀𝑥𝑥... and each stronger definition would permit more theorems to be proved from the core axioms. A reasonable rule seems to be to stop before nested quantifiers appear (since they typically require ax-10 2141 to work with), and also not to have redundant conjuncts when full metacomplete FOL= is developed.

(Contributed by BJ, 28-Jul-2023.)

Assertion
Ref Expression
df-bj-nnf (Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 ↔ ((∃𝑥𝜑𝜑) ∧ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)))

Detailed syntax breakdown of Definition df-bj-nnf
StepHypRef Expression
1 wph . . 3 wff 𝜑
2 vx . . 3 setvar 𝑥
31, 2wnnf 36689 . 2 wff Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑
41, 2wex 1777 . . . 4 wff 𝑥𝜑
54, 1wi 4 . . 3 wff (∃𝑥𝜑𝜑)
61, 2wal 1535 . . . 4 wff 𝑥𝜑
71, 6wi 4 . . 3 wff (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)
85, 7wa 395 . 2 wff ((∃𝑥𝜑𝜑) ∧ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑))
93, 8wb 206 1 wff (Ⅎ'𝑥𝜑 ↔ ((∃𝑥𝜑𝜑) ∧ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)))
Colors of variables: wff setvar class
This definition is referenced by:  bj-nnfbi  36691  bj-nnfa  36694  bj-nnfe  36697  bj-dfnnf2  36703  bj-wnfnf  36705  bj-nnfnt  36706  bj-nnftht  36707  bj-nnfim  36712  bj-nnfan  36714  bj-nnfand  36715  bj-nnfor  36716  bj-nnford  36717  bj-nnfv  36720  bj-dfnnf3  36723  bj-nnfa1  36725  bj-nnfe1  36726  bj-nnfalt  36732  bj-nnfext  36733
  Copyright terms: Public domain W3C validator