MPE Home Metamath Proof Explorer < Previous   Next >
Nearby theorems
Mirrors  >  Home  >  MPE Home  >  Th. List  >  abid1 Structured version   Visualization version   GIF version

Theorem abid1 2881
Description: Every class is equal to a class abstraction (the class of sets belonging to it). Theorem 5.2 of [Quine] p. 35. This is a generalization to classes of cvjust 2734. The proof does not rely on cvjust 2734, so cvjust 2734 could be proved as a special instance of it. Note however that abid1 2881 necessarily relies on df-clel 2819, whereas cvjust 2734 does not.

This theorem requires ax-ext 2711, df-clab 2718, df-cleq 2732, df-clel 2819, but to prove that any specific class term not containing class variables is a setvar or is equal to a class abstraction does not require these $a-statements. This last fact is a metatheorem, consequence of the fact that the only $a-statements with typecode class are cv 1536, cab 2717, and statements corresponding to defined class constructors.

Note on the simultaneous presence in set.mm of this abid1 2881 and its commuted form abid2 2882: It is rare that two forms so closely related both appear in set.mm. Indeed, such equalities are generally used in later proofs as parts of transitive inferences, and with the many variants of eqtri 2768 (search for *eqtr*), it would be rare that either one would shorten a proof compared to the other. There is typically a choice between what we call a "definitional form", where the shorter expression is on the LHS (left-hand side), and a "computational form", where the shorter expression is on the RHS (right-hand side). An example is df-2 12356 versus 1p1e2 12418. We do not need 1p1e2 12418, but because it occurs "naturally" in computations, it can be useful to have it directly, together with a uniform set of 1-digit operations like 1p2e3 12436, etc. In most cases, we do not need both a definitional and a computational forms. A definitional form would favor consistency with genuine definitions, while a computational form is often more natural. The situation is similar with biconditionals in propositional calculus: see for instance pm4.24 563 and anidm 564, while other biconditionals generally appear in a single form (either definitional, but more often computational). In the present case, the equality is important enough that both abid1 2881 and abid2 2882 are in set.mm.

(Contributed by NM, 26-Dec-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 10-Nov-2020.)

Assertion
Ref Expression
abid1 𝐴 = {𝑥𝑥𝐴}
Distinct variable group:   𝑥,𝐴

Proof of Theorem abid1
StepHypRef Expression
1 biid 261 . 2 (𝑥𝐴𝑥𝐴)
21eqabi 2880 1 𝐴 = {𝑥𝑥𝐴}
Colors of variables: wff setvar class
Syntax hints:   = wceq 1537  wcel 2108  {cab 2717
This theorem was proved from axioms:  ax-mp 5  ax-1 6  ax-2 7  ax-3 8  ax-gen 1793  ax-4 1807  ax-5 1909  ax-6 1967  ax-7 2007  ax-8 2110  ax-9 2118  ax-ext 2711
This theorem depends on definitions:  df-bi 207  df-an 396  df-tru 1540  df-ex 1778  df-sb 2065  df-clab 2718  df-cleq 2732  df-clel 2819
This theorem is referenced by:  abid2  2882  eqab  2883  eqabb  2884  abssdv  4091  inrab2  4336  nsgqusf1olem2  33407  disjdmqscossss  38759  riotaclbgBAD  38910  ssabdv  42213  aomclem4  43014  limexissupab  43245
  Copyright terms: Public domain W3C validator