![]() |
Metamath Proof Explorer |
< Previous
Next >
Nearby theorems |
|
Mirrors > Home > MPE Home > Th. List > ru | Structured version Visualization version GIF version |
Description: Russell's Paradox.
Proposition 4.14 of [TakeutiZaring] p.
14.
In the late 1800s, Frege's Axiom of (unrestricted) Comprehension, expressed in our notation as 𝐴 ∈ V, asserted that any collection of sets 𝐴 is a set i.e. belongs to the universe V of all sets. In particular, by substituting {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} (the "Russell class") for 𝐴, it asserted {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} ∈ V, meaning that the "collection of all sets which are not members of themselves" is a set. However, here we prove {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} ∉ V. This contradiction was discovered by Russell in 1901 (published in 1903), invalidating the Comprehension Axiom and leading to the collapse of Frege's system, which Frege acknowledged in the second edition of his Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. In 1908, Zermelo rectified this fatal flaw by replacing Comprehension with a weaker Subset (or Separation) Axiom ssex 5318 asserting that 𝐴 is a set only when it is smaller than some other set 𝐵. However, Zermelo was then faced with a "chicken and egg" problem of how to show 𝐵 is a set, leading him to introduce the set-building axioms of Null Set 0ex 5304, Pairing prex 5430, Union uniex 7744, Power Set pwex 5376, and Infinity omex 9679 to give him some starting sets to work with (all of which, before Russell's Paradox, were immediate consequences of Frege's Comprehension). In 1922 Fraenkel strengthened the Subset Axiom with our present Replacement Axiom funimaex 6639 (whose modern formalization is due to Skolem, also in 1922). Thus, in a very real sense Russell's Paradox spawned the invention of ZF set theory and completely revised the foundations of mathematics! Another mainstream formalization of set theory, devised by von Neumann, Bernays, and Goedel, uses class variables rather than setvar variables as its primitives. The axiom system NBG in [Mendelson] p. 225 is suitable for a Metamath encoding. NBG is a conservative extension of ZF in that it proves exactly the same theorems as ZF that are expressible in the language of ZF. An advantage of NBG is that it is finitely axiomatizable - the Axiom of Replacement can be broken down into a finite set of formulas that eliminate its wff metavariable. Finite axiomatizability is required by some proof languages (although not by Metamath). There is a stronger version of NBG called Morse-Kelley (axiom system MK in [Mendelson] p. 287). Russell himself continued in a different direction, avoiding the paradox with his "theory of types". Quine extended Russell's ideas to formulate his New Foundations set theory (axiom system NF of [Quine] p. 331). In NF, the collection of all sets is a set, contrarily to ZF and NBG set theories. Russell's paradox has other consequences: when classes are too large (beyond the size of those used in standard mathematics), the axiom of choice ac4 10509 and Cantor's theorem canth 7369 are provably false. (See ncanth 7370 for some intuition behind the latter.) Recent results (as of 2014) seem to show that NF is equiconsistent to Z (ZF in which ax-sep 5296 replaces ax-rep 5282) with ax-sep 5296 restricted to only bounded quantifiers. NF is finitely axiomatizable and can be encoded in Metamath using the axioms from T. Hailperin, "A set of axioms for logic", J. Symb. Logic 9:1-19 (1944). Under our ZF set theory, every set is a member of the Russell class by elirrv 9632 (derived from the Axiom of Regularity), so for us the Russell class equals the universe V (Theorem ruv 9638). See ruALT 9639 for an alternate proof of ru 3773 derived from that fact. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) Remove use of ax-13 2366. (Revised by BJ, 12-Oct-2019.) Remove use of ax-10 2130, ax-11 2147, and ax-12 2167. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 20-Jun-2025.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
Ref | Expression |
---|---|
ru | ⊢ {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} ∉ V |
Step | Hyp | Ref | Expression |
---|---|---|---|
1 | pm5.19 385 | . . . . . 6 ⊢ ¬ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧) | |
2 | elequ1 2106 | . . . . . . . 8 ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧)) | |
3 | df-nel 3037 | . . . . . . . . 9 ⊢ (𝑦 ∉ 𝑦 ↔ ¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑦) | |
4 | id 22 | . . . . . . . . . . 11 ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → 𝑦 = 𝑧) | |
5 | 4, 4 | eleq12d 2820 | . . . . . . . . . 10 ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧)) |
6 | 5 | notbid 317 | . . . . . . . . 9 ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → (¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧)) |
7 | 3, 6 | bitrid 282 | . . . . . . . 8 ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → (𝑦 ∉ 𝑦 ↔ ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧)) |
8 | 2, 7 | bibi12d 344 | . . . . . . 7 ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → ((𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ 𝑦 ∉ 𝑦) ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧))) |
9 | 8 | spvv 1993 | . . . . . 6 ⊢ (∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ 𝑦 ∉ 𝑦) → (𝑧 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧)) |
10 | 1, 9 | mto 196 | . . . . 5 ⊢ ¬ ∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ 𝑦 ∉ 𝑦) |
11 | id 22 | . . . . . . 7 ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝑥 = 𝑦) | |
12 | 11, 11 | neleq12d 3041 | . . . . . 6 ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 ∉ 𝑥 ↔ 𝑦 ∉ 𝑦)) |
13 | 12 | eqabbw 2802 | . . . . 5 ⊢ (𝑧 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} ↔ ∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ 𝑦 ∉ 𝑦)) |
14 | 10, 13 | mtbir 322 | . . . 4 ⊢ ¬ 𝑧 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} |
15 | 14 | nex 1795 | . . 3 ⊢ ¬ ∃𝑧 𝑧 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} |
16 | isset 3476 | . . 3 ⊢ ({𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} ∈ V ↔ ∃𝑧 𝑧 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥}) | |
17 | 15, 16 | mtbir 322 | . 2 ⊢ ¬ {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} ∈ V |
18 | 17 | nelir 3039 | 1 ⊢ {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∉ 𝑥} ∉ V |
Colors of variables: wff setvar class |
Syntax hints: ¬ wn 3 ↔ wb 205 ∀wal 1532 = wceq 1534 ∃wex 1774 ∈ wcel 2099 {cab 2703 ∉ wnel 3036 Vcvv 3462 |
This theorem was proved from axioms: ax-mp 5 ax-1 6 ax-2 7 ax-3 8 ax-gen 1790 ax-4 1804 ax-5 1906 ax-6 1964 ax-7 2004 ax-8 2101 ax-9 2109 ax-ext 2697 |
This theorem depends on definitions: df-bi 206 df-an 395 df-tru 1537 df-ex 1775 df-sb 2061 df-clab 2704 df-cleq 2718 df-clel 2803 df-nel 3037 df-v 3464 |
This theorem is referenced by: (None) |
Copyright terms: Public domain | W3C validator |