Intuitionistic Logic Explorer |
< Previous
Next >
Nearby theorems |
||
Mirrors > Home > ILE Home > Th. List > 1kp2ke3k | GIF version |
Description: Example for df-dec 9331, 1000 + 2000 = 3000.
This proof disproves (by counterexample) the assertion of Hao Wang, who stated, "There is a theorem in the primitive notation of set theory that corresponds to the arithmetic theorem 1000 + 2000 = 3000. The formula would be forbiddingly long... even if (one) knows the definitions and is asked to simplify the long formula according to them, chances are he will make errors and arrive at some incorrect result." (Hao Wang, "Theory and practice in mathematics" , In Thomas Tymoczko, editor, New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics, pp 129-152, Birkauser Boston, Inc., Boston, 1986. (QA8.6.N48). The quote itself is on page 140.) This is noted in Metamath: A Computer Language for Pure Mathematics by Norman Megill (2007) section 1.1.3. Megill then states, "A number of writers have conveyed the impression that the kind of absolute rigor provided by Metamath is an impossible dream, suggesting that a complete, formal verification of a typical theorem would take millions of steps in untold volumes of books... These writers assume, however, that in order to achieve the kind of complete formal verification they desire one must break down a proof into individual primitive steps that make direct reference to the axioms. This is not necessary. There is no reason not to make use of previously proved theorems rather than proving them over and over... A hierarchy of theorems and definitions permits an exponential growth in the formula sizes and primitive proof steps to be described with only a linear growth in the number of symbols used. Of course, this is how ordinary informal mathematics is normally done anyway, but with Metamath it can be done with absolute rigor and precision." The proof here starts with (2 + 1) = 3, commutes it, and repeatedly multiplies both sides by ten. This is certainly longer than traditional mathematical proofs, e.g., there are a number of steps explicitly shown here to show that we're allowed to do operations such as multiplication. However, while longer, the proof is clearly a manageable size - even though every step is rigorously derived all the way back to the primitive notions of set theory and logic. And while there's a risk of making errors, the many independent verifiers make it much less likely that an incorrect result will be accepted. This proof heavily relies on the decimal constructor df-dec 9331 developed by Mario Carneiro in 2015. The underlying Metamath language has an intentionally very small set of primitives; it doesn't even have a built-in construct for numbers. Instead, the digits are defined using these primitives, and the decimal constructor is used to make it easy to express larger numbers as combinations of digits. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 29-Jun-2016.) (Shortened by Mario Carneiro using the arithmetic algorithm in mmj2, 30-Jun-2016.) |
Ref | Expression |
---|---|
1kp2ke3k | ⊢ (;;;1000 + ;;;2000) = ;;;3000 |
Step | Hyp | Ref | Expression |
---|---|---|---|
1 | 1nn0 9138 | . . . 4 ⊢ 1 ∈ ℕ0 | |
2 | 0nn0 9137 | . . . 4 ⊢ 0 ∈ ℕ0 | |
3 | 1, 2 | deccl 9344 | . . 3 ⊢ ;10 ∈ ℕ0 |
4 | 3, 2 | deccl 9344 | . 2 ⊢ ;;100 ∈ ℕ0 |
5 | 2nn0 9139 | . . . 4 ⊢ 2 ∈ ℕ0 | |
6 | 5, 2 | deccl 9344 | . . 3 ⊢ ;20 ∈ ℕ0 |
7 | 6, 2 | deccl 9344 | . 2 ⊢ ;;200 ∈ ℕ0 |
8 | eqid 2170 | . 2 ⊢ ;;;1000 = ;;;1000 | |
9 | eqid 2170 | . 2 ⊢ ;;;2000 = ;;;2000 | |
10 | eqid 2170 | . . 3 ⊢ ;;100 = ;;100 | |
11 | eqid 2170 | . . 3 ⊢ ;;200 = ;;200 | |
12 | eqid 2170 | . . . 4 ⊢ ;10 = ;10 | |
13 | eqid 2170 | . . . 4 ⊢ ;20 = ;20 | |
14 | 1p2e3 8999 | . . . 4 ⊢ (1 + 2) = 3 | |
15 | 00id 8047 | . . . 4 ⊢ (0 + 0) = 0 | |
16 | 1, 2, 5, 2, 12, 13, 14, 15 | decadd 9383 | . . 3 ⊢ (;10 + ;20) = ;30 |
17 | 3, 2, 6, 2, 10, 11, 16, 15 | decadd 9383 | . 2 ⊢ (;;100 + ;;200) = ;;300 |
18 | 4, 2, 7, 2, 8, 9, 17, 15 | decadd 9383 | 1 ⊢ (;;;1000 + ;;;2000) = ;;;3000 |
Colors of variables: wff set class |
Syntax hints: = wceq 1348 (class class class)co 5850 0cc0 7761 1c1 7762 + caddc 7764 2c2 8916 3c3 8917 ;cdc 9330 |
This theorem was proved from axioms: ax-mp 5 ax-1 6 ax-2 7 ax-ia1 105 ax-ia2 106 ax-ia3 107 ax-in1 609 ax-in2 610 ax-io 704 ax-5 1440 ax-7 1441 ax-gen 1442 ax-ie1 1486 ax-ie2 1487 ax-8 1497 ax-10 1498 ax-11 1499 ax-i12 1500 ax-bndl 1502 ax-4 1503 ax-17 1519 ax-i9 1523 ax-ial 1527 ax-i5r 1528 ax-14 2144 ax-ext 2152 ax-sep 4105 ax-pow 4158 ax-pr 4192 ax-setind 4519 ax-cnex 7852 ax-resscn 7853 ax-1cn 7854 ax-1re 7855 ax-icn 7856 ax-addcl 7857 ax-addrcl 7858 ax-mulcl 7859 ax-addcom 7861 ax-mulcom 7862 ax-addass 7863 ax-mulass 7864 ax-distr 7865 ax-i2m1 7866 ax-1rid 7868 ax-0id 7869 ax-rnegex 7870 ax-cnre 7872 |
This theorem depends on definitions: df-bi 116 df-3an 975 df-tru 1351 df-fal 1354 df-nf 1454 df-sb 1756 df-eu 2022 df-mo 2023 df-clab 2157 df-cleq 2163 df-clel 2166 df-nfc 2301 df-ne 2341 df-ral 2453 df-rex 2454 df-reu 2455 df-rab 2457 df-v 2732 df-sbc 2956 df-dif 3123 df-un 3125 df-in 3127 df-ss 3134 df-pw 3566 df-sn 3587 df-pr 3588 df-op 3590 df-uni 3795 df-int 3830 df-br 3988 df-opab 4049 df-id 4276 df-xp 4615 df-rel 4616 df-cnv 4617 df-co 4618 df-dm 4619 df-iota 5158 df-fun 5198 df-fv 5204 df-riota 5806 df-ov 5853 df-oprab 5854 df-mpo 5855 df-sub 8079 df-inn 8866 df-2 8924 df-3 8925 df-4 8926 df-5 8927 df-6 8928 df-7 8929 df-8 8930 df-9 8931 df-n0 9123 df-dec 9331 |
This theorem is referenced by: (None) |
Copyright terms: Public domain | W3C validator |