HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 15 of 129)
< Previous  Next >
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 1401-1500   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremalim 1401 Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 30-Mar-2008.)
 |-  ( A. x (
 ph  ->  ps )  ->  ( A. x ph  ->  A. x ps ) )
 
Theoremal2imi 1402 Inference quantifying antecedent, nested antecedent, and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  ch ) )   =>    |-  ( A. x ph 
 ->  ( A. x ps  ->  A. x ch )
 )
 
Theoremalanimi 1403 Variant of al2imi 1402 with conjunctive antecedent. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.)
 |-  ( ( ph  /\  ps )  ->  ch )   =>    |-  ( ( A. x ph 
 /\  A. x ps )  ->  A. x ch )
 
Syntaxwnf 1404 Extend wff definition to include the not-free predicate.
 wff  F/ x ph
 
Definitiondf-nf 1405 Define the not-free predicate for wffs. This is read " x is not free in  ph". Not-free means that the value of  x cannot affect the value of  ph, e.g., any occurrence of  x in  ph is effectively bound by a "for all" or something that expands to one (such as "there exists"). In particular, substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect its value (sbf 1718). An example of where this is used is stdpc5 1531. See nf2 1614 for an alternate definition which does not involve nested quantifiers on the same variable.

Not-free is a commonly used constraint, so it is useful to have a notation for it. Surprisingly, there is no common formal notation for it, so here we devise one. Our definition lets us work with the not-free notion within the logic itself rather than as a metalogical side condition.

To be precise, our definition really means "effectively not free," because it is slightly less restrictive than the usual textbook definition for not-free (which only considers syntactic freedom). For example,  x is effectively not free in the bare expression  x  =  x, even though  x would be considered free in the usual textbook definition, because the value of  x in the expression  x  =  x cannot affect the truth of the expression (and thus substitution will not change the result). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)

 |-  ( F/ x ph  <->  A. x ( ph  ->  A. x ph ) )
 
Theoremnfi 1406 Deduce that  x is not free in  ph from the definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   =>    |- 
 F/ x ph
 
Theoremhbth 1407 No variable is (effectively) free in a theorem.

This and later "hypothesis-building" lemmas, with labels starting "hb...", allow us to construct proofs of formulas of the form  |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph ) from smaller formulas of this form. These are useful for constructing hypotheses that state " x is (effectively) not free in  ph." (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

 |-  ph   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )
 
Theoremnfth 1408 No variable is (effectively) free in a theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |-  ph   =>    |- 
 F/ x ph
 
Theoremnfnth 1409 No variable is (effectively) free in a non-theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Dec-2016.)
 |- 
 -.  ph   =>    |- 
 F/ x ph
 
Theoremnftru 1410 The true constant has no free variables. (This can also be proven in one step with nfv 1476, but this proof does not use ax-17 1474.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x T.
 
Theoremalimdh 1411 Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  ch )
 )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  ( A. x ps  ->  A. x ch ) )
 
Theoremalbi 1412 Theorem 19.15 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x (
 ph 
 <->  ps )  ->  ( A. x ph  <->  A. x ps )
 )
 
Theoremalrimih 1413 Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ps )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ps )
 
Theoremalbii 1414 Inference adding universal quantifier to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.)
 |-  ( ph  <->  ps )   =>    |-  ( A. x ph  <->  A. x ps )
 
Theorem2albii 1415 Inference adding 2 universal quantifiers to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.)
 |-  ( ph  <->  ps )   =>    |-  ( A. x A. y ph  <->  A. x A. y ps )
 
Theoremhbxfrbi 1416 A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Jonathan Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.)
 |-  ( ph  <->  ps )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )
 
Theoremnfbii 1417 Equality theorem for not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |-  ( ph  <->  ps )   =>    |-  ( F/ x ph  <->  F/ x ps )
 
Theoremnfxfr 1418 A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |-  ( ph  <->  ps )   &    |-  F/ x ps   =>    |-  F/ x ph
 
Theoremnfxfrd 1419 A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
 |-  ( ph  <->  ps )   &    |-  ( ch  ->  F/ x ps )   =>    |-  ( ch  ->  F/ x ph )
 
Theoremalcoms 1420 Swap quantifiers in an antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x A. y ph  ->  ps )   =>    |-  ( A. y A. x ph  ->  ps )
 
Theoremhbal 1421 If  x is not free in  ph, it is not free in  A. y ph. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   =>    |-  ( A. y ph  ->  A. x A. y ph )
 
Theoremalcom 1422 Theorem 19.5 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x A. y ph  <->  A. y A. x ph )
 
Theoremalrimdh 1423 Deduction from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  ch ) )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ch )
 )
 
Theoremalbidh 1424 Formula-building rule for universal quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  <->  ch ) )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  (
 A. x ps  <->  A. x ch )
 )
 
Theorem19.26 1425 Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90. Also Theorem *10.22 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 119. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Jul-2014.)
 |-  ( A. x (
 ph  /\  ps )  <->  (
 A. x ph  /\  A. x ps ) )
 
Theorem19.26-2 1426 Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90 with two quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.)
 |-  ( A. x A. y ( ph  /\  ps ) 
 <->  ( A. x A. y ph  /\  A. x A. y ps ) )
 
Theorem19.26-3an 1427 Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90 with triple conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-2011.)
 |-  ( A. x (
 ph  /\  ps  /\  ch ) 
 <->  ( A. x ph  /\ 
 A. x ps  /\  A. x ch ) )
 
Theorem19.33 1428 Theorem 19.33 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( ( A. x ph 
 \/  A. x ps )  ->  A. x ( ph  \/  ps ) )
 
Theoremalrot3 1429 Theorem *11.21 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 160. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 24-May-2011.)
 |-  ( A. x A. y A. z ph  <->  A. y A. z A. x ph )
 
Theoremalrot4 1430 Rotate 4 universal quantifiers twice. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2005.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jun-2014.)
 |-  ( A. x A. y A. z A. w ph  <->  A. z A. w A. x A. y ph )
 
Theoremalbiim 1431 Split a biconditional and distribute quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x (
 ph 
 <->  ps )  <->  ( A. x ( ph  ->  ps )  /\  A. x ( ps 
 ->  ph ) ) )
 
Theorem2albiim 1432 Split a biconditional and distribute 2 quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.)
 |-  ( A. x A. y ( ph  <->  ps )  <->  ( A. x A. y ( ph  ->  ps )  /\  A. x A. y ( ps  ->  ph ) ) )
 
Theoremhband 1433 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hban 1494. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )
 )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ch  ->  A. x ch )
 )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  (
 ( ps  /\  ch )  ->  A. x ( ps 
 /\  ch ) ) )
 
Theoremhb3and 1434 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hb3an 1497. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )
 )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ch  ->  A. x ch )
 )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( th  ->  A. x th )
 )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  (
 ( ps  /\  ch  /\ 
 th )  ->  A. x ( ps  /\  ch  /\  th ) ) )
 
Theoremhbald 1435 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbal 1421. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. y ph )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ps ) )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  ( A. y ps  ->  A. x A. y ps ) )
 
Syntaxwex 1436 Extend wff definition to include the existential quantifier ("there exists").
 wff  E. x ph
 
Axiomax-ie1 1437  x is bound in  E. x ph. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
 |-  ( E. x ph  ->  A. x E. x ph )
 
Axiomax-ie2 1438 Define existential quantification.  E. x ph means "there exists at least one set  x such that  ph is true." One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
 |-  ( A. x ( ps  ->  A. x ps )  ->  ( A. x ( ph  ->  ps )  <->  ( E. x ph  ->  ps ) ) )
 
Theoremhbe1 1439  x is not free in  E. x ph. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( E. x ph  ->  A. x E. x ph )
 
Theoremnfe1 1440  x is not free in  E. x ph. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x E. x ph
 
Theorem19.23ht 1441 Closed form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2005.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( A. x ( ps  ->  A. x ps )  ->  ( A. x ( ph  ->  ps )  <->  ( E. x ph  ->  ps ) ) )
 
Theorem19.23h 1442 Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   =>    |-  ( A. x (
 ph  ->  ps )  <->  ( E. x ph 
 ->  ps ) )
 
Theoremalnex 1443 Theorem 19.7 of [Margaris] p. 89. To read this intuitionistically, think of it as "if  ph can be refuted for all 
x, then it is not possible to find an  x for which  ph holds" (and likewise for the converse). Comparing this with dfexdc 1445 illustrates that statements which look similar (to someone used to classical logic) can be different intuitionistically due to different placement of negations. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 1-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-May-2015.)
 |-  ( A. x  -.  ph  <->  -. 
 E. x ph )
 
Theoremnex 1444 Generalization rule for negated wff. (Contributed by NM, 18-May-1994.)
 |- 
 -.  ph   =>    |- 
 -.  E. x ph
 
Theoremdfexdc 1445 Defining  E. x ph given decidability. It is common in classical logic to define  E. x ph as  -.  A. x -.  ph but in intuitionistic logic without a decidability condition, that is only an implication not an equivalence, as seen at exalim 1446. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Mar-2018.)
 |-  (DECID 
 E. x ph  ->  ( E. x ph  <->  -.  A. x  -.  ph ) )
 
Theoremexalim 1446 One direction of a classical definition of existential quantification. One direction of Definition of [Margaris] p. 49. For a decidable proposition, this is an equivalence, as seen as dfexdc 1445. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Jul-2018.)
 |-  ( E. x ph  ->  -.  A. x  -.  ph )
 
1.3.2  Equality predicate (continued)

The equality predicate was introduced above in wceq 1299 for use by df-tru 1302. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it.

 
Theoremweq 1447 Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas using the equality predicate.

(Instead of introducing weq 1447 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wceq 1299. This lets us avoid overloading the  = connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically weq 1447 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wceq 1299. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "show proof weq /all" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.)

 wff  x  =  y
 
Syntaxwcel 1448 Extend wff definition to include the membership connective between classes.

(The purpose of introducing 
wff  A  e.  B here is to allow us to express i.e. "prove" the wel 1449 of predicate calculus in terms of the wceq 1299 of set theory, so that we don't "overload" the  e. connective with two syntax definitions. This is done to prevent ambiguity that would complicate some Metamath parsers. The class variables  A and  B are introduced temporarily for the purpose of this definition but otherwise not used in predicate calculus.)

 wff  A  e.  B
 
Theoremwel 1449 Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas with the epsilon (membership) predicate. This is read " x is an element of  y," " x is a member of  y," " x belongs to  y," or " y contains  x." Note: The phrase " y includes  x " means " x is a subset of  y;" to use it also for  x  e.  y, as some authors occasionally do, is poor form and causes confusion, according to George Boolos (1992 lecture at MIT).

This syntactical construction introduces a binary non-logical predicate symbol  e. (epsilon) into our predicate calculus. We will eventually use it for the membership predicate of set theory, but that is irrelevant at this point: the predicate calculus axioms for  e. apply to any arbitrary binary predicate symbol. "Non-logical" means that the predicate is presumed to have additional properties beyond the realm of predicate calculus, although these additional properties are not specified by predicate calculus itself but rather by the axioms of a theory (in our case set theory) added to predicate calculus. "Binary" means that the predicate has two arguments.

(Instead of introducing wel 1449 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wcel 1448. This lets us avoid overloading the  e. connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically wel 1449 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wcel 1448. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "show proof wel /all" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.)

 wff  x  e.  y
 
Axiomax-8 1450 Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. This is similar to, but not quite, a transitive law for equality (proved later as equtr 1653). Axiom scheme C8' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom C7 of [Monk2] p. 105.

Axioms ax-8 1450 through ax-16 1753 are the axioms having to do with equality, substitution, and logical properties of our binary predicate  e. (which later in set theory will mean "is a member of"). Note that all axioms except ax-16 1753 and ax-17 1474 are still valid even when  x,  y, and  z are replaced with the same variable because they do not have any distinct variable (Metamath's $d) restrictions. Distinct variable restrictions are required for ax-16 1753 and ax-17 1474 only. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

 |-  ( x  =  y 
 ->  ( x  =  z 
 ->  y  =  z
 ) )
 
Axiomax-10 1451 Axiom of Quantifier Substitution. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Appears as Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint).

The original version of this axiom was ax-10o 1662 ("o" for "old") and was replaced with this shorter ax-10 1451 in May 2008. The old axiom is proved from this one as theorem ax10o 1661. Conversely, this axiom is proved from ax-10o 1662 as theorem ax10 1663. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

 |-  ( A. x  x  =  y  ->  A. y  y  =  x )
 
Axiomax-11 1452 Axiom of Variable Substitution. One of the 5 equality axioms of predicate calculus. The final consequent  A. x ( x  =  y  ->  ph ) is a way of expressing " y substituted for  x in wff  ph " (cf. sb6 1825). It is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and Axiom C8 of [Monk2] p. 105, from which it can be proved by cases.

Variants of this axiom which are equivalent in classical logic but which have not been shown to be equivalent for intuitionistic logic are ax11v 1766, ax11v2 1759 and ax-11o 1762. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

 |-  ( x  =  y 
 ->  ( A. y ph  ->  A. x ( x  =  y  ->  ph )
 ) )
 
Axiomax-i12 1453 Axiom of Quantifier Introduction. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Informally, it says that whenever  z is distinct from  x and  y, and  x  =  y is true, then  x  =  y quantified with  z is also true. In other words,  z is irrelevant to the truth of 
x  =  y. Axiom scheme C9' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear in the literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by cases.

This axiom has been modified from the original ax-12 1457 for compatibility with intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)

 |-  ( A. z  z  =  x  \/  ( A. z  z  =  y  \/  A. z ( x  =  y  ->  A. z  x  =  y ) ) )
 
Axiomax-bndl 1454 Axiom of bundling. The general idea of this axiom is that two variables are either distinct or non-distinct. That idea could be expressed as  A. z z  =  x  \/  -.  A. z z  =  x. However, we instead choose an axiom which has many of the same consequences, but which is different with respect to a universe which contains only one object.  A. z
z  =  x holds if  z and  x are the same variable, likewise for  z and  y, and  A. x A. z ( x  =  y  ->  A. z
x  =  y ) holds if  z is distinct from the others (and the universe has at least two objects).

As with other statements of the form "x is decidable (either true or false)", this does not entail the full Law of the Excluded Middle (which is the proposition that all statements are decidable), but instead merely the assertion that particular kinds of statements are decidable (or in this case, an assertion similar to decidability).

This axiom implies ax-i12 1453 as can be seen at axi12 1462. Whether ax-bndl 1454 can be proved from the remaining axioms including ax-i12 1453 is not known.

The reason we call this "bundling" is that a statement without a distinct variable constraint "bundles" together two statements, one in which the two variables are the same and one in which they are different. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2018.)

 |-  ( A. z  z  =  x  \/  ( A. z  z  =  y  \/  A. x A. z ( x  =  y  ->  A. z  x  =  y ) ) )
 
Axiomax-4 1455 Axiom of Specialization. A quantified wff implies the wff without a quantifier (i.e. an instance, or special case, of the generalized wff). In other words if something is true for all  x, it is true for any specific  x (that would typically occur as a free variable in the wff substituted for  ph). (A free variable is one that does not occur in the scope of a quantifier:  x and  y are both free in  x  =  y, but only  x is free in  A. y x  =  y.) Axiom scheme C5' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom B5 of [Tarski] p. 67 (under his system S2, defined in the last paragraph on p. 77).

Note that the converse of this axiom does not hold in general, but a weaker inference form of the converse holds and is expressed as rule ax-gen 1393. Conditional forms of the converse are given by ax-12 1457, ax-16 1753, and ax-17 1474.

Unlike the more general textbook Axiom of Specialization, we cannot choose a variable different from  x for the special case. For use, that requires the assistance of equality axioms, and we deal with it later after we introduce the definition of proper substitution - see stdpc4 1716.

(Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

 |-  ( A. x ph  -> 
 ph )
 
Theoremsp 1456 Specialization. Another name for ax-4 1455. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-2008.)
 |-  ( A. x ph  -> 
 ph )
 
Theoremax-12 1457 Rederive the original version of the axiom from ax-i12 1453. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( -.  A. z  z  =  x  ->  ( -.  A. z  z  =  y  ->  ( x  =  y  ->  A. z  x  =  y ) ) )
 
Theoremax12or 1458 Another name for ax-i12 1453. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( A. z  z  =  x  \/  ( A. z  z  =  y  \/  A. z ( x  =  y  ->  A. z  x  =  y ) ) )
 
Axiomax-13 1459 Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms for a non-logical predicate in our predicate calculus with equality. It substitutes equal variables into the left-hand side of the  e. binary predicate. Axiom scheme C12' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It is a special case of Axiom B8 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski] p. 77. "Non-logical" means that the predicate is not a primitive of predicate calculus proper but instead is an extension to it. "Binary" means that the predicate has two arguments. In a system of predicate calculus with equality, like ours, equality is not usually considered to be a non-logical predicate. In systems of predicate calculus without equality, it typically would be. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( x  =  y 
 ->  ( x  e.  z  ->  y  e.  z ) )
 
Axiomax-14 1460 Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms for a non-logical predicate in our predicate calculus with equality. It substitutes equal variables into the right-hand side of the  e. binary predicate. Axiom scheme C13' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It is a special case of Axiom B8 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski] p. 77. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( x  =  y 
 ->  ( z  e.  x  ->  z  e.  y ) )
 
Theoremhbequid 1461 Bound-variable hypothesis builder for  x  =  x. This theorem tells us that any variable, including  x, is effectively not free in  x  =  x, even though  x is technically free according to the traditional definition of free variable. (The proof uses only ax-5 1391, ax-8 1450, ax-12 1457, and ax-gen 1393. This shows that this can be proved without ax-9 1479, even though the theorem equid 1645 cannot be. A shorter proof using ax-9 1479 is obtainable from equid 1645 and hbth 1407.) (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 23-Mar-2014.)
 |-  ( x  =  x 
 ->  A. y  x  =  x )
 
Theoremaxi12 1462 Proof that ax-i12 1453 follows from ax-bndl 1454. So that we can track which theorems rely on ax-bndl 1454, proofs should reference ax-i12 1453 rather than this theorem. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Aug-2018.) (New usage is discouraged). (Proof modification is discouraged.)
 |-  ( A. z  z  =  x  \/  ( A. z  z  =  y  \/  A. z ( x  =  y  ->  A. z  x  =  y ) ) )
 
Theoremalequcom 1463 Commutation law for identical variable specifiers. The antecedent and consequent are true when  x and  y are substituted with the same variable. Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x  x  =  y  ->  A. y  y  =  x )
 
Theoremalequcoms 1464 A commutation rule for identical variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x  x  =  y  ->  ph )   =>    |-  ( A. y  y  =  x  ->  ph )
 
Theoremnalequcoms 1465 A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( -.  A. x  x  =  y  ->  ph )   =>    |-  ( -.  A. y  y  =  x  ->  ph )
 
Theoremnfr 1466 Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Sep-2016.)
 |-  ( F/ x ph  ->  ( ph  ->  A. x ph ) )
 
Theoremnfri 1467 Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x ph   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )
 
Theoremnfrd 1468 Consequence of the definition of not-free in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  F/ x ps )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )
 )
 
Theoremalimd 1469 Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x ph   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  ch )
 )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  ( A. x ps  ->  A. x ch ) )
 
Theoremalrimi 1470 Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x ph   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ps )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ps )
 
Theoremnfd 1471 Deduce that  x is not free in  ps in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x ph   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ps ) )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  F/ x ps )
 
Theoremnfdh 1472 Deduce that  x is not free in  ps in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ps ) )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  F/ x ps )
 
Theoremnfrimi 1473 Moving an antecedent outside  F/. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Mar-2018.)
 |- 
 F/ x ph   &    |-  F/ x (
 ph  ->  ps )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  F/ x ps )
 
1.3.3  Axiom ax-17 - first use of the $d distinct variable statement
 
Axiomax-17 1474* Axiom to quantify a variable over a formula in which it does not occur. Axiom C5 in [Megill] p. 444 (p. 11 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom B6 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski] p. 77 and Axiom C5-1 of [Monk2] p. 113.

(Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )
 
Theorema17d 1475* ax-17 1474 with antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )
 )
 
Theoremnfv 1476* If  x is not present in  ph, then  x is not free in  ph. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x ph
 
Theoremnfvd 1477* nfv 1476 with antecedent. Useful in proofs of deduction versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders such as nfimd 1532. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  F/ x ps )
 
1.3.4  Introduce Axiom of Existence
 
Axiomax-i9 1478 Axiom of Existence. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. One thing this axiom tells us is that at least one thing exists (although ax-4 1455 and possibly others also tell us that, i.e. they are not valid in the empty domain of a "free logic"). In this form (not requiring that  x and  y be distinct) it was used in an axiom system of Tarski (see Axiom B7' in footnote 1 of [KalishMontague] p. 81.) Another name for this theorem is a9e 1642, which has additional remarks. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
 |- 
 E. x  x  =  y
 
Theoremax-9 1479 Derive ax-9 1479 from ax-i9 1478, the modified version for intuitionistic logic. Although ax-9 1479 does hold intuistionistically, in intuitionistic logic it is weaker than ax-i9 1478. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.)
 |- 
 -.  A. x  -.  x  =  y
 
Theoremequidqe 1480 equid 1645 with some quantification and negation without using ax-4 1455 or ax-17 1474. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 27-Feb-2014.)
 |- 
 -.  A. y  -.  x  =  x
 
Theoremax4sp1 1481 A special case of ax-4 1455 without using ax-4 1455 or ax-17 1474. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.)
 |-  ( A. y  -.  x  =  x  ->  -.  x  =  x )
 
1.3.5  Additional intuitionistic axioms
 
Axiomax-ial 1482  x is not free in  A. x ph. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
 |-  ( A. x ph  ->  A. x A. x ph )
 
Axiomax-i5r 1483 Axiom of quantifier collection. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
 |-  ( ( A. x ph 
 ->  A. x ps )  ->  A. x ( A. x ph  ->  ps )
 )
 
1.3.6  Predicate calculus including ax-4, without distinct variables
 
Theoremspi 1484 Inference reversing generalization (specialization). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |- 
 A. x ph   =>    |-  ph
 
Theoremsps 1485 Generalization of antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  ps )   =>    |-  ( A. x ph  ->  ps )
 
Theoremspsd 1486 Deduction generalizing antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 17-Aug-1994.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  ->  ch ) )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  (
 A. x ps  ->  ch ) )
 
Theoremnfbidf 1487 An equality theorem for effectively not free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x ph   &    |-  ( ph  ->  ( ps  <->  ch ) )   =>    |-  ( ph  ->  ( F/ x ps  <->  F/ x ch )
 )
 
Theoremhba1 1488  x is not free in  A. x ph. Example in Appendix in [Megill] p. 450 (p. 19 of the preprint). Also Lemma 22 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x ph  ->  A. x A. x ph )
 
Theoremnfa1 1489  x is not free in  A. x ph. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x A. x ph
 
Theorema5i 1490 Inference generalizing a consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( A. x ph  ->  ps )   =>    |-  ( A. x ph  ->  A. x ps )
 
Theoremnfnf1 1491  x is not free in  F/ x ph. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
 |- 
 F/ x F/ x ph
 
Theoremhbim 1492 If  x is not free in  ph and  ps, it is not free in  ( ph  ->  ps ). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 3-Mar-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   =>    |-  ( ( ph  ->  ps )  ->  A. x ( ph  ->  ps )
 )
 
Theoremhbor 1493 If  x is not free in  ph and  ps, it is not free in  ( ph  \/  ps ). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   =>    |-  ( ( ph  \/  ps )  ->  A. x ( ph  \/  ps )
 )
 
Theoremhban 1494 If  x is not free in  ph and  ps, it is not free in  ( ph  /\  ps ). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   =>    |-  ( ( ph  /\ 
 ps )  ->  A. x ( ph  /\  ps )
 )
 
Theoremhbbi 1495 If  x is not free in  ph and  ps, it is not free in  ( ph  <->  ps ). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   =>    |-  ( ( ph  <->  ps )  ->  A. x ( ph  <->  ps ) )
 
Theoremhb3or 1496 If  x is not free in  ph,  ps, and  ch, it is not free in  ( ph  \/  ps  \/  ch ). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   &    |-  ( ch  ->  A. x ch )   =>    |-  (
 ( ph  \/  ps  \/  ch )  ->  A. x (
 ph  \/  ps  \/  ch ) )
 
Theoremhb3an 1497 If  x is not free in  ph,  ps, and  ch, it is not free in  ( ph  /\  ps  /\  ch ). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   &    |-  ( ps  ->  A. x ps )   &    |-  ( ch  ->  A. x ch )   =>    |-  (
 ( ph  /\  ps  /\  ch )  ->  A. x (
 ph  /\  ps  /\  ch ) )
 
Theoremhba2 1498 Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.)
 |-  ( A. y A. x ph  ->  A. x A. y A. x ph )
 
Theoremhbia1 1499 Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.)
 |-  ( ( A. x ph 
 ->  A. x ps )  ->  A. x ( A. x ph  ->  A. x ps ) )
 
Theorem19.3h 1500 A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-May-2007.)
 |-  ( ph  ->  A. x ph )   =>    |-  ( A. x ph  <->  ph )
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12832
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >