Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 140 of 140) | < Previous Wrap > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | nconstwlpolem0 13901* | Lemma for nconstwlpo 13904. If all the terms of the series are zero, so is their sum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2024.) |
Theorem | nconstwlpolemgt0 13902* | Lemma for nconstwlpo 13904. If one of the terms of series is positive, so is the sum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2024.) |
Theorem | nconstwlpolem 13903* | Lemma for nconstwlpo 13904. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Jul-2024.) |
Theorem | nconstwlpo 13904* | Existence of a certain non-constant function from reals to integers implies WOmni (the Weak Limited Principle of Omniscience or WLPO). Based on Exercise 11.6(ii) of [HoTT], p. (varies). (Contributed by BJ and Jim Kingdon, 22-Jul-2024.) |
WOmni | ||
Theorem | neapmkvlem 13905* | Lemma for neapmkv 13906. The result, with a few hypotheses broken out for convenience. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2024.) |
# | ||
Theorem | neapmkv 13906* | If negated equality for real numbers implies apartness, Markov's Principle follows. Exercise 11.10 of [HoTT], p. (varies). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jun-2024.) |
# Markov | ||
Theorem | supfz 13907 | The supremum of a finite sequence of integers. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Oct-2022.) |
Theorem | inffz 13908 | The infimum of a finite sequence of integers. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Oct-2022.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | taupi 13909 | Relationship between and . This can be seen as connecting the ratio of a circle's circumference to its radius and the ratio of a circle's circumference to its diameter. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Feb-2019.) (Revised by AV, 1-Oct-2020.) |
Theorem | ax1hfs 13910 | Heyting's formal system Axiom #1 from [Heyting] p. 127. (Contributed by MM, 11-Aug-2018.) |
Theorem | dftest 13911 |
A proposition is testable iff its negative or double-negative is true.
See Chapter 2 [Moschovakis] p. 2.
We do not formally define testability with a new token, but instead use DECID before the formula in question. For example, DECID corresponds to " is testable". (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 13-Aug-2018.) For statements about testable propositions, search for the keyword "testable" in the comments of statements, for instance using the Metamath command "MM> SEARCH * "testable" / COMMENTS". (New usage is discouraged.) |
DECID | ||
These are definitions and proofs involving an experimental "allsome" quantifier (aka "all some"). In informal language, statements like "All Martians are green" imply that there is at least one Martian. But it's easy to mistranslate informal language into formal notations because similar statements like do not imply that is ever true, leading to vacuous truths. Some systems include a mechanism to counter this, e.g., PVS allows types to be appended with "+" to declare that they are nonempty. This section presents a different solution to the same problem. The "allsome" quantifier expressly includes the notion of both "all" and "there exists at least one" (aka some), and is defined to make it easier to more directly express both notions. The hope is that if a quantifier more directly expresses this concept, it will be used instead and reduce the risk of creating formal expressions that look okay but in fact are mistranslations. The term "allsome" was chosen because it's short, easy to say, and clearly hints at the two concepts it combines. I do not expect this to be used much in metamath, because in metamath there's a general policy of avoiding the use of new definitions unless there are very strong reasons to do so. Instead, my goal is to rigorously define this quantifier and demonstrate a few basic properties of it. The syntax allows two forms that look like they would be problematic, but they are fine. When applied to a top-level implication we allow ! , and when restricted (applied to a class) we allow ! . The first symbol after the setvar variable must always be if it is the form applied to a class, and since cannot begin a wff, it is unambiguous. The looks like it would be a problem because or might include implications, but any implication arrow within any wff must be surrounded by parentheses, so only the implication arrow of ! can follow the wff. The implication syntax would work fine without the parentheses, but I added the parentheses because it makes things clearer inside larger complex expressions, and it's also more consistent with the rest of the syntax. For more, see "The Allsome Quantifier" by David A. Wheeler at https://dwheeler.com/essays/allsome.html I hope that others will eventually agree that allsome is awesome. | ||
Syntax | walsi 13912 | Extend wff definition to include "all some" applied to a top-level implication, which means is true whenever is true, and there is at least least one where is true. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! | ||
Syntax | walsc 13913 | Extend wff definition to include "all some" applied to a class, which means is true for all in , and there is at least one in . (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! | ||
Definition | df-alsi 13914 | Define "all some" applied to a top-level implication, which means is true whenever is true and there is at least one where is true. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! | ||
Definition | df-alsc 13915 | Define "all some" applied to a class, which means is true for all in and there is at least one in . (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! | ||
Theorem | alsconv 13916 | There is an equivalence between the two "all some" forms. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 22-Oct-2018.) |
! ! | ||
Theorem | alsi1d 13917 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a top-level inference, you can extract the "for all" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! | ||
Theorem | alsi2d 13918 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a top-level inference, you can extract the "exists" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! | ||
Theorem | alsc1d 13919 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a class, you can extract the "for all" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! | ||
Theorem | alsc2d 13920 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a class, you can extract the "there exists" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
! |
< Previous Wrap > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Wrap > |