Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 16 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | ax12or 1501 | Alias for ax-i12 1500, to be used in place of it for labeling consistency. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Axiom | ax-bndl 1502 |
Axiom of bundling. The general idea of this axiom is that two variables
are either distinct or non-distinct. That idea could be expressed as
. However, we instead choose an axiom
which has many of the same consequences, but which is different with
respect to a universe which contains only one object. holds
if and are the same variable,
likewise for and ,
and
holds if is distinct from
the others (and the universe has at least two objects).
As with other statements of the form "x is decidable (either true or false)", this does not entail the full Law of the Excluded Middle (which is the proposition that all statements are decidable), but instead merely the assertion that particular kinds of statements are decidable (or in this case, an assertion similar to decidability). This axiom implies ax-i12 1500 as can be seen at axi12 1507. Whether ax-bndl 1502 can be proved from the remaining axioms including ax-i12 1500 is not known. The reason we call this "bundling" is that a statement without a distinct variable constraint "bundles" together two statements, one in which the two variables are the same and one in which they are different. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2018.) |
Axiom | ax-4 1503 |
Axiom of Specialization. A quantified wff implies the wff without a
quantifier (i.e. an instance, or special case, of the generalized wff).
In other words if something is true for all , it is true for any
specific (that
would typically occur as a free variable in the wff
substituted for ). (A free variable is one that does not occur in
the scope of a quantifier: and are both
free in ,
but only is free
in .) Axiom
scheme C5' in [Megill]
p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom B5 of [Tarski]
p. 67 (under his system S2, defined in the last paragraph on p. 77).
Note that the converse of this axiom does not hold in general, but a weaker inference form of the converse holds and is expressed as rule ax-gen 1442. Conditional forms of the converse are given by ax12 1505, ax-16 1807, and ax-17 1519. Unlike the more general textbook Axiom of Specialization, we cannot choose a variable different from for the special case. For use, that requires the assistance of equality axioms, and we deal with it later after we introduce the definition of proper substitution - see stdpc4 1768. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sp 1504 | Specialization. Another name for ax-4 1503. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-2008.) |
Theorem | ax12 1505 | Rederive the original version of the axiom from ax-i12 1500. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | hbequid 1506 |
Bound-variable hypothesis builder for
. This theorem tells
us
that any variable, including , is effectively not free in
, even though is technically free according to the
traditional definition of free variable.
The proof uses only ax-8 1497 and ax-i12 1500 on top of (the FOL analogue of) modal logic KT. This shows that this can be proved without ax-i9 1523, even though Theorem equid 1694 cannot. A shorter proof using ax-i9 1523 is obtainable from equid 1694 and hbth 1456. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 23-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | axi12 1507 | Proof that ax-i12 1500 follows from ax-bndl 1502. So that we can track which theorems rely on ax-bndl 1502, proofs should reference ax12or 1501 rather than this theorem. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Aug-2018.) (New usage is discouraged). (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
Theorem | alequcom 1508 | Commutation law for identical variable specifiers. The antecedent and consequent are true when and are substituted with the same variable. Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | alequcoms 1509 | A commutation rule for identical variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nalequcoms 1510 | A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | nfr 1511 | Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | nfri 1512 | Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | nfrd 1513 | Consequence of the definition of not-free in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | alimd 1514 | Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | alrimi 1515 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | nfd 1516 | Deduce that is not free in in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | nfdh 1517 | Deduce that is not free in in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | nfrimi 1518 | Moving an antecedent outside . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Mar-2018.) |
Axiom | ax-17 1519* |
Axiom to quantify a variable over a formula in which it does not occur.
Axiom C5 in [Megill] p. 444 (p. 11 of the
preprint). Also appears as
Axiom B6 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski]
p. 77 and Axiom C5-1 of
[Monk2] p. 113.
(Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | a17d 1520* | ax-17 1519 with antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) |
Theorem | nfv 1521* | If is not present in , then is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | nfvd 1522* | nfv 1521 with antecedent. Useful in proofs of deduction versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders such as nfimd 1578. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
Axiom | ax-i9 1523 | Axiom of Existence. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. One thing this axiom tells us is that at least one thing exists (although ax-4 1503 and possibly others also tell us that, i.e. they are not valid in the empty domain of a "free logic"). In this form (not requiring that and be distinct) it was used in an axiom system of Tarski (see Axiom B7' in footnote 1 of [KalishMontague] p. 81.) Another name for this theorem is a9e 1689, which has additional remarks. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
Theorem | ax-9 1524 | Derive ax-9 1524 from ax-i9 1523, the modified version for intuitionistic logic. Although ax-9 1524 does hold intuistionistically, in intuitionistic logic it is weaker than ax-i9 1523. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | equidqe 1525 | equid 1694 with some quantification and negation without using ax-4 1503 or ax-17 1519. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 27-Feb-2014.) |
Theorem | ax4sp1 1526 | A special case of ax-4 1503 without using ax-4 1503 or ax-17 1519. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) |
Axiom | ax-ial 1527 | is not free in . One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
Axiom | ax-i5r 1528 | Axiom of quantifier collection. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
Theorem | spi 1529 | Inference reversing generalization (specialization). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sps 1530 | Generalization of antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | spsd 1531 | Deduction generalizing antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 17-Aug-1994.) |
Theorem | nfbidf 1532 | An equality theorem for effectively not free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | hba1 1533 | is not free in . Example in Appendix in [Megill] p. 450 (p. 19 of the preprint). Also Lemma 22 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfa1 1534 | is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | axc4i 1535 | Inference version of 19.21 1576. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) |
Theorem | a5i 1536 | Inference generalizing a consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfnf1 1537 | is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | hbim 1538 | If is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 3-Mar-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | hbor 1539 | If is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | hban 1540 | If is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | hbbi 1541 | If is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | hb3or 1542 | If is not free in , , and , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
Theorem | hb3an 1543 | If is not free in , , and , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
Theorem | hba2 1544 | Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.) |
Theorem | hbia1 1545 | Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.) |
Theorem | 19.3h 1546 | A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-May-2007.) |
Theorem | 19.3 1547 | A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | 19.16 1548 | Theorem 19.16 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.17 1549 | Theorem 19.17 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.21h 1550 | Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as " is not free in ". New proofs should use 19.21 1576 instead. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | 19.21bi 1551 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.21bbi 1552 | Inference removing double quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 20-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | 19.27h 1553 | Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.27 1554 | Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.28h 1555 | Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.28 1556 | Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfan1 1557 | A closed form of nfan 1558. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | nfan 1558 | If is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | nf3an 1559 | If is not free in , , and , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | nford 1560 | If in a context is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Oct-2019.) |
Theorem | nfand 1561 | If in a context is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | nf3and 1562 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder nf3an 1559. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | hbim1 1563 | A closed form of hbim 1538. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfim1 1564 | A closed form of nfim 1565. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | nfim 1565 | If is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | hbimd 1566 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbim 1538. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | nfor 1567 | If is not free in and , it is not free in . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | hbbid 1568 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbbi 1541. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) |
Theorem | nfal 1569 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) Remove dependency on ax-4 1503. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 25-Aug-2024.) |
Theorem | nfnf 1570 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | nfalt 1571 | Closed form of nfal 1569. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfa2 1572 | Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | nfia1 1573 | Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | 19.21ht 1574 | Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | 19.21t 1575 | Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) |
Theorem | 19.21 1576 | Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as " is not free in ". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | stdpc5 1577 | An axiom scheme of standard predicate calculus that emulates Axiom 5 of [Mendelson] p. 69. The hypothesis can be thought of as emulating " is not free in ". With this definition, the meaning of "not free" is less restrictive than the usual textbook definition; for example would not (for us) be free in by nfequid 1695. This theorem scheme can be proved as a metatheorem of Mendelson's axiom system, even though it is slightly stronger than his Axiom 5. (Contributed by NM, 22-Sep-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 1-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | nfimd 1578 | If in a context is not free in and , then it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | aaanh 1579 | Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | aaan 1580 | Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfbid 1581 | If in a context is not free in and , then it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 29-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | nfbi 1582 | If is not free in and , then it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | 19.8a 1583 | If a wff is true, then it is true for at least one instance. Special case of Theorem 19.8 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.8ad 1584 | If a wff is true, it is true for at least one instance. Deduction form of 19.8a 1583. (Contributed by DAW, 13-Feb-2017.) |
Theorem | 19.23bi 1585 | Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | exlimih 1586 | Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
Theorem | exlimi 1587 | Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | exlimd2 1588 | Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. Similar to exlimdh 1589 but with one slightly different hypothesis. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | exlimdh 1589 | Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 28-Jan-1997.) |
Theorem | exlimd 1590 | Deduction from Theorem 19.9 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | exlimiv 1591* |
Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p.
90.
This inference, along with our many variants is used to implement a metatheorem called "Rule C" that is given in many logic textbooks. See, for example, Rule C in [Mendelson] p. 81, Rule C in [Margaris] p. 40, or Rule C in Hirst and Hirst's A Primer for Logic and Proof p. 59 (PDF p. 65) at http://www.mathsci.appstate.edu/~jlh/primer/hirst.pdf. In informal proofs, the statement "Let C be an element such that..." almost always means an implicit application of Rule C. In essence, Rule C states that if we can prove that some element exists satisfying a wff, i.e. where has free, then we can use C as a hypothesis for the proof where C is a new (ficticious) constant not appearing previously in the proof, nor in any axioms used, nor in the theorem to be proved. The purpose of Rule C is to get rid of the existential quantifier. We cannot do this in Metamath directly. Instead, we use the original (containing ) as an antecedent for the main part of the proof. We eventually arrive at where is the theorem to be proved and does not contain . Then we apply exlimiv 1591 to arrive at . Finally, we separately prove and detach it with modus ponens ax-mp 5 to arrive at the final theorem . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 25-Jul-2012.) |
Theorem | exim 1592 | Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | eximi 1593 | Inference adding existential quantifier to antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 2eximi 1594 | Inference adding 2 existential quantifiers to antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | eximii 1595 | Inference associated with eximi 1593. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | alinexa 1596 | A transformation of quantifiers and logical connectives. (Contributed by NM, 19-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | exbi 1597 | Theorem 19.18 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | exbii 1598 | Inference adding existential quantifier to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1994.) |
Theorem | 2exbii 1599 | Inference adding 2 existential quantifiers to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | 3exbii 1600 | Inference adding 3 existential quantifiers to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 2-May-1995.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |