Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 18 of 144) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | stdpc6 1701 | One of the two equality axioms of standard predicate calculus, called reflexivity of equality. (The other one is stdpc7 1768.) Axiom 6 of [Mendelson] p. 95. Mendelson doesn't say why he prepended the redundant quantifier, but it was probably to be compatible with free logic (which is valid in the empty domain). (Contributed by NM, 16-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | equcomi 1702 | Commutative law for equality. Lemma 7 of [Tarski] p. 69. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | ax6evr 1703* | A commuted form of a9ev 1695. The naming reflects how axioms were numbered in the Metamath Proof Explorer as of 2020 (a numbering which we eventually plan to adopt here too, but until this happens everywhere only some theorems will have it). (Contributed by BJ, 7-Dec-2020.) |
Theorem | equcom 1704 | Commutative law for equality. (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equcomd 1705 | Deduction form of equcom 1704, symmetry of equality. For the versions for classes, see eqcom 2177 and eqcomd 2181. (Contributed by BJ, 6-Oct-2019.) |
Theorem | equcoms 1706 | An inference commuting equality in antecedent. Used to eliminate the need for a syllogism. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equtr 1707 | A transitive law for equality. (Contributed by NM, 23-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equtrr 1708 | A transitive law for equality. Lemma L17 in [Megill] p. 446 (p. 14 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 23-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equtr2 1709 | A transitive law for equality. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | equequ1 1710 | An equivalence law for equality. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equequ2 1711 | An equivalence law for equality. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | ax11i 1712 | Inference that has ax-11 1504 (without ) as its conclusion and does not require ax-10 1503, ax-11 1504, or ax12 1510 for its proof. The hypotheses may be eliminable without one or more of these axioms in special cases. Proof similar to Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 20-May-2008.) |
Theorem | ax10o 1713 |
Show that ax-10o 1714 can be derived from ax-10 1503. An open problem is
whether this theorem can be derived from ax-10 1503 and the others when
ax-11 1504 is replaced with ax-11o 1821. See Theorem ax10 1715
for the
rederivation of ax-10 1503 from ax10o 1713.
Normally, ax10o 1713 should be used rather than ax-10o 1714, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-2008.) |
Axiom | ax-10o 1714 |
Axiom ax-10o 1714 ("o" for "old") was the
original version of ax-10 1503,
before it was discovered (in May 2008) that the shorter ax-10 1503 could
replace it. It appears as Axiom scheme C11' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of
the preprint).
This axiom is redundant, as shown by Theorem ax10o 1713. Normally, ax10o 1713 should be used rather than ax-10o 1714, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | ax10 1715 |
Rederivation of ax-10 1503 from original version ax-10o 1714. See Theorem
ax10o 1713 for the derivation of ax-10o 1714 from ax-10 1503.
This theorem should not be referenced in any proof. Instead, use ax-10 1503 above so that uses of ax-10 1503 can be more easily identified. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | hbae 1716 | All variables are effectively bound in an identical variable specifier. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | nfae 1717 | All variables are effectively bound in an identical variable specifier. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | hbaes 1718 | Rule that applies hbae 1716 to antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | hbnae 1719 | All variables are effectively bound in a distinct variable specifier. Lemma L19 in [Megill] p. 446 (p. 14 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfnae 1720 | All variables are effectively bound in a distinct variable specifier. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | hbnaes 1721 | Rule that applies hbnae 1719 to antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | naecoms 1722 | A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
Theorem | equs4 1723 | Lemma used in proofs of substitution properties. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2014.) |
Theorem | equsalh 1724 | A useful equivalence related to substitution. New proofs should use equsal 1725 instead. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | equsal 1725 | A useful equivalence related to substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 5-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | equsex 1726 | A useful equivalence related to substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | equsexd 1727 | Deduction form of equsex 1726. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | dral1 1728 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | dral2 1729 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | drex2 1730 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | drnf1 1731 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | drnf2 1732 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | spimth 1733 | Closed theorem form of spim 1736. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jan-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | spimt 1734 | Closed theorem form of spim 1736. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jan-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 24-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | spimh 1735 | Specialization, using implicit substitition. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. The spim 1736 series of theorems requires that only one direction of the substitution hypothesis hold. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 8-May-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | spim 1736 | Specialization, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. The spim 1736 series of theorems requires that only one direction of the substitution hypothesis hold. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 10-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | spimeh 1737 | Existential introduction, using implicit substitition. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | spimed 1738 | Deduction version of spime 1739. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | spime 1739 | Existential introduction, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv3 1740 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because proofs are encouraged to use the weaker cbv3v 1742 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | cbv3h 1741 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv3v 1742* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbv3 1740 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | cbv1 1743 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Revised to format hypotheses to common style. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv1h 1744 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv1v 1745* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 16-Jun-2019.) |
Theorem | cbv2h 1746 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | cbv2 1747 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Revised to align format of hypotheses to common style. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv2w 1748* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbv2 1747 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Gino Giotto, 10-Jan-2024.) |
Theorem | cbvalv1 1749* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbval 1752 with a disjoint variable condition. See cbvalvw 1917 for a version with two disjoint variable conditions, and cbvalv 1915 for another variant. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | cbvexv1 1750* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbvex 1754 with a disjoint variable condition. See cbvexvw 1918 for a version with two disjoint variable conditions, and cbvexv 1916 for another variant. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | cbvalh 1751 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | cbval 1752 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | cbvexh 1753 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | cbvex 1754 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | chvar 1755 | Implicit substitution of for into a theorem. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 9-Jul-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | equvini 1756 | A variable introduction law for equality. Lemma 15 of [Monk2] p. 109, however we do not require to be distinct from and (making the proof longer). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | equveli 1757 | A variable elimination law for equality with no distinct variable requirements. (Compare equvini 1756.) (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | nfald 1758 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | nfexd 1759 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 7-Feb-2018.) |
Syntax | wsb 1760 | Extend wff definition to include proper substitution (read "the wff that results when is properly substituted for in wff "). (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.) |
Definition | df-sb 1761 |
Define proper substitution. Remark 9.1 in [Megill] p. 447 (p. 15 of the
preprint). For our notation, we use to mean "the wff
that results when
is properly substituted for in the wff
". We
can also use in
place of the "free for"
side condition used in traditional predicate calculus; see, for example,
stdpc4 1773.
Our notation was introduced in Haskell B. Curry's Foundations of Mathematical Logic (1977), p. 316 and is frequently used in textbooks of lambda calculus and combinatory logic. This notation improves the common but ambiguous notation, " is the wff that results when is properly substituted for in ". For example, if the original is , then is , from which we obtain that is . So what exactly does mean? Curry's notation solves this problem. In most books, proper substitution has a somewhat complicated recursive definition with multiple cases based on the occurrences of free and bound variables in the wff. Instead, we use a single formula that is exactly equivalent and gives us a direct definition. We later prove that our definition has the properties we expect of proper substitution (see Theorems sbequ 1838, sbcom2 1985 and sbid2v 1994). Note that our definition is valid even when and are replaced with the same variable, as sbid 1772 shows. We achieve this by having free in the first conjunct and bound in the second. We can also achieve this by using a dummy variable, as the alternate definition dfsb7 1989 shows (which some logicians may prefer because it doesn't mix free and bound variables). Another alternate definition which uses a dummy variable is dfsb7a 1992. When and are distinct, we can express proper substitution with the simpler expressions of sb5 1885 and sb6 1884. In classical logic, another possible definition is but we do not have an intuitionistic proof that this is equivalent. There are no restrictions on any of the variables, including what variables may occur in wff . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbimi 1762 | Infer substitution into antecedent and consequent of an implication. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jun-1998.) |
Theorem | sbbii 1763 | Infer substitution into both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sb1 1764 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sb2 1765 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbequ1 1766 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbequ2 1767 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | stdpc7 1768 | One of the two equality axioms of standard predicate calculus, called substitutivity of equality. (The other one is stdpc6 1701.) Translated to traditional notation, it can be read: " , , , provided that is free for in , ". Axiom 7 of [Mendelson] p. 95. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | sbequ12 1769 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbequ12r 1770 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 6-Oct-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | sbequ12a 1771 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbid 1772 | An identity theorem for substitution. Remark 9.1 in [Megill] p. 447 (p. 15 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | stdpc4 1773 | The specialization axiom of standard predicate calculus. It states that if a statement holds for all , then it also holds for the specific case of (properly) substituted for . Translated to traditional notation, it can be read: " , provided that is free for in ". Axiom 4 of [Mendelson] p. 69. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbh 1774 | Substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect it. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 17-Oct-2004.) |
Theorem | sbf 1775 | Substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect it. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sbf2 1776 | Substitution has no effect on a bound variable. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jul-2005.) |
Theorem | sb6x 1777 | Equivalence involving substitution for a variable not free. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | nfs1f 1778 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | hbs1f 1779 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | sbequ5 1780 | Substitution does not change an identical variable specifier. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-Dec-2004.) |
Theorem | sbequ6 1781 | Substitution does not change a distinctor. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 14-May-2005.) |
Theorem | sbt 1782 | A substitution into a theorem remains true. (See chvar 1755 and chvarv 1935 for versions using implicit substitition.) (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | equsb1 1783 | Substitution applied to an atomic wff. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equsb2 1784 | Substitution applied to an atomic wff. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbiedh 1785 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbieh 1788). New proofs should use sbied 1786 instead. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | sbied 1786 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbie 1789). (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sbiedv 1787* | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbie 1789). (Contributed by NM, 7-Jan-2017.) |
Theorem | sbieh 1788 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. New proofs should use sbie 1789 instead. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | sbie 1789 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 30-Apr-2018.) |
Theorem | sbiev 1790* | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. Version of sbie 1789 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 18-Jan-2023.) |
Theorem | equsalv 1791* | An equivalence related to implicit substitution. Version of equsal 1725 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jun-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | equs5a 1792 | A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 1827 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | equs5e 1793 | A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 1827 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | ax11e 1794 | Analogue to ax-11 1504 but for existential quantification. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 31-Dec-2017.) (Proved by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | ax10oe 1795 | Quantifier Substitution for existential quantifiers. Analogue to ax10o 1713 but for rather than . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | drex1 1796 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | drsb1 1797 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | exdistrfor 1798 | Distribution of existential quantifiers, with a bound-variable hypothesis saying that is not free in , but can be free in (and there is no distinct variable condition on and ). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sb4a 1799 | A version of sb4 1830 that doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | equs45f 1800 | Two ways of expressing substitution when is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-2008.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |