Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 18 of 140) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | equequ2 1701 | An equivalence law for equality. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | ax11i 1702 | Inference that has ax-11 1494 (without ) as its conclusion and does not require ax-10 1493, ax-11 1494, or ax12 1500 for its proof. The hypotheses may be eliminable without one or more of these axioms in special cases. Proof similar to Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 20-May-2008.) |
Theorem | ax10o 1703 |
Show that ax-10o 1704 can be derived from ax-10 1493. An open problem is
whether this theorem can be derived from ax-10 1493 and the others when
ax-11 1494 is replaced with ax-11o 1811. See Theorem ax10 1705
for the
rederivation of ax-10 1493 from ax10o 1703.
Normally, ax10o 1703 should be used rather than ax-10o 1704, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-2008.) |
Axiom | ax-10o 1704 |
Axiom ax-10o 1704 ("o" for "old") was the
original version of ax-10 1493,
before it was discovered (in May 2008) that the shorter ax-10 1493 could
replace it. It appears as Axiom scheme C11' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of
the preprint).
This axiom is redundant, as shown by Theorem ax10o 1703. Normally, ax10o 1703 should be used rather than ax-10o 1704, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | ax10 1705 |
Rederivation of ax-10 1493 from original version ax-10o 1704. See Theorem
ax10o 1703 for the derivation of ax-10o 1704 from ax-10 1493.
This theorem should not be referenced in any proof. Instead, use ax-10 1493 above so that uses of ax-10 1493 can be more easily identified. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | hbae 1706 | All variables are effectively bound in an identical variable specifier. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | nfae 1707 | All variables are effectively bound in an identical variable specifier. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | hbaes 1708 | Rule that applies hbae 1706 to antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | hbnae 1709 | All variables are effectively bound in a distinct variable specifier. Lemma L19 in [Megill] p. 446 (p. 14 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfnae 1710 | All variables are effectively bound in a distinct variable specifier. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | hbnaes 1711 | Rule that applies hbnae 1709 to antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | naecoms 1712 | A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
Theorem | equs4 1713 | Lemma used in proofs of substitution properties. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2014.) |
Theorem | equsalh 1714 | A useful equivalence related to substitution. New proofs should use equsal 1715 instead. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | equsal 1715 | A useful equivalence related to substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 5-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | equsex 1716 | A useful equivalence related to substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | equsexd 1717 | Deduction form of equsex 1716. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | dral1 1718 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | dral2 1719 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | drex2 1720 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | drnf1 1721 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | drnf2 1722 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | spimth 1723 | Closed theorem form of spim 1726. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jan-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | spimt 1724 | Closed theorem form of spim 1726. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jan-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 24-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | spimh 1725 | Specialization, using implicit substitition. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. The spim 1726 series of theorems requires that only one direction of the substitution hypothesis hold. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 8-May-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | spim 1726 | Specialization, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. The spim 1726 series of theorems requires that only one direction of the substitution hypothesis hold. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 10-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | spimeh 1727 | Existential introduction, using implicit substitition. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | spimed 1728 | Deduction version of spime 1729. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | spime 1729 | Existential introduction, using implicit substitution. Compare Lemma 14 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv3 1730 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because proofs are encouraged to use the weaker cbv3v 1732 if possible. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | cbv3h 1731 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv3v 1732* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbv3 1730 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | cbv1 1733 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Revised to format hypotheses to common style. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv1h 1734 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv1v 1735* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 16-Jun-2019.) |
Theorem | cbv2h 1736 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | cbv2 1737 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Revised to align format of hypotheses to common style. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2018.) |
Theorem | cbv2w 1738* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbv2 1737 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Gino Giotto, 10-Jan-2024.) |
Theorem | cbvalv1 1739* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbval 1742 with a disjoint variable condition. See cbvalvw 1907 for a version with two disjoint variable conditions, and cbvalv 1905 for another variant. (Contributed by NM, 13-May-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | cbvexv1 1740* | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. Version of cbvex 1744 with a disjoint variable condition. See cbvexvw 1908 for a version with two disjoint variable conditions, and cbvexv 1906 for another variant. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | cbvalh 1741 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | cbval 1742 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | cbvexh 1743 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | cbvex 1744 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | chvar 1745 | Implicit substitution of for into a theorem. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 9-Jul-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | equvini 1746 | A variable introduction law for equality. Lemma 15 of [Monk2] p. 109, however we do not require to be distinct from and (making the proof longer). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | equveli 1747 | A variable elimination law for equality with no distinct variable requirements. (Compare equvini 1746.) (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | nfald 1748 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | nfexd 1749 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 7-Feb-2018.) |
Syntax | wsb 1750 | Extend wff definition to include proper substitution (read "the wff that results when is properly substituted for in wff "). (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.) |
Definition | df-sb 1751 |
Define proper substitution. Remark 9.1 in [Megill] p. 447 (p. 15 of the
preprint). For our notation, we use to mean "the wff
that results when
is properly substituted for in the wff
". We
can also use in
place of the "free for"
side condition used in traditional predicate calculus; see, for example,
stdpc4 1763.
Our notation was introduced in Haskell B. Curry's Foundations of Mathematical Logic (1977), p. 316 and is frequently used in textbooks of lambda calculus and combinatory logic. This notation improves the common but ambiguous notation, " is the wff that results when is properly substituted for in ". For example, if the original is , then is , from which we obtain that is . So what exactly does mean? Curry's notation solves this problem. In most books, proper substitution has a somewhat complicated recursive definition with multiple cases based on the occurrences of free and bound variables in the wff. Instead, we use a single formula that is exactly equivalent and gives us a direct definition. We later prove that our definition has the properties we expect of proper substitution (see Theorems sbequ 1828, sbcom2 1975 and sbid2v 1984). Note that our definition is valid even when and are replaced with the same variable, as sbid 1762 shows. We achieve this by having free in the first conjunct and bound in the second. We can also achieve this by using a dummy variable, as the alternate definition dfsb7 1979 shows (which some logicians may prefer because it doesn't mix free and bound variables). Another alternate definition which uses a dummy variable is dfsb7a 1982. When and are distinct, we can express proper substitution with the simpler expressions of sb5 1875 and sb6 1874. In classical logic, another possible definition is but we do not have an intuitionistic proof that this is equivalent. There are no restrictions on any of the variables, including what variables may occur in wff . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbimi 1752 | Infer substitution into antecedent and consequent of an implication. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jun-1998.) |
Theorem | sbbii 1753 | Infer substitution into both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sb1 1754 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sb2 1755 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbequ1 1756 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbequ2 1757 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | stdpc7 1758 | One of the two equality axioms of standard predicate calculus, called substitutivity of equality. (The other one is stdpc6 1691.) Translated to traditional notation, it can be read: " , , , provided that is free for in , ". Axiom 7 of [Mendelson] p. 95. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | sbequ12 1759 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbequ12r 1760 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 6-Oct-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | sbequ12a 1761 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbid 1762 | An identity theorem for substitution. Remark 9.1 in [Megill] p. 447 (p. 15 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | stdpc4 1763 | The specialization axiom of standard predicate calculus. It states that if a statement holds for all , then it also holds for the specific case of (properly) substituted for . Translated to traditional notation, it can be read: " , provided that is free for in ". Axiom 4 of [Mendelson] p. 69. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbh 1764 | Substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect it. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 17-Oct-2004.) |
Theorem | sbf 1765 | Substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect it. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sbf2 1766 | Substitution has no effect on a bound variable. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jul-2005.) |
Theorem | sb6x 1767 | Equivalence involving substitution for a variable not free. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | nfs1f 1768 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | hbs1f 1769 | If is not free in , it is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | sbequ5 1770 | Substitution does not change an identical variable specifier. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-Dec-2004.) |
Theorem | sbequ6 1771 | Substitution does not change a distinctor. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 14-May-2005.) |
Theorem | sbt 1772 | A substitution into a theorem remains true. (See chvar 1745 and chvarv 1925 for versions using implicit substitition.) (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | equsb1 1773 | Substitution applied to an atomic wff. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equsb2 1774 | Substitution applied to an atomic wff. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbiedh 1775 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbieh 1778). New proofs should use sbied 1776 instead. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | sbied 1776 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbie 1779). (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sbiedv 1777* | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution (deduction version of sbie 1779). (Contributed by NM, 7-Jan-2017.) |
Theorem | sbieh 1778 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. New proofs should use sbie 1779 instead. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | sbie 1779 | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 30-Apr-2018.) |
Theorem | sbiev 1780* | Conversion of implicit substitution to explicit substitution. Version of sbie 1779 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 18-Jan-2023.) |
Theorem | equsalv 1781* | An equivalence related to implicit substitution. Version of equsal 1715 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jun-1993.) (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
Theorem | equs5a 1782 | A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 1817 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | equs5e 1783 | A property related to substitution that unlike equs5 1817 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | ax11e 1784 | Analogue to ax-11 1494 but for existential quantification. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 31-Dec-2017.) (Proved by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | ax10oe 1785 | Quantifier Substitution for existential quantifiers. Analogue to ax10o 1703 but for rather than . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | drex1 1786 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) (Revised by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
Theorem | drsb1 1787 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | exdistrfor 1788 | Distribution of existential quantifiers, with a bound-variable hypothesis saying that is not free in , but can be free in (and there is no distinct variable condition on and ). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sb4a 1789 | A version of sb4 1820 that doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | equs45f 1790 | Two ways of expressing substitution when is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-2008.) |
Theorem | sb6f 1791 | Equivalence for substitution when is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 30-Apr-2008.) |
Theorem | sb5f 1792 | Equivalence for substitution when is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 18-May-2008.) |
Theorem | sb4e 1793 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution that unlike sb4 1820 doesn't require a distinctor antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | hbsb2a 1794 | Special case of a bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | hbsb2e 1795 | Special case of a bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | hbsb3 1796 | If is not free in , is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfs1 1797 | If is not free in , is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | sbcof2 1798 | Version of sbco 1956 where is not free in . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | spimv 1799* | A version of spim 1726 with a distinct variable requirement instead of a bound-variable hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | aev 1800* | A "distinctor elimination" lemma with no restrictions on variables in the consequent, proved without using ax-16 1802. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2006.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jun-2011.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |