Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 15 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | truorfal 1401 | A ∨ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ∨ ⊥) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | falortru 1402 | A ∨ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ∨ ⊤) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | falorfal 1403 | A ∨ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ∨ ⊥) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | truimtru 1404 | A → identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊤ → ⊤) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | truimfal 1405 | A → identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ ((⊤ → ⊥) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | falimtru 1406 | A → identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊥ → ⊤) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | falimfal 1407 | A → identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊥ → ⊥) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | nottru 1408 | A ¬ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ (¬ ⊤ ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | notfal 1409 | A ¬ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ (¬ ⊥ ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | trubitru 1410 | A ↔ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ↔ ⊤) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | trubifal 1411 | A ↔ identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 23-Feb-2018.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ↔ ⊥) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | falbitru 1412 | A ↔ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ↔ ⊤) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | falbifal 1413 | A ↔ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ↔ ⊥) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | truxortru 1414 | A ⊻ identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ⊻ ⊤) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | truxorfal 1415 | A ⊻ identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ⊻ ⊥) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | falxortru 1416 | A ⊻ identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ⊻ ⊤) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | falxorfal 1417 | A ⊻ identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ⊻ ⊥) ↔ ⊥) | ||
The Greek Stoics developed a system of logic. The Stoic Chrysippus, in particular, was often considered one of the greatest logicians of antiquity. Stoic logic is different from Aristotle's system, since it focuses on propositional logic, though later thinkers did combine the systems of the Stoics with Aristotle. Jan Lukasiewicz reports, "For anybody familiar with mathematical logic it is self-evident that the Stoic dialectic is the ancient form of modern propositional logic" ( On the history of the logic of proposition by Jan Lukasiewicz (1934), translated in: Selected Works - Edited by Ludwik Borkowski - Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1970 pp. 197-217, referenced in "History of Logic" https://www.historyoflogic.com/logic-stoics.htm). For more about Aristotle's system, see barbara and related theorems. A key part of the Stoic logic system is a set of five "indemonstrables" assigned to Chrysippus of Soli by Diogenes Laertius, though in general it is difficult to assign specific ideas to specific thinkers. The indemonstrables are described in, for example, [Lopez-Astorga] p. 11 , [Sanford] p. 39, and [Hitchcock] p. 5. These indemonstrables are modus ponendo ponens (modus ponens) ax-mp 5, modus tollendo tollens (modus tollens) mto 657, modus ponendo tollens I mptnan 1418, modus ponendo tollens II mptxor 1419, and modus tollendo ponens (exclusive-or version) mtpxor 1421. The first is an axiom, the second is already proved; in this section we prove the other three. Since we assume or prove all of indemonstrables, the system of logic we use here is as at least as strong as the set of Stoic indemonstrables. Note that modus tollendo ponens mtpxor 1421 originally used exclusive-or, but over time the name modus tollendo ponens has increasingly referred to an inclusive-or variation, which is proved in mtpor 1420. This set of indemonstrables is not the entire system of Stoic logic. | ||
Theorem | mptnan 1418 | Modus ponendo tollens 1, one of the "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. See rule 1 on [Lopez-Astorga] p. 12 , rule 1 on [Sanford] p. 40, and rule A3 in [Hitchcock] p. 5. Sanford describes this rule second (after mptxor 1419) as a "safer, and these days much more common" version of modus ponendo tollens because it avoids confusion between inclusive-or and exclusive-or. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 3-Jul-2016.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ¬ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | mptxor 1419 | Modus ponendo tollens 2, one of the "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. Note that this uses exclusive-or ⊻. See rule 2 on [Lopez-Astorga] p. 12 , rule 4 on [Sanford] p. 39 and rule A4 in [Hitchcock] p. 5 . (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ¬ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | mtpor 1420 | Modus tollendo ponens (inclusive-or version), aka disjunctive syllogism. This is similar to mtpxor 1421, one of the five original "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. However, in Stoic logic this rule used exclusive-or, while the name modus tollendo ponens often refers to a variant of the rule that uses inclusive-or instead. The rule says, "if 𝜑 is not true, and 𝜑 or 𝜓 (or both) are true, then 𝜓 must be true". An alternate phrasing is, "Once you eliminate the impossible, whatever remains, no matter how improbable, must be the truth". -- Sherlock Holmes (Sir Arthur Conan Doyle, 1890: The Sign of the Four, ch. 6). (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 3-Jul-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | mtpxor 1421 | Modus tollendo ponens (original exclusive-or version), aka disjunctive syllogism, similar to mtpor 1420, one of the five "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. The rule says, "if 𝜑 is not true, and either 𝜑 or 𝜓 (exclusively) are true, then 𝜓 must be true". Today the name "modus tollendo ponens" often refers to a variant, the inclusive-or version as defined in mtpor 1420. See rule 3 on [Lopez-Astorga] p. 12 (note that the "or" is the same as mptxor 1419, that is, it is exclusive-or df-xor 1371), rule 3 of [Sanford] p. 39 (where it is not as clearly stated which kind of "or" is used but it appears to be in the same sense as mptxor 1419), and rule A5 in [Hitchcock] p. 5 (exclusive-or is expressly used). (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 4-Jul-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Nov-2017.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 19-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | stoic2a 1422 |
Stoic logic Thema 2 version a.
Statement T2 of [Bobzien] p. 117 shows a reconstructed version of Stoic logic thema 2 as follows: "When from two assertibles a third follows, and from the third and one (or both) of the two another follows, then this other follows from the first two." Bobzien uses constructs such as 𝜑, 𝜓⊢ 𝜒; in Metamath we will represent that construct as 𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 → 𝜒. This version a is without the phrase "or both"; see stoic2b 1423 for the version with the phrase "or both". We already have this rule as syldan 280, so here we show the equivalence and discourage its use. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | stoic2b 1423 |
Stoic logic Thema 2 version b. See stoic2a 1422.
Version b is with the phrase "or both". We already have this rule as mpd3an3 1333, so here we prove the equivalence and discourage its use. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | stoic3 1424 |
Stoic logic Thema 3.
Statement T3 of [Bobzien] p. 116-117 discusses Stoic logic thema 3. "When from two (assemblies) a third follows, and from the one that follows (i.e., the third) together with another, external external assumption, another follows, then other follows from the first two and the externally co-assumed one. (Simp. Cael. 237.2-4)" (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | stoic4a 1425 |
Stoic logic Thema 4 version a.
Statement T4 of [Bobzien] p. 117 shows a reconstructed version of Stoic logic thema 4: "When from two assertibles a third follows, and from the third and one (or both) of the two and one (or more) external assertible(s) another follows, then this other follows from the first two and the external(s)." We use 𝜃 to represent the "external" assertibles. This is version a, which is without the phrase "or both"; see stoic4b 1426 for the version with the phrase "or both". (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜒 ∧ 𝜑 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | stoic4b 1426 |
Stoic logic Thema 4 version b.
This is version b, which is with the phrase "or both". See stoic4a 1425 for more information. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ (((𝜒 ∧ 𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | syl6an 1427 | A syllogism deduction combined with conjoining antecedents. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Oct-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | syl10 1428 | A nested syllogism inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 17-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜏))) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜏 → 𝜂)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜂))) | ||
Theorem | exbir 1429 | Exportation implication also converting head from biconditional to conditional. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | 3impexp 1430 | impexp 261 with a 3-conjunct antecedent. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ↔ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | 3impexpbicom 1431 | 3impexp 1430 with biconditional consequent of antecedent that is commuted in consequent. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ↔ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜃))))) | ||
Theorem | 3impexpbicomi 1432 | Deduction form of 3impexpbicom 1431. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | ancomsimp 1433 | Closed form of ancoms 266. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜑) → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | expcomd 1434 | Deduction form of expcom 115. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 22-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | expdcom 1435 | Commuted form of expd 256. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 18-Mar-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | simplbi2comg 1436 | Implication form of simplbi2com 1437. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 22-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) → (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | simplbi2com 1437 | A deduction eliminating a conjunct, similar to simplbi2 383. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 22-Jul-2012.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 10-Nov-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | syl6ci 1438 | A syllogism inference combined with contraction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 18-Mar-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | mpisyl 1439 | A syllogism combined with a modus ponens inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
The universal quantifier was introduced above in wal 1346 for use by df-tru 1351. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it. | ||
Axiom | ax-5 1440 | Axiom of Quantified Implication. Axiom C4 of [Monk2] p. 105. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Axiom | ax-7 1441 | Axiom of Quantifier Commutation. This axiom says universal quantifiers can be swapped. One of the predicate logic axioms which do not involve equality. Axiom scheme C6' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Lemma 12 of [Monk2] p. 109 and Axiom C5-3 of [Monk2] p. 113. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-gen 1442 | Rule of Generalization. The postulated inference rule of predicate calculus. See, e.g., Rule 2 of [Hamilton] p. 74. This rule says that if something is unconditionally true, then it is true for all values of a variable. For example, if we have proved 𝑥 = 𝑥, we can conclude ∀𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥 or even ∀𝑦𝑥 = 𝑥. Theorem spi 1529 shows we can go the other way also: in other words we can add or remove universal quantifiers from the beginning of any theorem as required. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ∀𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | gen2 1443 | Generalization applied twice. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1998.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 | ||
Theorem | mpg 1444 | Modus ponens combined with generalization. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1994.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | mpgbi 1445 | Modus ponens on biconditional combined with generalization. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1994.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 28-Oct-2008.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | mpgbir 1446 | Modus ponens on biconditional combined with generalization. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1994.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 28-Oct-2008.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | a7s 1447 | Swap quantifiers in an antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | alimi 1448 | Inference quantifying both antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 2alimi 1449 | Inference doubly quantifying both antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | alim 1450 | Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 30-Mar-2008.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | al2imi 1451 | Inference quantifying antecedent, nested antecedent, and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | alanimi 1452 | Variant of al2imi 1451 with conjunctive antecedent. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥𝜒) | ||
Syntax | wnf 1453 | Extend wff definition to include the not-free predicate. |
wff Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Definition | df-nf 1454 |
Define the not-free predicate for wffs. This is read "𝑥 is not
free
in 𝜑". Not-free means that the
value of 𝑥 cannot affect the
value of 𝜑, e.g., any occurrence of 𝑥 in
𝜑 is
effectively
bound by a "for all" or something that expands to one (such as
"there
exists"). In particular, substitution for a variable not free in a
wff
does not affect its value (sbf 1770). An example of where this is used is
stdpc5 1577. See nf2 1661 for an alternate definition which
does not involve
nested quantifiers on the same variable.
Nonfreeness is a commonly used condition, so it is useful to have a notation for it. Surprisingly, there is no common formal notation for it, so here we devise one. Our definition lets us work with the notion of nonfreeness within the logic itself rather than as a metalogical side condition. To be precise, our definition really means "effectively not free", because it is slightly less restrictive than the usual textbook definition for "not free" (which considers syntactic freedom). For example, 𝑥 is effectively not free in the expression 𝑥 = 𝑥 (even though 𝑥 is syntactically free in it, so would be considered "free" in the usual textbook definition) because the value of 𝑥 in the formula 𝑥 = 𝑥 does not affect the truth of that formula (and thus substitutions will not change the result), see nfequid 1695. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | nfi 1455 | Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 from the definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | hbth 1456 |
No variable is (effectively) free in a theorem.
This and later "hypothesis-building" lemmas, with labels starting "hb...", allow us to construct proofs of formulas of the form ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) from smaller formulas of this form. These are useful for constructing hypotheses that state "𝑥 is (effectively) not free in 𝜑". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfth 1457 | No variable is (effectively) free in a theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfnth 1458 | No variable is (effectively) free in a non-theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nftru 1459 | The true constant has no free variables. (This can also be proven in one step with nfv 1521, but this proof does not use ax-17 1519.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥⊤ | ||
Theorem | alimdh 1460 | Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | albi 1461 | Theorem 19.15 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | alrimih 1462 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | albii 1463 | Inference adding universal quantifier to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 2albii 1464 | Inference adding 2 universal quantifiers to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | hbxfrbi 1465 | A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Jonathan Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfbii 1466 | Equality theorem for not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ↔ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfxfr 1467 | A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfxfrd 1468 | A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | alcoms 1469 | Swap quantifiers in an antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | hbal 1470 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in ∀𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | alcom 1471 | Theorem 19.5 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | alrimdh 1472 | Deduction from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | albidh 1473 | Formula-building rule for universal quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 19.26 1474 | Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90. Also Theorem *10.22 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 119. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.26-2 1475 | Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90 with two quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.26-3an 1476 | Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90 with triple conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 19.33 1477 | Theorem 19.33 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 ∨ ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | alrot3 1478 | Theorem *11.21 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 160. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 24-May-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | alrot4 1479 | Rotate 4 universal quantifiers twice. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2005.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jun-2014.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧∀𝑤∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | albiim 1480 | Split a biconditional and distribute quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | 2albiim 1481 | Split a biconditional and distribute 2 quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜓 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | hband 1482 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hban 1540. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | hb3and 1483 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hb3an 1543. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → ∀𝑥𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) → ∀𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | hbald 1484 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbal 1470. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑦𝜓 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Syntax | wex 1485 | Extend wff definition to include the existential quantifier ("there exists"). |
wff ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Axiom | ax-ie1 1486 | 𝑥 is bound in ∃𝑥𝜑. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-ie2 1487 | Define existential quantification. ∃𝑥𝜑 means "there exists at least one set 𝑥 such that 𝜑 is true". One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | hbe1 1488 | 𝑥 is not free in ∃𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfe1 1489 | 𝑥 is not free in ∃𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | 19.23ht 1490 | Closed form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2005.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | 19.23h 1491 | Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | alnex 1492 | Theorem 19.7 of [Margaris] p. 89. To read this intuitionistically, think of it as "if 𝜑 can be refuted for all 𝑥, then it is not possible to find an 𝑥 for which 𝜑 holds" (and likewise for the converse). Comparing this with dfexdc 1494 illustrates that statements which look similar (to someone used to classical logic) can be different intuitionistically due to different placement of negations. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 1-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-May-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑 ↔ ¬ ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nex 1493 | Generalization rule for negated wff. (Contributed by NM, 18-May-1994.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ¬ ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | dfexdc 1494 | Defining ∃𝑥𝜑 given decidability. It is common in classical logic to define ∃𝑥𝜑 as ¬ ∀𝑥¬ 𝜑 but in intuitionistic logic without a decidability condition, that is only an implication not an equivalence, as seen at exalim 1495. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID ∃𝑥𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | exalim 1495 | One direction of a classical definition of existential quantification. One direction of Definition of [Margaris] p. 49. For a decidable proposition, this is an equivalence, as seen as dfexdc 1494. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑) | ||
The equality predicate was introduced above in wceq 1348 for use by df-tru 1351. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it. | ||
Theorem | weq 1496 |
Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas using the equality
predicate.
(Instead of introducing weq 1496 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wceq 1348. This lets us avoid overloading the = connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically weq 1496 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wceq 1348. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "show proof weq /all" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.) |
wff 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Axiom | ax-8 1497 |
Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms of
predicate calculus with equality. This is similar to, but not quite, a
transitive law for equality (proved later as equtr 1702). Axiom scheme C8'
in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint).
Also appears as Axiom C7 of
[Monk2] p. 105.
Axioms ax-8 1497 through ax-16 1807 are the axioms having to do with equality, substitution, and logical properties of our binary predicate ∈ (which later in set theory will mean "is a member of"). Note that all axioms except ax-16 1807 and ax-17 1519 are still valid even when 𝑥, 𝑦, and 𝑧 are replaced with the same variable because they do not have any distinct variable (Metamath's $d) restrictions. Distinct variable restrictions are required for ax-16 1807 and ax-17 1519 only. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑧 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) | ||
Axiom | ax-10 1498 |
Axiom of Quantifier Substitution. One of the equality and substitution
axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Appears as Lemma L12 in
[Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint).
The original version of this axiom was ax-10o 1709 ("o" for "old") and was replaced with this shorter ax-10 1498 in May 2008. The old axiom is proved from this one as Theorem ax10o 1708. Conversely, this axiom is proved from ax-10o 1709 as Theorem ax10 1710. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥) | ||
Axiom | ax-11 1499 |
Axiom of Variable Substitution. One of the 5 equality axioms of predicate
calculus. The final consequent ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) is a way of
expressing "𝑦 substituted for 𝑥 in wff
𝜑
" (cf. sb6 1879). It
is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and
Axiom C8 of [Monk2] p. 105,
from which it can be proved by cases.
Variants of this axiom which are equivalent in classical logic but which have not been shown to be equivalent for intuitionistic logic are ax11v 1820, ax11v2 1813 and ax-11o 1816. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑))) | ||
Axiom | ax-i12 1500 |
Axiom of Quantifier Introduction. One of the equality and substitution
axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Informally, it says that
whenever 𝑧 is distinct from 𝑥 and
𝑦,
and 𝑥 =
𝑦 is true,
then 𝑥 = 𝑦 quantified with 𝑧 is also
true. In other words, 𝑧
is irrelevant to the truth of 𝑥 = 𝑦. Axiom scheme C9' in [Megill]
p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear
in the literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by
cases.
This axiom has been modified from the original ax12 1505 for compatibility with intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) Use its alias ax12or 1501 instead, for labeling consistency. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |