HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 15 of 142)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 1401-1500   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremtruorfal 1401 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊤ ∨ ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalortru 1402 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊥ ∨ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalorfal 1403 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊥ ∨ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremtruimtru 1404 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊤ → ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtruimfal 1405 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊤ → ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalimtru 1406 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊥ → ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalimfal 1407 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊥ → ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremnottru 1408 A ¬ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
(¬ ⊤ ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremnotfal 1409 A ¬ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
(¬ ⊥ ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtrubitru 1410 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊤ ↔ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtrubifal 1411 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 23-Feb-2018.)
((⊤ ↔ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalbitru 1412 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊥ ↔ ⊤) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalbifal 1413 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊥ ↔ ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtruxortru 1414 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊤ ⊻ ⊤) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremtruxorfal 1415 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊤ ⊻ ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalxortru 1416 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊥ ⊻ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalxorfal 1417 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊥ ⊻ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
1.2.15  Stoic logic indemonstrables (Chrysippus of Soli)

The Greek Stoics developed a system of logic. The Stoic Chrysippus, in particular, was often considered one of the greatest logicians of antiquity. Stoic logic is different from Aristotle's system, since it focuses on propositional logic, though later thinkers did combine the systems of the Stoics with Aristotle. Jan Lukasiewicz reports, "For anybody familiar with mathematical logic it is self-evident that the Stoic dialectic is the ancient form of modern propositional logic" ( On the history of the logic of proposition by Jan Lukasiewicz (1934), translated in: Selected Works - Edited by Ludwik Borkowski - Amsterdam, North-Holland, 1970 pp. 197-217, referenced in "History of Logic" https://www.historyoflogic.com/logic-stoics.htm). For more about Aristotle's system, see barbara and related theorems.

A key part of the Stoic logic system is a set of five "indemonstrables" assigned to Chrysippus of Soli by Diogenes Laertius, though in general it is difficult to assign specific ideas to specific thinkers. The indemonstrables are described in, for example, [Lopez-Astorga] p. 11 , [Sanford] p. 39, and [Hitchcock] p. 5. These indemonstrables are modus ponendo ponens (modus ponens) ax-mp 5, modus tollendo tollens (modus tollens) mto 657, modus ponendo tollens I mptnan 1418, modus ponendo tollens II mptxor 1419, and modus tollendo ponens (exclusive-or version) mtpxor 1421. The first is an axiom, the second is already proved; in this section we prove the other three. Since we assume or prove all of indemonstrables, the system of logic we use here is as at least as strong as the set of Stoic indemonstrables. Note that modus tollendo ponens mtpxor 1421 originally used exclusive-or, but over time the name modus tollendo ponens has increasingly referred to an inclusive-or variation, which is proved in mtpor 1420. This set of indemonstrables is not the entire system of Stoic logic.

 
Theoremmptnan 1418 Modus ponendo tollens 1, one of the "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. See rule 1 on [Lopez-Astorga] p. 12 , rule 1 on [Sanford] p. 40, and rule A3 in [Hitchcock] p. 5. Sanford describes this rule second (after mptxor 1419) as a "safer, and these days much more common" version of modus ponendo tollens because it avoids confusion between inclusive-or and exclusive-or. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 3-Jul-2016.)
𝜑    &    ¬ (𝜑𝜓)        ¬ 𝜓
 
Theoremmptxor 1419 Modus ponendo tollens 2, one of the "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. Note that this uses exclusive-or . See rule 2 on [Lopez-Astorga] p. 12 , rule 4 on [Sanford] p. 39 and rule A4 in [Hitchcock] p. 5 . (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
𝜑    &   (𝜑𝜓)        ¬ 𝜓
 
Theoremmtpor 1420 Modus tollendo ponens (inclusive-or version), aka disjunctive syllogism. This is similar to mtpxor 1421, one of the five original "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. However, in Stoic logic this rule used exclusive-or, while the name modus tollendo ponens often refers to a variant of the rule that uses inclusive-or instead. The rule says, "if 𝜑 is not true, and 𝜑 or 𝜓 (or both) are true, then 𝜓 must be true". An alternate phrasing is, "Once you eliminate the impossible, whatever remains, no matter how improbable, must be the truth". -- Sherlock Holmes (Sir Arthur Conan Doyle, 1890: The Sign of the Four, ch. 6). (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 3-Jul-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Nov-2017.)
¬ 𝜑    &   (𝜑𝜓)       𝜓
 
Theoremmtpxor 1421 Modus tollendo ponens (original exclusive-or version), aka disjunctive syllogism, similar to mtpor 1420, one of the five "indemonstrables" in Stoic logic. The rule says, "if 𝜑 is not true, and either 𝜑 or 𝜓 (exclusively) are true, then 𝜓 must be true". Today the name "modus tollendo ponens" often refers to a variant, the inclusive-or version as defined in mtpor 1420. See rule 3 on [Lopez-Astorga] p. 12 (note that the "or" is the same as mptxor 1419, that is, it is exclusive-or df-xor 1371), rule 3 of [Sanford] p. 39 (where it is not as clearly stated which kind of "or" is used but it appears to be in the same sense as mptxor 1419), and rule A5 in [Hitchcock] p. 5 (exclusive-or is expressly used). (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 4-Jul-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Nov-2017.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 19-Apr-2019.)
¬ 𝜑    &   (𝜑𝜓)       𝜓
 
Theoremstoic2a 1422 Stoic logic Thema 2 version a.

Statement T2 of [Bobzien] p. 117 shows a reconstructed version of Stoic logic thema 2 as follows: "When from two assertibles a third follows, and from the third and one (or both) of the two another follows, then this other follows from the first two."

Bobzien uses constructs such as 𝜑, 𝜓𝜒; in Metamath we will represent that construct as 𝜑𝜓𝜒.

This version a is without the phrase "or both"; see stoic2b 1423 for the version with the phrase "or both". We already have this rule as syldan 280, so here we show the equivalence and discourage its use. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.)

((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)    &   ((𝜑𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremstoic2b 1423 Stoic logic Thema 2 version b. See stoic2a 1422.

Version b is with the phrase "or both". We already have this rule as mpd3an3 1333, so here we prove the equivalence and discourage its use. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.)

((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremstoic3 1424 Stoic logic Thema 3.

Statement T3 of [Bobzien] p. 116-117 discusses Stoic logic thema 3.

"When from two (assemblies) a third follows, and from the one that follows (i.e., the third) together with another, external external assumption, another follows, then other follows from the first two and the externally co-assumed one. (Simp. Cael. 237.2-4)" (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.)

((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)    &   ((𝜒𝜃) → 𝜏)       ((𝜑𝜓𝜃) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremstoic4a 1425 Stoic logic Thema 4 version a.

Statement T4 of [Bobzien] p. 117 shows a reconstructed version of Stoic logic thema 4: "When from two assertibles a third follows, and from the third and one (or both) of the two and one (or more) external assertible(s) another follows, then this other follows from the first two and the external(s)."

We use 𝜃 to represent the "external" assertibles. This is version a, which is without the phrase "or both"; see stoic4b 1426 for the version with the phrase "or both". (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.)

((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)    &   ((𝜒𝜑𝜃) → 𝜏)       ((𝜑𝜓𝜃) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremstoic4b 1426 Stoic logic Thema 4 version b.

This is version b, which is with the phrase "or both". See stoic4a 1425 for more information. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 17-Feb-2019.)

((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)    &   (((𝜒𝜑𝜓) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)       ((𝜑𝜓𝜃) → 𝜏)
 
1.2.16  Logical implication (continued)
 
Theoremsyl6an 1427 A syllogism deduction combined with conjoining antecedents. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Oct-2011.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒𝜃))    &   ((𝜓𝜃) → 𝜏)       (𝜑 → (𝜒𝜏))
 
Theoremsyl10 1428 A nested syllogism inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 17-Jul-2011.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃𝜏)))    &   (𝜒 → (𝜏𝜂))       (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃𝜂)))
 
Theoremexbir 1429 Exportation implication also converting head from biconditional to conditional. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.)
(((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜒𝜃)) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃𝜒))))
 
Theorem3impexp 1430 impexp 261 with a 3-conjunct antecedent. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.)
(((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃) ↔ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒𝜃))))
 
Theorem3impexpbicom 1431 3impexp 1430 with biconditional consequent of antecedent that is commuted in consequent. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.)
(((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → (𝜃𝜏)) ↔ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜏𝜃)))))
 
Theorem3impexpbicomi 1432 Deduction form of 3impexpbicom 1431. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.)
((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → (𝜃𝜏))       (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜏𝜃))))
 
Theoremancomsimp 1433 Closed form of ancoms 266. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.)
(((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜓𝜑) → 𝜒))
 
Theoremexpcomd 1434 Deduction form of expcom 115. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 22-Jul-2012.)
(𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃))       (𝜑 → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜃)))
 
Theoremexpdcom 1435 Commuted form of expd 256. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 18-Mar-2012.)
(𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃))       (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜑𝜃)))
 
Theoremsimplbi2comg 1436 Implication form of simplbi2com 1437. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 22-Jul-2012.)
((𝜑 ↔ (𝜓𝜒)) → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑)))
 
Theoremsimplbi2com 1437 A deduction eliminating a conjunct, similar to simplbi2 383. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 22-Jul-2012.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 10-Nov-2012.)
(𝜑 ↔ (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑))
 
Theoremsyl6ci 1438 A syllogism inference combined with contraction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 18-Mar-2012.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   (𝜑𝜃)    &   (𝜒 → (𝜃𝜏))       (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜏))
 
Theoremmpisyl 1439 A syllogism combined with a modus ponens inference. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 25-Jul-2011.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   𝜒    &   (𝜓 → (𝜒𝜃))       (𝜑𝜃)
 
1.3  Predicate calculus mostly without distinct variables
 
1.3.1  Universal quantifier (continued)

The universal quantifier was introduced above in wal 1346 for use by df-tru 1351. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it.

 
Axiomax-5 1440 Axiom of Quantified Implication. Axiom C4 of [Monk2] p. 105. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Axiomax-7 1441 Axiom of Quantifier Commutation. This axiom says universal quantifiers can be swapped. One of the predicate logic axioms which do not involve equality. Axiom scheme C6' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Lemma 12 of [Monk2] p. 109 and Axiom C5-3 of [Monk2] p. 113. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝑥𝜑)
 
Axiomax-gen 1442 Rule of Generalization. The postulated inference rule of predicate calculus. See, e.g., Rule 2 of [Hamilton] p. 74. This rule says that if something is unconditionally true, then it is true for all values of a variable. For example, if we have proved 𝑥 = 𝑥, we can conclude 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑥 or even 𝑦𝑥 = 𝑥. Theorem spi 1529 shows we can go the other way also: in other words we can add or remove universal quantifiers from the beginning of any theorem as required. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
𝜑       𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremgen2 1443 Generalization applied twice. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1998.)
𝜑       𝑥𝑦𝜑
 
Theoremmpg 1444 Modus ponens combined with generalization. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1994.)
(∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)    &   𝜑       𝜓
 
Theoremmpgbi 1445 Modus ponens on biconditional combined with generalization. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1994.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 28-Oct-2008.)
(∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)    &   𝜑       𝜓
 
Theoremmpgbir 1446 Modus ponens on biconditional combined with generalization. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1994.) (Proof shortened by Stefan Allan, 28-Oct-2008.)
(𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   𝜓       𝜑
 
Theorema7s 1447 Swap quantifiers in an antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥𝑦𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑦𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremalimi 1448 Inference quantifying both antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorem2alimi 1449 Inference doubly quantifying both antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremalim 1450 Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 30-Mar-2008.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremal2imi 1451 Inference quantifying antecedent, nested antecedent, and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (∀𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒))
 
Theoremalanimi 1452 Variant of al2imi 1451 with conjunctive antecedent. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.)
((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)       ((∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥𝜒)
 
Syntaxwnf 1453 Extend wff definition to include the not-free predicate.
wff 𝑥𝜑
 
Definitiondf-nf 1454 Define the not-free predicate for wffs. This is read "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". Not-free means that the value of 𝑥 cannot affect the value of 𝜑, e.g., any occurrence of 𝑥 in 𝜑 is effectively bound by a "for all" or something that expands to one (such as "there exists"). In particular, substitution for a variable not free in a wff does not affect its value (sbf 1770). An example of where this is used is stdpc5 1577. See nf2 1661 for an alternate definition which does not involve nested quantifiers on the same variable.

Nonfreeness is a commonly used condition, so it is useful to have a notation for it. Surprisingly, there is no common formal notation for it, so here we devise one. Our definition lets us work with the notion of nonfreeness within the logic itself rather than as a metalogical side condition.

To be precise, our definition really means "effectively not free", because it is slightly less restrictive than the usual textbook definition for "not free" (which considers syntactic freedom). For example, 𝑥 is effectively not free in the expression 𝑥 = 𝑥 (even though 𝑥 is syntactically free in it, so would be considered "free" in the usual textbook definition) because the value of 𝑥 in the formula 𝑥 = 𝑥 does not affect the truth of that formula (and thus substitutions will not change the result), see nfequid 1695. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)

(Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑))
 
Theoremnfi 1455 Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 from the definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)       𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremhbth 1456 No variable is (effectively) free in a theorem.

This and later "hypothesis-building" lemmas, with labels starting "hb...", allow us to construct proofs of formulas of the form (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) from smaller formulas of this form. These are useful for constructing hypotheses that state "𝑥 is (effectively) not free in 𝜑". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

𝜑       (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnfth 1457 No variable is (effectively) free in a theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝜑       𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremnfnth 1458 No variable is (effectively) free in a non-theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Dec-2016.)
¬ 𝜑       𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremnftru 1459 The true constant has no free variables. (This can also be proven in one step with nfv 1521, but this proof does not use ax-17 1519.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.)
𝑥
 
Theoremalimdh 1460 Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒))
 
Theoremalbi 1461 Theorem 19.15 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremalrimih 1462 Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremalbii 1463 Inference adding universal quantifier to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorem2albii 1464 Inference adding 2 universal quantifiers to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremhbxfrbi 1465 A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Jonathan Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnfbii 1466 Equality theorem for not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ↔ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremnfxfr 1467 A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   𝑥𝜓       𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremnfxfrd 1468 A utility lemma to transfer a bound-variable hypothesis builder into a definition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜒 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)       (𝜒 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremalcoms 1469 Swap quantifiers in an antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.)
(∀𝑥𝑦𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑦𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremhbal 1470 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in 𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)       (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑦𝜑)
 
Theoremalcom 1471 Theorem 19.5 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremalrimdh 1472 Deduction from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒))
 
Theoremalbidh 1473 Formula-building rule for universal quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜒))
 
Theorem19.26 1474 Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90. Also Theorem *10.22 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 119. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Jul-2014.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theorem19.26-2 1475 Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90 with two quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.)
(∀𝑥𝑦(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝑦𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝑦𝜓))
 
Theorem19.26-3an 1476 Theorem 19.26 of [Margaris] p. 90 with triple conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-2011.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓𝜒) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜒))
 
Theorem19.33 1477 Theorem 19.33 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
((∀𝑥𝜑 ∨ ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremalrot3 1478 Theorem *11.21 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 160. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 24-May-2011.)
(∀𝑥𝑦𝑧𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝑧𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremalrot4 1479 Rotate 4 universal quantifiers twice. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2005.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jun-2014.)
(∀𝑥𝑦𝑧𝑤𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧𝑤𝑥𝑦𝜑)
 
Theoremalbiim 1480 Split a biconditional and distribute quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜓𝜑)))
 
Theorem2albiim 1481 Split a biconditional and distribute 2 quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.)
(∀𝑥𝑦(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝑦(𝜑𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥𝑦(𝜓𝜑)))
 
Theoremhband 1482 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hban 1540. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒))       (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremhb3and 1483 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hb3an 1543. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜃 → ∀𝑥𝜃))       (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒𝜃) → ∀𝑥(𝜓𝜒𝜃)))
 
Theoremhbald 1484 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbal 1470. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑦𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝑦𝜓))
 
Syntaxwex 1485 Extend wff definition to include the existential quantifier ("there exists").
wff 𝑥𝜑
 
Axiomax-ie1 1486 𝑥 is bound in 𝑥𝜑. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
(∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑥𝜑)
 
Axiomax-ie2 1487 Define existential quantification. 𝑥𝜑 means "there exists at least one set 𝑥 such that 𝜑 is true". One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
(∀𝑥(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theoremhbe1 1488 𝑥 is not free in 𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnfe1 1489 𝑥 is not free in 𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝑥𝜑
 
Theorem19.23ht 1490 Closed form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2005.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.)
(∀𝑥(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theorem19.23h 1491 Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.)
(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremalnex 1492 Theorem 19.7 of [Margaris] p. 89. To read this intuitionistically, think of it as "if 𝜑 can be refuted for all 𝑥, then it is not possible to find an 𝑥 for which 𝜑 holds" (and likewise for the converse). Comparing this with dfexdc 1494 illustrates that statements which look similar (to someone used to classical logic) can be different intuitionistically due to different placement of negations. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 1-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-May-2015.)
(∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑 ↔ ¬ ∃𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnex 1493 Generalization rule for negated wff. (Contributed by NM, 18-May-1994.)
¬ 𝜑        ¬ ∃𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremdfexdc 1494 Defining 𝑥𝜑 given decidability. It is common in classical logic to define 𝑥𝜑 as ¬ ∀𝑥¬ 𝜑 but in intuitionistic logic without a decidability condition, that is only an implication not an equivalence, as seen at exalim 1495. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Mar-2018.)
(DECID𝑥𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑))
 
Theoremexalim 1495 One direction of a classical definition of existential quantification. One direction of Definition of [Margaris] p. 49. For a decidable proposition, this is an equivalence, as seen as dfexdc 1494. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Jul-2018.)
(∃𝑥𝜑 → ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑)
 
1.3.2  Equality predicate (continued)

The equality predicate was introduced above in wceq 1348 for use by df-tru 1351. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it.

 
Theoremweq 1496 Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas using the equality predicate.

(Instead of introducing weq 1496 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wceq 1348. This lets us avoid overloading the = connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically weq 1496 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wceq 1348. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "show proof weq /all" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.)

wff 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Axiomax-8 1497 Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. This is similar to, but not quite, a transitive law for equality (proved later as equtr 1702). Axiom scheme C8' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom C7 of [Monk2] p. 105.

Axioms ax-8 1497 through ax-16 1807 are the axioms having to do with equality, substitution, and logical properties of our binary predicate (which later in set theory will mean "is a member of"). Note that all axioms except ax-16 1807 and ax-17 1519 are still valid even when 𝑥, 𝑦, and 𝑧 are replaced with the same variable because they do not have any distinct variable (Metamath's $d) restrictions. Distinct variable restrictions are required for ax-16 1807 and ax-17 1519 only. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑧))
 
Axiomax-10 1498 Axiom of Quantifier Substitution. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Appears as Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint).

The original version of this axiom was ax-10o 1709 ("o" for "old") and was replaced with this shorter ax-10 1498 in May 2008. The old axiom is proved from this one as Theorem ax10o 1708. Conversely, this axiom is proved from ax-10o 1709 as Theorem ax10 1710. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥)
 
Axiomax-11 1499 Axiom of Variable Substitution. One of the 5 equality axioms of predicate calculus. The final consequent 𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) is a way of expressing "𝑦 substituted for 𝑥 in wff 𝜑 " (cf. sb6 1879). It is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and Axiom C8 of [Monk2] p. 105, from which it can be proved by cases.

Variants of this axiom which are equivalent in classical logic but which have not been shown to be equivalent for intuitionistic logic are ax11v 1820, ax11v2 1813 and ax-11o 1816. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
 
Axiomax-i12 1500 Axiom of Quantifier Introduction. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Informally, it says that whenever 𝑧 is distinct from 𝑥 and 𝑦, and 𝑥 = 𝑦 is true, then 𝑥 = 𝑦 quantified with 𝑧 is also true. In other words, 𝑧 is irrelevant to the truth of 𝑥 = 𝑦. Axiom scheme C9' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear in the literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by cases.

This axiom has been modified from the original ax12 1505 for compatibility with intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) Use its alias ax12or 1501 instead, for labeling consistency. (New usage is discouraged.)

(∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13300 134 13301-13400 135 13401-13500 136 13501-13600 137 13601-13700 138 13701-13800 139 13801-13900 140 13901-14000 141 14001-14100 142 14101-14113
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >