Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 70 of 140) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | resfnfinfinss 6901 | The restriction of a function to a finite subset of its domain is finite. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 3-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | relcnvfi 6902 | If a relation is finite, its converse is as well. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Feb-2022.) |
Theorem | funrnfi 6903 | The range of a finite relation is finite if its converse is a function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Feb-2022.) |
Theorem | f1ofi 6904 | If a 1-1 and onto function has a finite domain, its range is finite. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Feb-2022.) |
Theorem | f1dmvrnfibi 6905 | A one-to-one function whose domain is a set is finite if and only if its range is finite. See also f1vrnfibi 6906. (Contributed by AV, 10-Jan-2020.) |
Theorem | f1vrnfibi 6906 | A one-to-one function which is a set is finite if and only if its range is finite. See also f1dmvrnfibi 6905. (Contributed by AV, 10-Jan-2020.) |
Theorem | iunfidisj 6907* | The finite union of disjoint finite sets is finite. Note that depends on , i.e. can be thought of as . (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-2006.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2022.) |
Disj | ||
Theorem | f1finf1o 6908 | Any injection from one finite set to another of equal size must be a bijection. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 5-Jun-2010.) |
Theorem | en1eqsn 6909 | A set with one element is a singleton. (Contributed by FL, 18-Aug-2008.) |
Theorem | en1eqsnbi 6910 | A set containing an element has exactly one element iff it is a singleton. (Contributed by FL, 13-Feb-2010.) (Revised by AV, 25-Jan-2020.) |
Theorem | snexxph 6911* | A case where the antecedent of snexg 4162 is not needed. The class is from dcextest 4557. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2022.) |
Theorem | preimaf1ofi 6912 | The preimage of a finite set under a one-to-one, onto function is finite. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Sep-2022.) |
Theorem | fidcenumlemim 6913* | Lemma for fidcenum 6917. Forward direction. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | fidcenumlemrks 6914* | Lemma for fidcenum 6917. Induction step for fidcenumlemrk 6915. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | fidcenumlemrk 6915* | Lemma for fidcenum 6917. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | fidcenumlemr 6916* | Lemma for fidcenum 6917. Reverse direction (put into deduction form). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | fidcenum 6917* | A set is finite if and only if it has decidable equality and is finitely enumerable. Proposition 8.1.11 of [AczelRathjen], p. 72. The definition of "finitely enumerable" as is Definition 8.1.4 of [AczelRathjen], p. 71. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | sbthlem1 6918* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 22-Mar-1998.) |
Theorem | sbthlem2 6919* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 22-Mar-1998.) |
Theorem | sbthlemi3 6920* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 22-Mar-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Theorem | sbthlemi4 6921* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Theorem | sbthlemi5 6922* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 22-Mar-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Theorem | sbthlemi6 6923* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Theorem | sbthlem7 6924* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1998.) |
Theorem | sbthlemi8 6925* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Theorem | sbthlemi9 6926* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Theorem | sbthlemi10 6927* | Lemma for isbth 6928. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Theorem | isbth 6928 | Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem. Theorem 18 of [Suppes] p. 95. This theorem states that if set is smaller (has lower cardinality) than and vice-versa, then and are equinumerous (have the same cardinality). The interesting thing is that this can be proved without invoking the Axiom of Choice, as we do here, but the proof as you can see is quite difficult. (The theorem can be proved more easily if we allow AC.) The main proof consists of lemmas sbthlem1 6918 through sbthlemi10 6927; this final piece mainly changes bound variables to eliminate the hypotheses of sbthlemi10 6927. We follow closely the proof in Suppes, which you should consult to understand our proof at a higher level. Note that Suppes' proof, which is credited to J. M. Whitaker, does not require the Axiom of Infinity. The proof does require the law of the excluded middle which cannot be avoided as shown at exmidsbthr 13862. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jun-1998.) |
EXMID | ||
Syntax | cfi 6929 | Extend class notation with the function whose value is the class of finite intersections of the elements of a given set. |
Definition | df-fi 6930* | Function whose value is the class of finite intersections of the elements of the argument. Note that the empty intersection being the universal class, hence a proper class, it cannot be an element of that class. Therefore, the function value is the class of nonempty finite intersections of elements of the argument (see elfi2 6933). (Contributed by FL, 27-Apr-2008.) |
Theorem | fival 6931* | The set of all the finite intersections of the elements of . (Contributed by FL, 27-Apr-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Nov-2013.) |
Theorem | elfi 6932* | Specific properties of an element of . (Contributed by FL, 27-Apr-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Nov-2013.) |
Theorem | elfi2 6933* | The empty intersection need not be considered in the set of finite intersections. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 21-Mar-2015.) |
Theorem | elfir 6934 | Sufficient condition for an element of . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Nov-2013.) |
Theorem | ssfii 6935 | Any element of a set is the intersection of a finite subset of . (Contributed by FL, 27-Apr-2008.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 21-Mar-2015.) |
Theorem | fi0 6936 | The set of finite intersections of the empty set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Aug-2015.) |
Theorem | fieq0 6937 | A set is empty iff the class of all the finite intersections of that set is empty. (Contributed by FL, 27-Apr-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Nov-2013.) |
Theorem | fiss 6938 | Subset relationship for function . (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 7-Oct-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Nov-2013.) |
Theorem | fiuni 6939 | The union of the finite intersections of a set is simply the union of the set itself. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 5-Sep-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Nov-2013.) |
Theorem | fipwssg 6940 | If a set is a family of subsets of some base set, then so is its finite intersection. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Aug-2015.) |
Theorem | fifo 6941* | Describe a surjection from nonempty finite sets to finite intersections. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
Theorem | dcfi 6942* | Decidability of a family of propositions indexed by a finite set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Sep-2024.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Syntax | csup 6943 | Extend class notation to include supremum of class . Here is ordinarily a relation that strictly orders class . For example, could be 'less than' and could be the set of real numbers. |
Syntax | cinf 6944 | Extend class notation to include infimum of class . Here is ordinarily a relation that strictly orders class . For example, could be 'less than' and could be the set of real numbers. |
inf | ||
Definition | df-sup 6945* | Define the supremum of class . It is meaningful when is a relation that strictly orders and when the supremum exists. (Contributed by NM, 22-May-1999.) |
Definition | df-inf 6946 | Define the infimum of class . It is meaningful when is a relation that strictly orders and when the infimum exists. For example, could be 'less than', could be the set of real numbers, and could be the set of all positive reals; in this case the infimum is 0. The infimum is defined as the supremum using the converse ordering relation. In the given example, 0 is the supremum of all reals (greatest real number) for which all positive reals are greater. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | supeq1 6947 | Equality theorem for supremum. (Contributed by NM, 22-May-1999.) |
Theorem | supeq1d 6948 | Equality deduction for supremum. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 22-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | supeq1i 6949 | Equality inference for supremum. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 22-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | supeq2 6950 | Equality theorem for supremum. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
Theorem | supeq3 6951 | Equality theorem for supremum. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | supeq123d 6952 | Equality deduction for supremum. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) |
Theorem | nfsup 6953 | Hypothesis builder for supremum. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | supmoti 6954* | Any class has at most one supremum in (where is interpreted as 'less than'). The hypothesis is satisfied by real numbers (see lttri3 7974) or other orders which correspond to tight apartnesses. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | supeuti 6955* | A supremum is unique. Similar to Theorem I.26 of [Apostol] p. 24 (but for suprema in general). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | supval2ti 6956* | Alternate expression for the supremum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | eqsupti 6957* | Sufficient condition for an element to be equal to the supremum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | eqsuptid 6958* | Sufficient condition for an element to be equal to the supremum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | supclti 6959* | A supremum belongs to its base class (closure law). See also supubti 6960 and suplubti 6961. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | supubti 6960* |
A supremum is an upper bound. See also supclti 6959 and suplubti 6961.
This proof demonstrates how to expand an iota-based definition (df-iota 5152) using riotacl2 5810. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | suplubti 6961* | A supremum is the least upper bound. See also supclti 6959 and supubti 6960. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | suplub2ti 6962* | Bidirectional form of suplubti 6961. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Jan-2022.) |
Theorem | supelti 6963* | Supremum membership in a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jan-2022.) |
Theorem | sup00 6964 | The supremum under an empty base set is always the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2020.) |
Theorem | supmaxti 6965* | The greatest element of a set is its supremum. Note that the converse is not true; the supremum might not be an element of the set considered. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | supsnti 6966* | The supremum of a singleton. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | isotilem 6967* | Lemma for isoti 6968. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | isoti 6968* | An isomorphism preserves tightness. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | supisolem 6969* | Lemma for supisoti 6971. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Dec-2016.) |
Theorem | supisoex 6970* | Lemma for supisoti 6971. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Dec-2016.) |
Theorem | supisoti 6971* | Image of a supremum under an isomorphism. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | infeq1 6972 | Equality theorem for infimum. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf inf | ||
Theorem | infeq1d 6973 | Equality deduction for infimum. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf inf | ||
Theorem | infeq1i 6974 | Equality inference for infimum. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf inf | ||
Theorem | infeq2 6975 | Equality theorem for infimum. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf inf | ||
Theorem | infeq3 6976 | Equality theorem for infimum. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf inf | ||
Theorem | infeq123d 6977 | Equality deduction for infimum. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf inf | ||
Theorem | nfinf 6978 | Hypothesis builder for infimum. (Contributed by AV, 2-Sep-2020.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | cnvinfex 6979* | Two ways of expressing existence of an infimum (one in terms of converse). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Dec-2021.) |
Theorem | cnvti 6980* | If a relation satisfies a condition corresponding to tightness of an apartness generated by an order, so does its converse. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Dec-2021.) |
Theorem | eqinfti 6981* | Sufficient condition for an element to be equal to the infimum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | eqinftid 6982* | Sufficient condition for an element to be equal to the infimum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | infvalti 6983* | Alternate expression for the infimum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | infclti 6984* | An infimum belongs to its base class (closure law). See also inflbti 6985 and infglbti 6986. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | inflbti 6985* | An infimum is a lower bound. See also infclti 6984 and infglbti 6986. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | infglbti 6986* | An infimum is the greatest lower bound. See also infclti 6984 and inflbti 6985. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | infnlbti 6987* | A lower bound is not greater than the infimum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | infminti 6988* | The smallest element of a set is its infimum. Note that the converse is not true; the infimum might not be an element of the set considered. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | infmoti 6989* | Any class has at most one infimum in (where is interpreted as 'less than'). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2021.) |
Theorem | infeuti 6990* | An infimum is unique. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Dec-2021.) |
Theorem | infsnti 6991* | The infimum of a singleton. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Dec-2021.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | inf00 6992 | The infimum regarding an empty base set is always the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2020.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | infisoti 6993* | Image of an infimum under an isomorphism. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Dec-2021.) |
inf inf | ||
Theorem | supex2g 6994 | Existence of supremum. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
Theorem | infex2g 6995 | Existence of infimum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Oct-2024.) |
inf | ||
Theorem | ordiso2 6996 | Generalize ordiso 6997 to proper classes. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
Theorem | ordiso 6997* | Order-isomorphic ordinal numbers are equal. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 16-Oct-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
Syntax | cdju 6998 | Extend class notation to include disjoint union of two classes. |
⊔ | ||
Definition | df-dju 6999 | Disjoint union of two classes. This is a way of creating a class which contains elements corresponding to each element of or , tagging each one with whether it came from or . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jun-2022.) |
⊔ | ||
Theorem | djueq12 7000 | Equality theorem for disjoint union. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Jun-2022.) |
⊔ ⊔ |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |