Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 47 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | nnsucpred 4601 | The successor of the precedessor of a nonzero natural number. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jul-2022.) |
Theorem | nndceq0 4602 | A natural number is either zero or nonzero. Decidable equality for natural numbers is a special case of the law of the excluded middle which holds in most constructive set theories including ours. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Jan-2019.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | 0elnn 4603 | A natural number is either the empty set or has the empty set as an element. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Aug-2019.) |
Theorem | nn0eln0 4604 | A natural number is nonempty iff it contains the empty set. Although in constructive mathematics it is generally more natural to work with inhabited sets and ignore the whole concept of nonempty sets, in the specific case of natural numbers this theorem may be helpful in converting proofs which were written assuming excluded middle. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Aug-2019.) |
Theorem | nnregexmid 4605* | If inhabited sets of natural numbers always have minimal elements, excluded middle follows. The argument is essentially the same as regexmid 4519 and the larger lesson is that although natural numbers may behave "non-constructively" even in a constructive set theory (for example see nndceq 6478 or nntri3or 6472), sets of natural numbers are a different animal. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 6-Sep-2019.) |
Theorem | omsinds 4606* | Strong (or "total") induction principle over . (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 17-Jul-2015.) |
Theorem | nnpredcl 4607 | The predecessor of a natural number is a natural number. This theorem is most interesting when the natural number is a successor (as seen in theorems like onsucuni2 4548) but also holds when it is by uni0 3823. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jul-2022.) |
Theorem | nnpredlt 4608 | The predecessor (see nnpredcl 4607) of a nonzero natural number is less than (see df-iord 4351) that number. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Sep-2024.) |
Syntax | cxp 4609 | Extend the definition of a class to include the cross product. |
Syntax | ccnv 4610 | Extend the definition of a class to include the converse of a class. |
Syntax | cdm 4611 | Extend the definition of a class to include the domain of a class. |
Syntax | crn 4612 | Extend the definition of a class to include the range of a class. |
Syntax | cres 4613 | Extend the definition of a class to include the restriction of a class. (Read: The restriction of to .) |
Syntax | cima 4614 | Extend the definition of a class to include the image of a class. (Read: The image of under .) |
Syntax | ccom 4615 | Extend the definition of a class to include the composition of two classes. (Read: The composition of and .) |
Syntax | wrel 4616 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the relation predicate. (Read: is a relation.) |
Definition | df-xp 4617* | Define the Cartesian product of two classes. This is also sometimes called the "cross product" but that term also has other meanings; we intentionally choose a less ambiguous term. Definition 9.11 of [Quine] p. 64. For example, . Another example is that the set of rational numbers is defined using the Cartesian product as ; the left- and right-hand sides of the Cartesian product represent the top (integer) and bottom (natural) numbers of a fraction. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Definition | df-rel 4618 | Define the relation predicate. Definition 6.4(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 23. For alternate definitions, see dfrel2 5061 and dfrel3 5068. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
Definition | df-cnv 4619* |
Define the converse of a class. Definition 9.12 of [Quine] p. 64. The
converse of a binary relation swaps its arguments, i.e., if
and then , as proven in brcnv 4794
(see df-br 3990 and df-rel 4618 for more on relations). For example,
.
We use Quine's breve accent (smile) notation. Like Quine, we use it as a prefix, which eliminates the need for parentheses. "Converse" is Quine's terminology. Some authors use a "minus one" exponent and call it "inverse", especially when the argument is a function, although this is not in general a genuine inverse. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Definition | df-co 4620* | Define the composition of two classes. Definition 6.6(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. Note that Definition 7 of [Suppes] p. 63 reverses and , uses a slash instead of , and calls the operation "relative product". (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Definition | df-dm 4621* | Define the domain of a class. Definition 3 of [Suppes] p. 59. For example, F = { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } dom F = { 2 , 3 } . Contrast with range (defined in df-rn 4622). For alternate definitions see dfdm2 5145, dfdm3 4798, and dfdm4 4803. The notation " " is used by Enderton; other authors sometimes use script D. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
Definition | df-rn 4622 | Define the range of a class. For example, F = { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } -> ran F = { 6 , 9 } . Contrast with domain (defined in df-dm 4621). For alternate definitions, see dfrn2 4799, dfrn3 4800, and dfrn4 5071. The notation " " is used by Enderton; other authors sometimes use script R or script W. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
Definition | df-res 4623 | Define the restriction of a class. Definition 6.6(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. For example, . We do not introduce a special syntax for the corestriction of a class: it will be expressed either as the intersection or as the converse of the restricted converse. (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.) |
Definition | df-ima 4624 | Define the image of a class (as restricted by another class). Definition 6.6(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. For example, ( F = { 2 , 6 , 3 , 9 } /\ B = { 1 , 2 } ) -> ( F B ) = { 6 } . Contrast with restriction (df-res 4623) and range (df-rn 4622). For an alternate definition, see dfima2 4955. (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.) |
Theorem | xpeq1 4625 | Equality theorem for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | xpeq2 4626 | Equality theorem for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | elxpi 4627* | Membership in a cross product. Uses fewer axioms than elxp 4628. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | elxp 4628* | Membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | elxp2 4629* | Membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 23-Feb-2004.) |
Theorem | xpeq12 4630 | Equality theorem for cross product. (Contributed by FL, 31-Aug-2009.) |
Theorem | xpeq1i 4631 | Equality inference for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 21-Dec-2008.) |
Theorem | xpeq2i 4632 | Equality inference for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 21-Dec-2008.) |
Theorem | xpeq12i 4633 | Equality inference for cross product. (Contributed by FL, 31-Aug-2009.) |
Theorem | xpeq1d 4634 | Equality deduction for cross product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 17-Jun-2010.) |
Theorem | xpeq2d 4635 | Equality deduction for cross product. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 17-Jun-2010.) |
Theorem | xpeq12d 4636 | Equality deduction for Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2013.) |
Theorem | sqxpeqd 4637 | Equality deduction for a Cartesian square, see Wikipedia "Cartesian product", https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Cartesian_product#n-ary_Cartesian_power. (Contributed by AV, 13-Jan-2020.) |
Theorem | nfxp 4638 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for cross product. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | 0nelxp 4639 | The empty set is not a member of a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 2-May-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | 0nelelxp 4640 | A member of a cross product (ordered pair) doesn't contain the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 15-Dec-2008.) |
Theorem | opelxp 4641 | Ordered pair membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | brxp 4642 | Binary relation on a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | opelxpi 4643 | Ordered pair membership in a cross product (implication). (Contributed by NM, 28-May-1995.) |
Theorem | opelxpd 4644 | Ordered pair membership in a Cartesian product, deduction form. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 3-Mar-2021.) |
Theorem | opelxp1 4645 | The first member of an ordered pair of classes in a cross product belongs to first cross product argument. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | opelxp2 4646 | The second member of an ordered pair of classes in a cross product belongs to second cross product argument. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | otelxp1 4647 | The first member of an ordered triple of classes in a cross product belongs to first cross product argument. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-2008.) |
Theorem | rabxp 4648* | Membership in a class builder restricted to a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 20-Feb-2014.) |
Theorem | brrelex12 4649 | A true binary relation on a relation implies the arguments are sets. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | brrelex1 4650 | A true binary relation on a relation implies the first argument is a set. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by NM, 18-May-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | brrelex 4651 | A true binary relation on a relation implies the first argument is a set. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by NM, 18-May-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | brrelex2 4652 | A true binary relation on a relation implies the second argument is a set. (This is a property of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | brrelex12i 4653 | Two classes that are related by a binary relation are sets. (An artifact of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by BJ, 3-Oct-2022.) |
Theorem | brrelex1i 4654 | The first argument of a binary relation exists. (An artifact of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by NM, 4-Jun-1998.) |
Theorem | brrelex2i 4655 | The second argument of a binary relation exists. (An artifact of our ordered pair definition.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | nprrel 4656 | No proper class is related to anything via any relation. (Contributed by Roy F. Longton, 30-Jul-2005.) |
Theorem | 0nelrel 4657 | A binary relation does not contain the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 15-Nov-2021.) |
Theorem | fconstmpt 4658* | Representation of a constant function using the mapping operation. (Note that cannot appear free in .) (Contributed by NM, 12-Oct-1999.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2013.) |
Theorem | vtoclr 4659* | Variable to class conversion of transitive relation. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | opelvvg 4660 | Ordered pair membership in the universal class of ordered pairs. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
Theorem | opelvv 4661 | Ordered pair membership in the universal class of ordered pairs. (Contributed by NM, 22-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | opthprc 4662 | Justification theorem for an ordered pair definition that works for any classes, including proper classes. This is a possible definition implied by the footnote in [Jech] p. 78, which says, "The sophisticated reader will not object to our use of a pair of classes." (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2003.) |
Theorem | brel 4663 | Two things in a binary relation belong to the relation's domain. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | brab2a 4664* | Ordered pair membership in an ordered pair class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Nov-2015.) |
Theorem | elxp3 4665* | Membership in a cross product. (Contributed by NM, 5-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | opeliunxp 4666 | Membership in a union of cross products. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Jan-2017.) |
Theorem | xpundi 4667 | Distributive law for cross product over union. Theorem 103 of [Suppes] p. 52. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-2004.) |
Theorem | xpundir 4668 | Distributive law for cross product over union. Similar to Theorem 103 of [Suppes] p. 52. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2002.) |
Theorem | xpiundi 4669* | Distributive law for cross product over indexed union. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Apr-2014.) |
Theorem | xpiundir 4670* | Distributive law for cross product over indexed union. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Apr-2014.) |
Theorem | iunxpconst 4671* | Membership in a union of cross products when the second factor is constant. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Dec-2014.) |
Theorem | xpun 4672 | The cross product of two unions. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-2004.) |
Theorem | elvv 4673* | Membership in universal class of ordered pairs. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | elvvv 4674* | Membership in universal class of ordered triples. (Contributed by NM, 17-Dec-2008.) |
Theorem | elvvuni 4675 | An ordered pair contains its union. (Contributed by NM, 16-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | mosubopt 4676* | "At most one" remains true inside ordered pair quantification. (Contributed by NM, 28-Aug-2007.) |
Theorem | mosubop 4677* | "At most one" remains true inside ordered pair quantification. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-1995.) |
Theorem | brinxp2 4678 | Intersection of binary relation with Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 3-Mar-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
Theorem | brinxp 4679 | Intersection of binary relation with Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.) |
Theorem | poinxp 4680 | Intersection of partial order with cross product of its field. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | soinxp 4681 | Intersection of linear order with cross product of its field. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | seinxp 4682 | Intersection of set-like relation with cross product of its field. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
Se Se | ||
Theorem | posng 4683 | Partial ordering of a singleton. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Dec-2018.) |
Theorem | sosng 4684 | Strict linear ordering on a singleton. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Dec-2018.) |
Theorem | opabssxp 4685* | An abstraction relation is a subset of a related cross product. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | brab2ga 4686* | The law of concretion for a binary relation. See brab2a 4664 for alternate proof. TODO: should one of them be deleted? (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
Theorem | optocl 4687* | Implicit substitution of class for ordered pair. (Contributed by NM, 5-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | 2optocl 4688* | Implicit substitution of classes for ordered pairs. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | 3optocl 4689* | Implicit substitution of classes for ordered pairs. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | opbrop 4690* | Ordered pair membership in a relation. Special case. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1995.) |
Theorem | 0xp 4691 | The cross product with the empty set is empty. Part of Theorem 3.13(ii) of [Monk1] p. 37. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | csbxpg 4692 | Distribute proper substitution through the cross product of two classes. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 10-Nov-2012.) |
Theorem | releq 4693 | Equality theorem for the relation predicate. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
Theorem | releqi 4694 | Equality inference for the relation predicate. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2006.) |
Theorem | releqd 4695 | Equality deduction for the relation predicate. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | nfrel 4696 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for a relation. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jan-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sbcrel 4697 | Distribute proper substitution through a relation predicate. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 23-Jul-2017.) |
Theorem | relss 4698 | Subclass theorem for relation predicate. Theorem 2 of [Suppes] p. 58. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-1994.) |
Theorem | ssrel 4699* | A subclass relationship depends only on a relation's ordered pairs. Theorem 3.2(i) of [Monk1] p. 33. (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 27-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | eqrel 4700* | Extensionality principle for relations. Theorem 3.2(ii) of [Monk1] p. 33. (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |