Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 6801-6900 *Has distinct variable
group(s)
Type | Label | Description |
Statement |
|
Theorem | xp1en 6801 |
One times a cardinal number. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised
by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | endisj 6802* |
Any two sets are equinumerous to disjoint sets. Exercise 4.39 of
[Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed by
NM, 16-Apr-2004.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpcomf1o 6803* |
The canonical bijection from to .
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Apr-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpcomco 6804* |
Composition with the bijection of xpcomf1o 6803 swaps the arguments to a
mapping. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpcomen 6805 |
Commutative law for equinumerosity of Cartesian product. Proposition
4.22(d) of [Mendelson] p. 254.
(Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-2004.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpcomeng 6806 |
Commutative law for equinumerosity of Cartesian product. Proposition
4.22(d) of [Mendelson] p. 254.
(Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-2006.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpsnen2g 6807 |
A set is equinumerous to its Cartesian product with a singleton on the
left. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpassen 6808 |
Associative law for equinumerosity of Cartesian product. Proposition
4.22(e) of [Mendelson] p. 254.
(Contributed by NM, 22-Jan-2004.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpdom2 6809 |
Dominance law for Cartesian product. Proposition 10.33(2) of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 92.
(Contributed by NM, 24-Jul-2004.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpdom2g 6810 |
Dominance law for Cartesian product. Theorem 6L(c) of [Enderton]
p. 149. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpdom1g 6811 |
Dominance law for Cartesian product. Theorem 6L(c) of [Enderton]
p. 149. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
26-Apr-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpdom3m 6812* |
A set is dominated by its Cartesian product with an inhabited set.
Exercise 6 of [Suppes] p. 98.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
15-Apr-2020.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpdom1 6813 |
Dominance law for Cartesian product. Theorem 6L(c) of [Enderton]
p. 149. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by NM,
29-Mar-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fopwdom 6814 |
Covering implies injection on power sets. (Contributed by Stefan
O'Rear, 6-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | 0domg 6815 |
Any set dominates the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | dom0 6816 |
A set dominated by the empty set is empty. (Contributed by NM,
22-Nov-2004.)
|
|
|
Theorem | 0dom 6817 |
Any set dominates the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | enen1 6818 |
Equality-like theorem for equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM,
18-Dec-2003.)
|
|
|
Theorem | enen2 6819 |
Equality-like theorem for equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM,
18-Dec-2003.)
|
|
|
Theorem | domen1 6820 |
Equality-like theorem for equinumerosity and dominance. (Contributed by
NM, 8-Nov-2003.)
|
|
|
Theorem | domen2 6821 |
Equality-like theorem for equinumerosity and dominance. (Contributed by
NM, 8-Nov-2003.)
|
|
|
2.6.29 Equinumerosity (cont.)
|
|
Theorem | xpf1o 6822* |
Construct a bijection on a Cartesian product given bijections on the
factors. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpen 6823 |
Equinumerosity law for Cartesian product. Proposition 4.22(b) of
[Mendelson] p. 254. (Contributed by
NM, 24-Jul-2004.)
|
|
|
Theorem | mapen 6824 |
Two set exponentiations are equinumerous when their bases and exponents
are equinumerous. Theorem 6H(c) of [Enderton] p. 139. (Contributed by
NM, 16-Dec-2003.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | mapdom1g 6825 |
Order-preserving property of set exponentiation. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 15-Jul-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | mapxpen 6826 |
Equinumerosity law for double set exponentiation. Proposition 10.45 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 96.
(Contributed by NM, 21-Feb-2004.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpmapenlem 6827* |
Lemma for xpmapen 6828. (Contributed by NM, 1-May-2004.) (Revised
by
Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | xpmapen 6828 |
Equinumerosity law for set exponentiation of a Cartesian product.
Exercise 4.47 of [Mendelson] p. 255.
(Contributed by NM, 23-Feb-2004.)
(Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | ssenen 6829* |
Equinumerosity of equinumerous subsets of a set. (Contributed by NM,
30-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
2.6.30 Pigeonhole Principle
|
|
Theorem | phplem1 6830 |
Lemma for Pigeonhole Principle. If we join a natural number to itself
minus an element, we end up with its successor minus the same element.
(Contributed by NM, 25-May-1998.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phplem2 6831 |
Lemma for Pigeonhole Principle. A natural number is equinumerous to its
successor minus one of its elements. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1998.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phplem3 6832 |
Lemma for Pigeonhole Principle. A natural number is equinumerous to its
successor minus any element of the successor. For a version without the
redundant hypotheses, see phplem3g 6834. (Contributed by NM,
26-May-1998.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phplem4 6833 |
Lemma for Pigeonhole Principle. Equinumerosity of successors implies
equinumerosity of the original natural numbers. (Contributed by NM,
28-May-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phplem3g 6834 |
A natural number is equinumerous to its successor minus any element of
the successor. Version of phplem3 6832 with unnecessary hypotheses
removed. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | nneneq 6835 |
Two equinumerous natural numbers are equal. Proposition 10.20 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 90 and its
converse. Also compare Corollary 6E of
[Enderton] p. 136. (Contributed by NM,
28-May-1998.)
|
|
|
Theorem | php5 6836 |
A natural number is not equinumerous to its successor. Corollary
10.21(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 90.
(Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-2004.)
|
|
|
Theorem | snnen2og 6837 |
A singleton is never equinumerous with the ordinal
number 2. If
is a proper
class, see snnen2oprc 6838. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
1-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | snnen2oprc 6838 |
A singleton is never equinumerous with the ordinal
number 2. If
is a set, see snnen2og 6837. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
1-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | 1nen2 6839 |
One and two are not equinumerous. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
25-Jan-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phplem4dom 6840 |
Dominance of successors implies dominance of the original natural
numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | php5dom 6841 |
A natural number does not dominate its successor. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 1-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | nndomo 6842 |
Cardinal ordering agrees with natural number ordering. Example 3 of
[Enderton] p. 146. (Contributed by NM,
17-Jun-1998.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phpm 6843* |
Pigeonhole Principle. A natural number is not equinumerous to a proper
subset of itself. By "proper subset" here we mean that there
is an
element which is in the natural number and not in the subset, or in
symbols (which is stronger than not being equal
in the absence of excluded middle). Theorem (Pigeonhole Principle) of
[Enderton] p. 134. The theorem is
so-called because you can't put n +
1 pigeons into n holes (if each hole holds only one pigeon). The
proof consists of lemmas phplem1 6830 through phplem4 6833, nneneq 6835, and
this final piece of the proof. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-1998.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phpelm 6844 |
Pigeonhole Principle. A natural number is not equinumerous to an
element of itself. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 6-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | phplem4on 6845 |
Equinumerosity of successors of an ordinal and a natural number implies
equinumerosity of the originals. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
5-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
2.6.31 Finite sets
|
|
Theorem | fict 6846 |
A finite set is dominated by . Also see finct 7093. (Contributed
by Thierry Arnoux, 27-Mar-2018.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fidceq 6847 |
Equality of members of a finite set is decidable. This may be
counterintuitive: cannot any two sets be elements of a finite set?
Well, to show, for example, that is finite would require
showing it is equinumerous to or to but to show that you'd
need to know
or , respectively.
(Contributed by
Jim Kingdon, 5-Sep-2021.)
|
DECID |
|
Theorem | fidifsnen 6848 |
All decrements of a finite set are equinumerous. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 9-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fidifsnid 6849 |
If we remove a single element from a finite set then put it back in, we
end up with the original finite set. This strengthens difsnss 3726 from
subset to equality when the set is finite. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
9-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | nnfi 6850 |
Natural numbers are finite sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear,
21-Mar-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | enfi 6851 |
Equinumerous sets have the same finiteness. (Contributed by NM,
22-Aug-2008.)
|
|
|
Theorem | enfii 6852 |
A set equinumerous to a finite set is finite. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 12-Mar-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | ssfilem 6853* |
Lemma for ssfiexmid 6854. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 3-Feb-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | ssfiexmid 6854* |
If any subset of a finite set is finite, excluded middle follows. One
direction of Theorem 2.1 of [Bauer], p.
485. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 19-May-2020.)
|
|
|
Theorem | infiexmid 6855* |
If the intersection of any finite set and any other set is finite,
excluded middle follows. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Feb-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | domfiexmid 6856* |
If any set dominated by a finite set is finite, excluded middle follows.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 3-Feb-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | dif1en 6857 |
If a set is
equinumerous to the successor of a natural number
, then with an element removed is
equinumerous to .
(Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear,
16-Aug-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | dif1enen 6858 |
Subtracting one element from each of two equinumerous finite sets.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Jun-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fiunsnnn 6859 |
Adding one element to a finite set which is equinumerous to a natural
number. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | php5fin 6860 |
A finite set is not equinumerous to a set which adds one element.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fisbth 6861 |
Schroeder-Bernstein Theorem for finite sets. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 12-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | 0fin 6862 |
The empty set is finite. (Contributed by FL, 14-Jul-2008.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fin0 6863* |
A nonempty finite set has at least one element. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 10-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fin0or 6864* |
A finite set is either empty or inhabited. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
30-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | diffitest 6865* |
If subtracting any set from a finite set gives a finite set, any
proposition of the form is
decidable. This is not a proof of
full excluded middle, but it is close enough to show we won't be able to
prove . (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon,
8-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | findcard 6866* |
Schema for induction on the cardinality of a finite set. The inductive
hypothesis is that the result is true on the given set with any one
element removed. The result is then proven to be true for all finite
sets. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.)
|
|
|
Theorem | findcard2 6867* |
Schema for induction on the cardinality of a finite set. The inductive
step shows that the result is true if one more element is added to the
set. The result is then proven to be true for all finite sets.
(Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 8-Jul-2010.)
|
|
|
Theorem | findcard2s 6868* |
Variation of findcard2 6867 requiring that the element added in the
induction step not be a member of the original set. (Contributed by
Paul Chapman, 30-Nov-2012.)
|
|
|
Theorem | findcard2d 6869* |
Deduction version of findcard2 6867. If you also need
(which
doesn't come for free due to ssfiexmid 6854), use findcard2sd 6870 instead.
(Contributed by SO, 16-Jul-2018.)
|
|
|
Theorem | findcard2sd 6870* |
Deduction form of finite set induction . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
14-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | diffisn 6871 |
Subtracting a singleton from a finite set produces a finite set.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | diffifi 6872 |
Subtracting one finite set from another produces a finite set.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 8-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | infnfi 6873 |
An infinite set is not finite. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
20-Feb-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | ominf 6874 |
The set of natural numbers is not finite. Although we supply this theorem
because we can, the more natural way to express " is infinite" is
which is an instance
of domrefg 6745. (Contributed by NM,
2-Jun-1998.)
|
|
|
Theorem | isinfinf 6875* |
An infinite set contains subsets of arbitrarily large finite
cardinality. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jun-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | ac6sfi 6876* |
Existence of a choice function for finite sets. (Contributed by Jeff
Hankins, 26-Jun-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro,
29-Jan-2014.)
|
|
|
Theorem | tridc 6877* |
A trichotomous order is decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
5-Sep-2022.)
|
DECID |
|
Theorem | fimax2gtrilemstep 6878* |
Lemma for fimax2gtri 6879. The induction step. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 5-Sep-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | fimax2gtri 6879* |
A finite set has a maximum under a trichotomous order. (Contributed
by Jim Kingdon, 5-Sep-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | finexdc 6880* |
Decidability of existence, over a finite set and defined by a decidable
proposition. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Jul-2022.)
|
DECID DECID |
|
Theorem | dfrex2fin 6881* |
Relationship between universal and existential quantifiers over a finite
set. Remark in Section 2.2.1 of [Pierik], p. 8. Although Pierik does
not mention the decidability condition explicitly, it does say
"only
finitely many x to check" which means there must be some way of
checking
each value of x. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Jul-2022.)
|
DECID
|
|
Theorem | infm 6882* |
An infinite set is inhabited. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
18-Feb-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | infn0 6883 |
An infinite set is not empty. (Contributed by NM, 23-Oct-2004.)
|
|
|
Theorem | inffiexmid 6884* |
If any given set is either finite or infinite, excluded middle follows.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jun-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | en2eqpr 6885 |
Building a set with two elements. (Contributed by FL, 11-Aug-2008.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.)
|
|
|
Theorem | exmidpw 6886 |
Excluded middle is equivalent to the power set of having two
elements. Remark of [PradicBrown2022], p. 2. (Contributed by
Jim
Kingdon, 30-Jun-2022.)
|
EXMID
|
|
Theorem | exmidpweq 6887 |
Excluded middle is equivalent to the power set of being .
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Jul-2024.)
|
EXMID |
|
Theorem | pw1fin 6888 |
Excluded middle is equivalent to the power set of being finite.
(Contributed by SN and Jim Kingdon, 7-Aug-2024.)
|
EXMID |
|
Theorem | pw1dc0el 6889 |
Another equivalent of excluded middle, which is a mere reformulation of
the definition. (Contributed by BJ, 9-Aug-2024.)
|
EXMID DECID |
|
Theorem | ss1o0el1o 6890 |
Reformulation of ss1o0el1 4183 using instead of .
(Contributed by BJ, 9-Aug-2024.)
|
|
|
Theorem | pw1dc1 6891 |
If, in the set of truth values (the powerset of 1o), equality to 1o is
decidable, then excluded middle holds (and conversely). (Contributed by
BJ and Jim Kingdon, 8-Aug-2024.)
|
EXMID DECID |
|
Theorem | fientri3 6892 |
Trichotomy of dominance for finite sets. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
15-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | nnwetri 6893* |
A natural number is well-ordered by . More specifically, this
order both satisfies and is trichotomous. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 25-Sep-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | onunsnss 6894 |
Adding a singleton to create an ordinal. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
20-Oct-2021.)
|
|
|
Theorem | unfiexmid 6895* |
If the union of any two finite sets is finite, excluded middle follows.
Remark 8.1.17 of [AczelRathjen], p.
74. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro
and Jim Kingdon, 5-Mar-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | unsnfi 6896 |
Adding a singleton to a finite set yields a finite set. (Contributed by
Jim Kingdon, 3-Feb-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | unsnfidcex 6897 |
The condition in unsnfi 6896. This is intended to show that
unsnfi 6896 without that condition would not be provable
but it probably
would need to be strengthened (for example, to imply included middle) to
fully show that. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 6-Feb-2022.)
|
DECID |
|
Theorem | unsnfidcel 6898 |
The condition in unsnfi 6896. This is intended to show that
unsnfi 6896 without that condition would not be provable
but it probably
would need to be strengthened (for example, to imply included middle) to
fully show that. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 6-Feb-2022.)
|
DECID |
|
Theorem | unfidisj 6899 |
The union of two disjoint finite sets is finite. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 25-Feb-2022.)
|
|
|
Theorem | undifdcss 6900* |
Union of complementary parts into whole and decidability. (Contributed
by Jim Kingdon, 17-Jun-2022.)
|
DECID |