Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 14 of 140) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | 3orbi123d 1301 | Deduction joining 3 equivalences to form equivalence of disjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 20-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | 3anbi123d 1302 | Deduction joining 3 equivalences to form equivalence of conjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | 3anbi12d 1303 | Deduction conjoining and adding a conjunct to equivalences. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | 3anbi13d 1304 | Deduction conjoining and adding a conjunct to equivalences. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | 3anbi23d 1305 | Deduction conjoining and adding a conjunct to equivalences. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | 3anbi1d 1306 | Deduction adding conjuncts to an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | 3anbi2d 1307 | Deduction adding conjuncts to an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | 3anbi3d 1308 | Deduction adding conjuncts to an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | 3anim123d 1309 | Deduction joining 3 implications to form implication of conjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | 3orim123d 1310 | Deduction joining 3 implications to form implication of disjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-1997.) |
Theorem | an6 1311 | Rearrangement of 6 conjuncts. (Contributed by NM, 13-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | 3an6 1312 | Analog of an4 576 for triple conjunction. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | 3or6 1313 | Analog of or4 761 for triple conjunction. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Mar-2011.) |
Theorem | mp3an1 1314 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | mp3an2 1315 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | mp3an3 1316 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | mp3an12 1317 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jul-2005.) |
Theorem | mp3an13 1318 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-Jul-2005.) |
Theorem | mp3an23 1319 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-Jul-2005.) |
Theorem | mp3an1i 1320 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jul-2005.) |
Theorem | mp3anl1 1321 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | mp3anl2 1322 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | mp3anl3 1323 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | mp3anr1 1324 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2006.) |
Theorem | mp3anr2 1325 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-2006.) |
Theorem | mp3anr3 1326 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 19-Oct-2007.) |
Theorem | mp3an 1327 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1999.) |
Theorem | mpd3an3 1328 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2007.) |
Theorem | mpd3an23 1329 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 4-Dec-2006.) |
Theorem | mp3and 1330 | A deduction based on modus ponens. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Dec-2016.) |
Theorem | mp3an12i 1331 | mp3an 1327 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with one hypothesis an implication. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | mp3an2i 1332 | mp3an 1327 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with two hypotheses which are implications. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | mp3an3an 1333 | mp3an 1327 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with two hypotheses which are implications. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | mp3an2ani 1334 | An elimination deduction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 17-Oct-2017.) |
Theorem | biimp3a 1335 | Infer implication from a logical equivalence. Similar to biimpa 294. (Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2005.) |
Theorem | biimp3ar 1336 | Infer implication from a logical equivalence. Similar to biimpar 295. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2009.) |
Theorem | 3anandis 1337 | Inference that undistributes a triple conjunction in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 18-Apr-2007.) |
Theorem | 3anandirs 1338 | Inference that undistributes a triple conjunction in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jul-2006.) (Revised by NM, 18-Apr-2007.) |
Theorem | ecased 1339 | Deduction form of disjunctive syllogism. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | ecase23d 1340 | Variation of ecased 1339 with three disjuncts instead of two. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 9-Dec-2017.) |
Even though it is not ordinarily part of propositional calculus, the universal quantifier is introduced here so that the soundness of Definition df-tru 1346 can be checked by the same algorithm that is used for predicate calculus. Its first real use is in Axiom ax-5 1435 in the predicate calculus section below. For those who want propositional calculus to be self-contained, i.e., to use wff variables only, the alternate Definition dftru2 1351 may be adopted and this subsection moved down to the start of the subsection with wex 1480 below. However, the use of dftru2 1351 as a definition requires a more elaborate definition checking algorithm that we prefer to avoid. | ||
Syntax | wal 1341 | Extend wff definition to include the universal quantifier ("for all"). is read " (phi) is true for all ". Typically, in its final application would be replaced with a wff containing a (free) occurrence of the variable , for example . In a universe with a finite number of objects, "for all" is equivalent to a big conjunction (AND) with one wff for each possible case of . When the universe is infinite (as with set theory), such a propositional-calculus equivalent is not possible because an infinitely long formula has no meaning, but conceptually the idea is the same. |
Even though it is not ordinarily part of propositional calculus, the equality predicate is introduced here so that the soundness of definition df-tru 1346 can be checked by the same algorithm as is used for predicate calculus. Its first real use is in Axiom ax-8 1492 in the predicate calculus section below. For those who want propositional calculus to be self-contained, i.e., to use wff variables only, the alternate definition dftru2 1351 may be adopted and this subsection moved down to just above weq 1491 below. However, the use of dftru2 1351 as a definition requires a more elaborate definition checking algorithm that we prefer to avoid. | ||
Syntax | cv 1342 |
This syntax construction states that a variable , which has been
declared to be a setvar variable by $f statement vx, is also a class
expression. This can be justified informally as follows. We know that
the class builder is a class by cab 2151.
Since (when
is distinct from
) we have by
cvjust 2160, we can argue that the syntax " " can be viewed as
an abbreviation for " ". See the
discussion
under the definition of class in [Jech] p.
4 showing that "Every set can
be considered to be a class."
While it is tempting and perhaps occasionally useful to view cv 1342 as a "type conversion" from a setvar variable to a class variable, keep in mind that cv 1342 is intrinsically no different from any other class-building syntax such as cab 2151, cun 3114, or c0 3409. For a general discussion of the theory of classes and the role of cv 1342, see https://us.metamath.org/mpeuni/mmset.html#class 1342. (The description above applies to set theory, not predicate calculus. The purpose of introducing here, and not in set theory where it belongs, is to allow us to express i.e. "prove" the weq 1491 of predicate calculus from the wceq 1343 of set theory, so that we don't overload the connective with two syntax definitions. This is done to prevent ambiguity that would complicate some Metamath parsers.) |
Syntax | wceq 1343 |
Extend wff definition to include class equality.
For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see https://us.metamath.org/mpeuni/mmset.html#class. (The purpose of introducing here, and not in set theory where it belongs, is to allow us to express i.e. "prove" the weq 1491 of predicate calculus in terms of the wceq 1343 of set theory, so that we don't "overload" the connective with two syntax definitions. This is done to prevent ambiguity that would complicate some Metamath parsers. For example, some parsers - although not the Metamath program - stumble on the fact that the in could be the of either weq 1491 or wceq 1343, although mathematically it makes no difference. The class variables and are introduced temporarily for the purpose of this definition but otherwise not used in predicate calculus. See df-cleq 2158 for more information on the set theory usage of wceq 1343.) |
Syntax | wtru 1344 | is a wff. |
Theorem | trujust 1345 | Soundness justification theorem for df-tru 1346. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-Nov-2013.) (Revised by NM, 11-Jul-2019.) |
Definition | df-tru 1346 | Definition of the truth value "true", or "verum", denoted by . This is a tautology, as proved by tru 1347. In this definition, an instance of id 19 is used as the definiens, although any tautology, such as an axiom, can be used in its place. This particular id 19 instance was chosen so this definition can be checked by the same algorithm that is used for predicate calculus. This definition should be referenced directly only by tru 1347, and other proofs should depend on tru 1347 (directly or indirectly) instead of this definition, since there are many alternate ways to define . (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) (Revised by NM, 11-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | tru 1347 | The truth value is provable. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) |
Syntax | wfal 1348 | is a wff. |
Definition | df-fal 1349 | Definition of the truth value "false", or "falsum", denoted by . See also df-tru 1346. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
Theorem | fal 1350 | The truth value is refutable. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 11-Mar-2012.) |
Theorem | dftru2 1351 | An alternate definition of "true". (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) (Revised by BJ, 12-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | mptru 1352 | Eliminate as an antecedent. A proposition implied by is true. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | tbtru 1353 | A proposition is equivalent to itself being equivalent to . (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 14-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | nbfal 1354 | The negation of a proposition is equivalent to itself being equivalent to . (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 14-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | bitru 1355 | A theorem is equivalent to truth. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.) |
Theorem | bifal 1356 | A contradiction is equivalent to falsehood. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.) |
Theorem | falim 1357 | The truth value implies anything. Also called the principle of explosion, or "ex falso quodlibet". (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Anthony Hart, 1-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | falimd 1358 | The truth value implies anything. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) |
Theorem | a1tru 1359 | Anything implies . (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Anthony Hart, 1-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | truan 1360 | True can be removed from a conjunction. (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | dfnot 1361 | Given falsum, we can define the negation of a wff as the statement that a contradiction follows from assuming . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | inegd 1362 | Negation introduction rule from natural deduction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) |
Theorem | pm2.21fal 1363 | If a wff and its negation are provable, then falsum is provable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) |
Theorem | pclem6 1364 | Negation inferred from embedded conjunct. (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2018.) |
Syntax | wxo 1365 | Extend wff definition to include exclusive disjunction ('xor'). |
Definition | df-xor 1366 | Define exclusive disjunction (logical 'xor'). Return true if either the left or right, but not both, are true. Contrast with (wa 103), (wo 698), and (wi 4) . (Contributed by FL, 22-Nov-2010.) (Modified by Jim Kingdon, 1-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | xoranor 1367 | One way of defining exclusive or. Equivalent to df-xor 1366. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon and Mario Carneiro, 1-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | excxor 1368 | This tautology shows that xor is really exclusive. (Contributed by FL, 22-Nov-2010.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
Theorem | xoror 1369 | XOR implies OR. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Apr-2019.) |
Theorem | xorbi2d 1370 | Deduction joining an equivalence and a left operand to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
Theorem | xorbi1d 1371 | Deduction joining an equivalence and a right operand to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
Theorem | xorbi12d 1372 | Deduction joining two equivalences to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
Theorem | xorbi12i 1373 | Equality property for XOR. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) |
Theorem | xorbin 1374 | A consequence of exclusive or. In classical logic the converse also holds. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 8-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | pm5.18im 1375 | One direction of pm5.18dc 873, which holds for all propositions, not just decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | xornbi 1376 | A consequence of exclusive or. For decidable propositions this is an equivalence, as seen at xornbidc 1381. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | xor3dc 1377 | Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Apr-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | xorcom 1378 | is commutative. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 6-Oct-2018.) |
Theorem | pm5.15dc 1379 | A decidable proposition is equivalent to a decidable proposition or its negation. Based on theorem *5.15 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Apr-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | xor2dc 1380 | Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Apr-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | xornbidc 1381 | Exclusive or is equivalent to negated biconditional for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Apr-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | xordc 1382 | Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. Theorem *5.22 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | xordc1 1383 | Exclusive or implies the left proposition is decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Mar-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | nbbndc 1384 | Move negation outside of biconditional, for decidable propositions. Compare Theorem *5.18 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Apr-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | biassdc 1385 |
Associative law for the biconditional, for decidable propositions.
The classical version (without the decidability conditions) is an axiom of system DS in Vladimir Lifschitz, "On calculational proofs", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 113:207-224, 2002, http://www.cs.utexas.edu/users/ai-lab/pub-view.php?PubID=26805, and, interestingly, was not included in Principia Mathematica but was apparently first noted by Jan Lukasiewicz circa 1923. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2018.) |
DECID DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | bilukdc 1386 | Lukasiewicz's shortest axiom for equivalential calculus (but modified to require decidable propositions). Storrs McCall, ed., Polish Logic 1920-1939 (Oxford, 1967), p. 96. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
DECID DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | dfbi3dc 1387 | An alternate definition of the biconditional for decidable propositions. Theorem *5.23 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but with decidability conditions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | pm5.24dc 1388 | Theorem *5.24 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | xordidc 1389 | Conjunction distributes over exclusive-or, for decidable propositions. This is one way to interpret the distributive law of multiplication over addition in modulo 2 arithmetic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Jul-2018.) |
DECID DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | anxordi 1390 | Conjunction distributes over exclusive-or. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
For classical logic, truth tables can be used to define propositional logic operations, by showing the results of those operations for all possible combinations of true () and false (). Although the intuitionistic logic connectives are not as simply defined, and do play similar roles as in classical logic and most theorems from classical logic continue to hold. Here we show that our definitions and axioms produce equivalent results for and as we would get from truth tables for (conjunction aka logical 'and') wa 103, (disjunction aka logical inclusive 'or') wo 698, (implies) wi 4, (not) wn 3, (logical equivalence) df-bi 116, and (exclusive or) df-xor 1366. | ||
Theorem | truantru 1391 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
Theorem | truanfal 1392 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
Theorem | falantru 1393 | A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 23-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | falanfal 1394 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
Theorem | truortru 1395 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
Theorem | truorfal 1396 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
Theorem | falortru 1397 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
Theorem | falorfal 1398 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
Theorem | truimtru 1399 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
Theorem | truimfal 1400 | A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |