Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 64 of 140) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | tfrlemi14d 6301* | The domain of recs is all ordinals (lemma for transfinite recursion). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Jul-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrexlem 6302* | The transfinite recursion function is set-like if the input is. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfri1d 6303* |
Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 1 of 3. Theorem 7.41(1) of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an
additional condition.
The condition is that is defined "everywhere", which is stated here as . Alternately, would suffice. Given a function satisfying that condition, we define a class of all "acceptable" functions. The final function we're interested in is the union recs of them. is then said to be defined by transfinite recursion. The purpose of the 3 parts of this theorem is to demonstrate properties of . In this first part we show that is a function whose domain is all ordinal numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfri2d 6304* | Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 2 of 3. Theorem 7.41(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition on the recursion rule ( as described at tfri1 6333). Here we show that the function has the property that for any function satisfying that condition, the "next" value of is recursively applied to all "previous" values of . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlem3ag 6305* | Lemma for transfinite recursion. This lemma changes some bound variables in (version of tfrlem3ag 6277 but for tfr1on 6318 related lemmas). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Mar-2022.) |
Theorem | tfr1onlem3 6306* | Lemma for transfinite recursion. This lemma changes some bound variables in (version of tfrlem3 6279 but for tfr1on 6318 related lemmas). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2022.) |
Theorem | tfr1onlemssrecs 6307* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. The union of functions acceptable for tfr1on 6318 is a subset of recs. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlemsucfn 6308* | We can extend an acceptable function by one element to produce a function. Lemma for tfr1on 6318. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlemsucaccv 6309* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. We can extend an acceptable function by one element to produce an acceptable function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlembacc 6310* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. Each element of is an acceptable function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlembxssdm 6311* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. The union of is defined on all elements of . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlembfn 6312* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. The union of is a function defined on . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlembex 6313* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. The set exists. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlemubacc 6314* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. The union of satisfies the recursion rule. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlemex 6315* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlemaccex 6316* |
We can define an acceptable function on any element of .
As with many of the transfinite recursion theorems, we have hypotheses that state that is a function and that it is defined up to . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1onlemres 6317* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. Recursion is defined on an ordinal if the characteristic function is defined up to a suitable point. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfr1on 6318* | Recursion is defined on an ordinal if the characteristic function is defined up to a suitable point. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfri1dALT 6319* |
Alternate proof of tfri1d 6303 in terms of tfr1on 6318.
Although this does show that the tfr1on 6318 proof is general enough to also prove tfri1d 6303, the tfri1d 6303 proof is simpler in places because it does not need to deal with being any ordinal. For that reason, we have both proofs. (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllemssrecs 6320* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. The union of functions acceptable for tfrcl 6332 is a subset of recs. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllemsucfn 6321* | We can extend an acceptable function by one element to produce a function. Lemma for tfrcl 6332. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllemsucaccv 6322* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. We can extend an acceptable function by one element to produce an acceptable function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllembacc 6323* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. Each element of is an acceptable function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllembxssdm 6324* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. The union of is defined on all elements of . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllembfn 6325* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. The union of is a function defined on . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllembex 6326* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. The set exists. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllemubacc 6327* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. The union of satisfies the recursion rule. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllemex 6328* | Lemma for tfrcl 6332. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllemaccex 6329* |
We can define an acceptable function on any element of .
As with many of the transfinite recursion theorems, we have hypotheses that state that is a function and that it is defined up to . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcllemres 6330* | Lemma for tfr1on 6318. Recursion is defined on an ordinal if the characteristic function is defined up to a suitable point. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcldm 6331* | Recursion is defined on an ordinal if the characteristic function satisfies a closure hypothesis up to a suitable point. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrcl 6332* | Closure for transfinite recursion. As with tfr1on 6318, the characteristic function must be defined up to a suitable point, not necessarily on all ordinals. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Mar-2022.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfri1 6333* |
Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 1 of 3. Theorem 7.41(1) of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an
additional condition.
The condition is that is defined "everywhere", which is stated here as . Alternately, would suffice. Given a function satisfying that condition, we define a class of all "acceptable" functions. The final function we're interested in is the union recs of them. is then said to be defined by transfinite recursion. The purpose of the 3 parts of this theorem is to demonstrate properties of . In this first part we show that is a function whose domain is all ordinal numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-May-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfri2 6334* | Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 2 of 3. Theorem 7.41(2) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition on the recursion rule ( as described at tfri1 6333). Here we show that the function has the property that for any function satisfying that condition, the "next" value of is recursively applied to all "previous" values of . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfri3 6335* | Principle of Transfinite Recursion, part 3 of 3. Theorem 7.41(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 47, with an additional condition on the recursion rule ( as described at tfri1 6333). Finally, we show that is unique. We do this by showing that any class with the same properties of that we showed in parts 1 and 2 is identical to . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | tfrex 6336* | The transfinite recursion function is set-like if the input is. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.) |
recs | ||
Syntax | crdg 6337 | Extend class notation with the recursive definition generator, with characteristic function and initial value . |
Definition | df-irdg 6338* |
Define a recursive definition generator on (the class of ordinal
numbers) with characteristic function and initial value .
This rather amazing operation allows us to define, with compact direct
definitions, functions that are usually defined in textbooks only with
indirect self-referencing recursive definitions. A recursive definition
requires advanced metalogic to justify - in particular, eliminating a
recursive definition is very difficult and often not even shown in
textbooks. On the other hand, the elimination of a direct definition is
a matter of simple mechanical substitution. The price paid is the
daunting complexity of our operation (especially when df-recs 6273
that it is built on is also eliminated). But once we get past this
hurdle, definitions that would otherwise be recursive become relatively
simple. In classical logic it would be easier to divide this definition
into cases based on whether the domain of is zero, a successor, or
a limit ordinal. Cases do not (in general) work that way in
intuitionistic logic, so instead we choose a definition which takes the
union of all the results of the characteristic function for ordinals in
the domain of .
This means that this definition has the expected
properties for increasing and continuous ordinal functions, which
include ordinal addition and multiplication.
For finite recursion we also define df-frec 6359 and for suitable characteristic functions df-frec 6359 yields the same result as restricted to , as seen at frecrdg 6376. Note: We introduce with the philosophical goal of being able to eliminate all definitions with direct mechanical substitution and to verify easily the soundness of definitions. Metamath itself has no built-in technical limitation that prevents multiple-part recursive definitions in the traditional textbook style. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-May-2019.) |
recs | ||
Theorem | rdgeq1 6339 | Equality theorem for the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.) |
Theorem | rdgeq2 6340 | Equality theorem for the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.) |
Theorem | rdgfun 6341 | The recursive definition generator is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.) |
Theorem | rdgtfr 6342* | The recursion rule for the recursive definition generator is defined everywhere. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-May-2020.) |
Theorem | rdgruledefgg 6343* | The recursion rule for the recursive definition generator is defined everywhere. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgruledefg 6344* | The recursion rule for the recursive definition generator is defined everywhere. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgexggg 6345 | The recursive definition generator produces a set on a set input. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgexgg 6346 | The recursive definition generator produces a set on a set input. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgifnon 6347 | The recursive definition generator is a function on ordinal numbers. The condition states that the characteristic function is defined for all sets (being defined for all ordinals might be enough if being used in a manner similar to rdgon 6354; in cases like df-oadd 6388 either presumably could work). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgifnon2 6348* | The recursive definition generator is a function on ordinal numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-May-2020.) |
Theorem | rdgivallem 6349* | Value of the recursive definition generator. Lemma for rdgival 6350 which simplifies the value further. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | rdgival 6350* | Value of the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgss 6351 | Subset and recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jul-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgisuc1 6352* |
One way of describing the value of the recursive definition generator at
a successor. There is no condition on the characteristic function
other than
. Given that, the resulting expression
encompasses both the expected successor term
but also
terms that correspond to
the initial value and to limit ordinals
.
If we add conditions on the characteristic function, we can show tighter results such as rdgisucinc 6353. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Jun-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgisucinc 6353* |
Value of the recursive definition generator at a successor.
This can be thought of as a generalization of oasuc 6432 and omsuc 6440. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Aug-2019.) |
Theorem | rdgon 6354* | Evaluating the recursive definition generator produces an ordinal. There is a hypothesis that the characteristic function produces ordinals on ordinal arguments. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2019.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 13-Apr-2022.) |
Theorem | rdg0 6355 | The initial value of the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2014.) |
Theorem | rdg0g 6356 | The initial value of the recursive definition generator. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | rdgexg 6357 | The recursive definition generator produces a set on a set input. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.) |
Syntax | cfrec 6358 | Extend class notation with the finite recursive definition generator, with characteristic function and initial value . |
frec | ||
Definition | df-frec 6359* |
Define a recursive definition generator on (the class of finite
ordinals) with characteristic function and initial value .
This rather amazing operation allows us to define, with compact direct
definitions, functions that are usually defined in textbooks only with
indirect self-referencing recursive definitions. A recursive definition
requires advanced metalogic to justify - in particular, eliminating a
recursive definition is very difficult and often not even shown in
textbooks. On the other hand, the elimination of a direct definition is
a matter of simple mechanical substitution. The price paid is the
daunting complexity of our frec operation (especially when df-recs 6273
that it is built on is also eliminated). But once we get past this
hurdle, definitions that would otherwise be recursive become relatively
simple; see frec0g 6365 and frecsuc 6375.
Unlike with transfinite recursion, finite recurson can readily divide definitions and proofs into zero and successor cases, because even without excluded middle we have theorems such as nn0suc 4581. The analogous situation with transfinite recursion - being able to say that an ordinal is zero, successor, or limit - is enabled by excluded middle and thus is not available to us. For the characteristic functions which satisfy the conditions given at frecrdg 6376, this definition and df-irdg 6338 restricted to produce the same result. Note: We introduce frec with the philosophical goal of being able to eliminate all definitions with direct mechanical substitution and to verify easily the soundness of definitions. Metamath itself has no built-in technical limitation that prevents multiple-part recursive definitions in the traditional textbook style. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 10-Aug-2019.) |
frec recs | ||
Theorem | freceq1 6360 | Equality theorem for the finite recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-May-2020.) |
frec frec | ||
Theorem | freceq2 6361 | Equality theorem for the finite recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-May-2020.) |
frec frec | ||
Theorem | frecex 6362 | Finite recursion produces a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Aug-2021.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | frecfun 6363 | Finite recursion produces a function. See also frecfnom 6369 which also states that the domain of that function is but which puts conditions on and . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Feb-2022.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | nffrec 6364 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the finite recursive definition generator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-May-2020.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | frec0g 6365 | The initial value resulting from finite recursive definition generation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-May-2020.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | frecabex 6366* | The class abstraction from df-frec 6359 exists. This is a lemma for other finite recursion proofs. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-May-2020.) |
Theorem | frecabcl 6367* | The class abstraction from df-frec 6359 exists. Unlike frecabex 6366 the function only needs to be defined on , not all sets. This is a lemma for other finite recursion proofs. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Mar-2022.) |
Theorem | frectfr 6368* |
Lemma to connect transfinite recursion theorems with finite recursion.
That is, given the conditions
and on
frec , we
want to be able to apply tfri1d 6303 or tfri2d 6304,
and this lemma lets us satisfy hypotheses of those theorems.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Aug-2019.) |
Theorem | frecfnom 6369* | The function generated by finite recursive definition generation is a function on omega. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-May-2020.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | freccllem 6370* | Lemma for freccl 6371. Just giving a name to a common expression to simplify the proof. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Mar-2022.) |
recs frec | ||
Theorem | freccl 6371* | Closure for finite recursion. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Mar-2022.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | frecfcllem 6372* | Lemma for frecfcl 6373. Just giving a name to a common expression to simplify the proof. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Mar-2022.) |
recs frec | ||
Theorem | frecfcl 6373* | Finite recursion yields a function on the natural numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Mar-2022.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | frecsuclem 6374* | Lemma for frecsuc 6375. Just giving a name to a common expression to simplify the proof. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Mar-2022.) |
frec frec | ||
Theorem | frecsuc 6375* | The successor value resulting from finite recursive definition generation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Mar-2022.) |
frec frec | ||
Theorem | frecrdg 6376* |
Transfinite recursion restricted to omega.
Given a suitable characteristic function, df-frec 6359 produces the same results as df-irdg 6338 restricted to . Presumably the theorem would also hold if were changed to . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Aug-2019.) |
frec | ||
Syntax | c1o 6377 | Extend the definition of a class to include the ordinal number 1. |
Syntax | c2o 6378 | Extend the definition of a class to include the ordinal number 2. |
Syntax | c3o 6379 | Extend the definition of a class to include the ordinal number 3. |
Syntax | c4o 6380 | Extend the definition of a class to include the ordinal number 4. |
Syntax | coa 6381 | Extend the definition of a class to include the ordinal addition operation. |
Syntax | comu 6382 | Extend the definition of a class to include the ordinal multiplication operation. |
Syntax | coei 6383 | Extend the definition of a class to include the ordinal exponentiation operation. |
↑o | ||
Definition | df-1o 6384 | Define the ordinal number 1. (Contributed by NM, 29-Oct-1995.) |
Definition | df-2o 6385 | Define the ordinal number 2. (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2004.) |
Definition | df-3o 6386 | Define the ordinal number 3. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2013.) |
Definition | df-4o 6387 | Define the ordinal number 4. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2013.) |
Definition | df-oadd 6388* | Define the ordinal addition operation. (Contributed by NM, 3-May-1995.) |
Definition | df-omul 6389* | Define the ordinal multiplication operation. (Contributed by NM, 26-Aug-1995.) |
Definition | df-oexpi 6390* |
Define the ordinal exponentiation operation.
This definition is similar to a conventional definition of exponentiation except that it defines ↑o to be for all , in order to avoid having different cases for whether the base is or not. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Jul-2019.) |
↑o | ||
Theorem | 1on 6391 | Ordinal 1 is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 29-Oct-1995.) |
Theorem | 1oex 6392 | Ordinal 1 is a set. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Jul-2022.) |
Theorem | 2on 6393 | Ordinal 2 is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
Theorem | 2on0 6394 | Ordinal two is not zero. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 17-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | 3on 6395 | Ordinal 3 is an ordinal number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2016.) |
Theorem | 4on 6396 | Ordinal 3 is an ordinal number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2016.) |
Theorem | df1o2 6397 | Expanded value of the ordinal number 1. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2002.) |
Theorem | df2o3 6398 | Expanded value of the ordinal number 2. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Aug-2015.) |
Theorem | df2o2 6399 | Expanded value of the ordinal number 2. (Contributed by NM, 29-Jan-2004.) |
Theorem | 1n0 6400 | Ordinal one is not equal to ordinal zero. (Contributed by NM, 26-Dec-2004.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |