Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 19 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | hbsb3 1801 | If is not free in , is not free in . (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfs1 1802 | If is not free in , is not free in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | sbcof2 1803 | Version of sbco 1961 where is not free in . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | spimv 1804* | A version of spim 1731 with a distinct variable requirement instead of a bound-variable hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | aev 1805* | A "distinctor elimination" lemma with no restrictions on variables in the consequent, proved without using ax-16 1807. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2006.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | ax16 1806* |
Theorem showing that ax-16 1807 is redundant if ax-17 1519 is included in the
axiom system. The important part of the proof is provided by aev 1805.
See ax16ALT 1852 for an alternate proof that does not require ax-10 1498 or ax12 1505. This theorem should not be referenced in any proof. Instead, use ax-16 1807 below so that theorems needing ax-16 1807 can be more easily identified. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2006.) |
Axiom | ax-16 1807* |
Axiom of Distinct Variables. The only axiom of predicate calculus
requiring that variables be distinct (if we consider ax-17 1519 to be a
metatheorem and not an axiom). Axiom scheme C16' in [Megill] p. 448 (p.
16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear in the
literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by
cases. It is a somewhat bizarre axiom since the antecedent is always
false in set theory, but nonetheless it is technically necessary as you
can see from its uses.
This axiom is redundant if we include ax-17 1519; see Theorem ax16 1806. This axiom is obsolete and should no longer be used. It is proved above as Theorem ax16 1806. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | dveeq2 1808* | Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
Theorem | dveeq2or 1809* | Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. Like dveeq2 1808 but connecting by a disjunction rather than negation and implication makes the theorem stronger in intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | dvelimfALT2 1810* | Proof of dvelimf 2008 using dveeq2 1808 (shown as the last hypothesis) instead of ax12 1505. This shows that ax12 1505 could be replaced by dveeq2 1808 (the last hypothesis). (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 21-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | nd5 1811* | A lemma for proving conditionless ZFC axioms. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jan-2002.) |
Theorem | exlimdv 1812* | Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | ax11v2 1813* | Recovery of ax11o 1815 from ax11v 1820 without using ax-11 1499. The hypothesis is even weaker than ax11v 1820, with both distinct from and not occurring in . Thus the hypothesis provides an alternate axiom that can be used in place of ax11o 1815. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | ax11a2 1814* | Derive ax-11o 1816 from a hypothesis in the form of ax-11 1499. The hypothesis is even weaker than ax-11 1499, with both distinct from and not occurring in . Thus the hypothesis provides an alternate axiom that can be used in place of ax11o 1815. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2007.) |
Theorem | ax11o 1815 |
Derivation of set.mm's original ax-11o 1816 from the shorter ax-11 1499 that
has replaced it.
An open problem is whether this theorem can be proved without relying on ax-16 1807 or ax-17 1519. Normally, ax11o 1815 should be used rather than ax-11o 1816, except by theorems specifically studying the latter's properties. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2007.) |
Axiom | ax-11o 1816 |
Axiom ax-11o 1816 ("o" for "old") was the
original version of ax-11 1499,
before it was discovered (in Jan. 2007) that the shorter ax-11 1499 could
replace it. It appears as Axiom scheme C15' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of
the preprint). It is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and Axiom C8 of
[Monk2] p. 105, from which it can be proved
by cases. To understand this
theorem more easily, think of " ..." as informally
meaning "if
and are distinct
variables, then..." The
antecedent becomes false if the same variable is substituted for and
, ensuring the
theorem is sound whenever this is the case. In some
later theorems, we call an antecedent of the form a
"distinctor."
This axiom is redundant, as shown by Theorem ax11o 1815. This axiom is obsolete and should no longer be used. It is proved above as Theorem ax11o 1815. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | albidv 1817* | Formula-building rule for universal quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | exbidv 1818* | Formula-building rule for existential quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | ax11b 1819 | A bidirectional version of ax-11o 1816. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-2006.) |
Theorem | ax11v 1820* | This is a version of ax-11o 1816 when the variables are distinct. Axiom (C8) of [Monk2] p. 105. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | ax11ev 1821* | Analogue to ax11v 1820 for existential quantification. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | equs5 1822 | Lemma used in proofs of substitution properties. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equs5or 1823 | Lemma used in proofs of substitution properties. Like equs5 1822 but, in intuitionistic logic, replacing negation and implication with disjunction makes this a stronger result. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sb3 1824 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sb4 1825 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sb4or 1826 | One direction of a simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. Similar to sb4 1825 but stronger in intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sb4b 1827 | Simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) |
Theorem | sb4bor 1828 | Simplified definition of substitution when variables are distinct, expressed via disjunction. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | hbsb2 1829 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | nfsb2or 1830 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for substitution. Similar to hbsb2 1829 but in intuitionistic logic a disjunction is stronger than an implication. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sbequilem 1831 | Propositional logic lemma used in the sbequi 1832 proof. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sbequi 1832 | An equality theorem for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof modified by Jim Kingdon, 1-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sbequ 1833 | An equality theorem for substitution. Used in proof of Theorem 9.7 in [Megill] p. 449 (p. 16 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | drsb2 1834 | Formula-building lemma for use with the Distinctor Reduction Theorem. Part of Theorem 9.4 of [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of preprint). (Contributed by NM, 27-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | spsbe 1835 | A specialization theorem, mostly the same as Theorem 19.8 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 29-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | spsbim 1836 | Specialization of implication. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 21-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | spsbbi 1837 | Specialization of biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 21-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sbbidh 1838 | Deduction substituting both sides of a biconditional. New proofs should use sbbid 1839 instead. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | sbbid 1839 | Deduction substituting both sides of a biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1993.) |
Theorem | sbequ8 1840 | Elimination of equality from antecedent after substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof revised by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sbft 1841 | Substitution has no effect on a nonfree variable. (Contributed by NM, 30-May-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 3-May-2018.) |
Theorem | sbid2h 1842 | An identity law for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | sbid2 1843 | An identity law for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sbidm 1844 | An idempotent law for substitution. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jun-1994.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 21-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sb5rf 1845 | Reversed substitution. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | sb6rf 1846 | Reversed substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | sb8h 1847 | Substitution of variable in universal quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sb8eh 1848 | Substitution of variable in existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sb8 1849 | Substitution of variable in universal quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sb8e 1850 | Substitution of variable in existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | ax16i 1851* | Inference with ax-16 1807 as its conclusion, that does not require ax-10 1498, ax-11 1499, or ax12 1505 for its proof. The hypotheses may be eliminable without one or more of these axioms in special cases. (Contributed by NM, 20-May-2008.) |
Theorem | ax16ALT 1852* | Version of ax16 1806 that does not require ax-10 1498 or ax12 1505 for its proof. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-2008.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | spv 1853* | Specialization, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | spimev 1854* | Distinct-variable version of spime 1734. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | speiv 1855* | Inference from existential specialization, using implicit substitition. (Contributed by NM, 19-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | equvin 1856* | A variable introduction law for equality. Lemma 15 of [Monk2] p. 109. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | a16g 1857* | A generalization of Axiom ax-16 1807. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | a16gb 1858* | A generalization of Axiom ax-16 1807. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | a16nf 1859* | If there is only one element in the universe, then everything satisfies . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | 2albidv 1860* | Formula-building rule for 2 existential quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 4-Mar-1997.) |
Theorem | 2exbidv 1861* | Formula-building rule for 2 existential quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 1-May-1995.) |
Theorem | 3exbidv 1862* | Formula-building rule for 3 existential quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 1-May-1995.) |
Theorem | 4exbidv 1863* | Formula-building rule for 4 existential quantifiers (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-1995.) |
Theorem | 19.9v 1864* | Special case of Theorem 19.9 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 28-May-1995.) (Revised by NM, 21-May-2007.) |
Theorem | exlimdd 1865 | Existential elimination rule of natural deduction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) |
Theorem | 19.21v 1866* | Special case of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. Notational convention: We sometimes suffix with "v" the label of a theorem eliminating a hypothesis such as in 19.21 1576 via the use of distinct variable conditions combined with ax-17 1519. Conversely, we sometimes suffix with "f" the label of a theorem introducing such a hypothesis to eliminate the need for the distinct variable condition; e.g., euf 2024 derived from df-eu 2022. The "f" stands for "not free in" which is less restrictive than "does not occur in". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | alrimiv 1867* | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | alrimivv 1868* | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | alrimdv 1869* | Deduction from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 10-Feb-1997.) |
Theorem | nfdv 1870* | Apply the definition of not-free in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
Theorem | 2ax17 1871* | Quantification of two variables over a formula in which they do not occur. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 12-Apr-2011.) |
Theorem | alimdv 1872* | Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | eximdv 1873* | Deduction from Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | 2alimdv 1874* | Deduction from Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | 2eximdv 1875* | Deduction from Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-1995.) |
Theorem | 19.23v 1876* | Special case of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 28-Jun-1998.) |
Theorem | 19.23vv 1877* | Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90 extended to two variables. (Contributed by NM, 10-Aug-2004.) |
Theorem | sb56 1878* | Two equivalent ways of expressing the proper substitution of for in , when and are distinct. Theorem 6.2 of [Quine] p. 40. The proof does not involve df-sb 1756. (Contributed by NM, 14-Apr-2008.) |
Theorem | sb6 1879* | Equivalence for substitution. Compare Theorem 6.2 of [Quine] p. 40. Also proved as Lemmas 16 and 17 of [Tarski] p. 70. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 14-Apr-2008.) |
Theorem | sb5 1880* | Equivalence for substitution. Similar to Theorem 6.1 of [Quine] p. 40. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 14-Apr-2008.) |
Theorem | sbnv 1881* | Version of sbn 1945 where and are distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | sbanv 1882* | Version of sban 1948 where and are distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | sborv 1883* | Version of sbor 1947 where and are distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 3-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sbi1v 1884* | Forward direction of sbimv 1886. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Dec-2017.) |
Theorem | sbi2v 1885* | Reverse direction of sbimv 1886. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sbimv 1886* | Intuitionistic proof of sbim 1946 where and are distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | sblimv 1887* | Version of sblim 1950 where and are distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jan-2018.) |
Theorem | pm11.53 1888* | Theorem *11.53 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 164. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 24-May-2011.) |
Theorem | exlimivv 1889* | Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1995.) |
Theorem | exlimdvv 1890* | Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | exlimddv 1891* | Existential elimination rule of natural deduction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jun-2016.) |
Theorem | 19.27v 1892* | Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jun-2004.) |
Theorem | 19.28v 1893* | Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2004.) |
Theorem | 19.36aiv 1894* | Inference from Theorem 19.36 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.41v 1895* | Special case of Theorem 19.41 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | 19.41vv 1896* | Theorem 19.41 of [Margaris] p. 90 with 2 quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | 19.41vvv 1897* | Theorem 19.41 of [Margaris] p. 90 with 3 quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | 19.41vvvv 1898* | Theorem 19.41 of [Margaris] p. 90 with 4 quantifiers. (Contributed by FL, 14-Jul-2007.) |
Theorem | 19.42v 1899* | Special case of Theorem 19.42 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | spvv 1900* | Version of spv 1853 with a disjoint variable condition. (Contributed by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |