Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 124 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | pcfaclem 12301 | Lemma for pcfac 12302. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2014.) |
Theorem | pcfac 12302* | Calculate the prime count of a factorial. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Mar-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 21-May-2014.) |
Theorem | pcbc 12303* | Calculate the prime count of a binomial coefficient. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Mar-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 21-May-2014.) |
Theorem | qexpz 12304 | If a power of a rational number is an integer, then the number is an integer. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Aug-2015.) |
Theorem | expnprm 12305 | A second or higher power of a rational number is not a prime number. Or by contraposition, the n-th root of a prime number is not rational. Suggested by Norm Megill. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Aug-2015.) |
Theorem | oddprmdvds 12306* | Every positive integer which is not a power of two is divisible by an odd prime number. (Contributed by AV, 6-Aug-2021.) |
Theorem | prmpwdvds 12307 | A relation involving divisibility by a prime power. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | pockthlem 12308 | Lemma for pockthg 12309. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | pockthg 12309* | The generalized Pocklington's theorem. If where , then is prime if and only if for every prime factor of , there is an such that and . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | pockthi 12310 | Pocklington's theorem, which gives a sufficient criterion for a number to be prime. This is the preferred method for verifying large primes, being much more efficient to compute than trial division. This form has been optimized for application to specific large primes; see pockthg 12309 for a more general closed-form version. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Mar-2014.) |
Theorem | infpnlem1 12311* | Lemma for infpn 12313. The smallest divisor (greater than 1) of is a prime greater than . (Contributed by NM, 5-May-2005.) |
Theorem | infpnlem2 12312* | Lemma for infpn 12313. For any positive integer , there exists a prime number greater than . (Contributed by NM, 5-May-2005.) |
Theorem | infpn 12313* | There exist infinitely many prime numbers: for any positive integer , there exists a prime number greater than . (See infpn2 12411 for the equinumerosity version.) (Contributed by NM, 1-Jun-2006.) |
Theorem | prmunb 12314* | The primes are unbounded. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 28-Nov-2012.) |
Theorem | 1arithlem1 12315* | Lemma for 1arith 12319. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2014.) |
Theorem | 1arithlem2 12316* | Lemma for 1arith 12319. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2014.) |
Theorem | 1arithlem3 12317* | Lemma for 1arith 12319. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2014.) |
Theorem | 1arithlem4 12318* | Lemma for 1arith 12319. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2014.) |
Theorem | 1arith 12319* | Fundamental theorem of arithmetic, where a prime factorization is represented as a sequence of prime exponents, for which only finitely many primes have nonzero exponent. The function maps the set of positive integers one-to-one onto the set of prime factorizations . (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 17-Nov-2012.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2014.) |
Theorem | 1arith2 12320* | Fundamental theorem of arithmetic, where a prime factorization is represented as a finite monotonic 1-based sequence of primes. Every positive integer has a unique prime factorization. Theorem 1.10 in [ApostolNT] p. 17. This is Metamath 100 proof #80. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 17-Nov-2012.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2014.) |
Syntax | cgz 12321 | Extend class notation with the set of gaussian integers. |
Definition | df-gz 12322 | Define the set of gaussian integers, which are complex numbers whose real and imaginary parts are integers. (Note that the is actually part of the symbol token and has no independent meaning.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | elgz 12323 | Elementhood in the gaussian integers. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gzcn 12324 | A gaussian integer is a complex number. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | zgz 12325 | An integer is a gaussian integer. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | igz 12326 | is a gaussian integer. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gznegcl 12327 | The gaussian integers are closed under negation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gzcjcl 12328 | The gaussian integers are closed under conjugation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gzaddcl 12329 | The gaussian integers are closed under addition. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gzmulcl 12330 | The gaussian integers are closed under multiplication. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gzreim 12331 | Construct a gaussian integer from real and imaginary parts. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gzsubcl 12332 | The gaussian integers are closed under subtraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | gzabssqcl 12333 | The squared norm of a gaussian integer is an integer. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem5 12334 | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem6 12335 | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem7 12336 | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem8 12337 | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem9 12338 | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem10 12339 | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem1 12340* | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . The set is the set of all numbers that are expressible as a sum of four squares. Our goal is to show that ; here we show one subset direction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem2 12341* | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . Change bound variables in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem3 12342* | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . Sufficient condition to be in . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem4a 12343* | Lemma for 4sqlem4 12344. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | 4sqlem4 12344* | Lemma for 4sq (not yet proved here) . We can express the four-square property more compactly in terms of gaussian integers, because the norms of gaussian integers are exactly sums of two squares. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | mul4sqlem 12345* | Lemma for mul4sq 12346: algebraic manipulations. The extra assumptions involving would let us know not just that the product is a sum of squares, but also that it preserves divisibility by . (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | mul4sq 12346* | Euler's four-square identity: The product of two sums of four squares is also a sum of four squares. This is usually quoted as an explicit formula involving eight real variables; we save some time by working with complex numbers (gaussian integers) instead, so that we only have to work with four variables, and also hiding the actual formula for the product in the proof of mul4sqlem 12345. (For the curious, the explicit formula that is used is .) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Jul-2014.) |
Theorem | oddennn 12347 | There are as many odd positive integers as there are positive integers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2022.) |
Theorem | evenennn 12348 | There are as many even positive integers as there are positive integers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-May-2022.) |
Theorem | xpnnen 12349 | The Cartesian product of the set of positive integers with itself is equinumerous to the set of positive integers. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-2004.) |
Theorem | xpomen 12350 | The Cartesian product of omega (the set of ordinal natural numbers) with itself is equinumerous to omega. Exercise 1 of [Enderton] p. 133. (Contributed by NM, 23-Jul-2004.) |
Theorem | xpct 12351 | The cartesian product of two sets dominated by is dominated by . (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 24-Sep-2017.) |
Theorem | unennn 12352 | The union of two disjoint countably infinite sets is countably infinite. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-May-2022.) |
Theorem | znnen 12353 | The set of integers and the set of positive integers are equinumerous. Corollary 8.1.23 of [AczelRathjen], p. 75. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-2004.) |
Theorem | ennnfonelemdc 12354* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. A direct consequence of fidcenumlemrk 6931. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jul-2023.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemk 12355* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jul-2023.) |
Theorem | ennnfonelemj0 12356* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Initial state for . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemjn 12357* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Non-initial state for . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemg 12358* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Closure for . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemh 12359* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 8-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelem0 12360* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Initial value. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemp1 12361* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Value of at a successor. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelem1 12362* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Second value. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemom 12363* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. yields finite sequences. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemhdmp1 12364* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Domain at a successor where we need to add an element to the sequence. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemss 12365* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. We only add elements to as the index increases. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfoneleminc 12366* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. We only add elements to as the index increases. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemkh 12367* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Because we add zero or one entries for each new index, the length of each sequence is no greater than its index. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemhf1o 12368* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Each of the functions in is one to one and onto an image of . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemex 12369* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. Extending the sequence to include an additional element. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemhom 12370* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. The sequences in increase in length without bound if you go out far enough. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemrnh 12371* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. A consequence of ennnfonelemss 12365. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemfun 12372* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. is a function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemf1 12373* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. is one-to-one. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemrn 12374* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. is onto . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemdm 12375* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. The function is defined everywhere. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemen 12376* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. The result. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jul-2023.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemnn0 12377* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. A version of ennnfonelemen 12376 expressed in terms of instead of . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Oct-2022.) |
DECID frec | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemr 12378* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. The interesting direction, expressed in deduction form. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | ennnfonelemim 12379* | Lemma for ennnfone 12380. The trivial direction. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | ennnfone 12380* | A condition for a set being countably infinite. Corollary 8.1.13 of [AczelRathjen], p. 73. Roughly speaking, the condition says that is countable (that's the part, as seen in theorems like ctm 7086), infinite (that's the part about being able to find an element of distinct from any mapping of a natural number via ), and has decidable equality. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Oct-2022.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | exmidunben 12381* | If any unbounded set of positive integers is equinumerous to , then the Limited Principle of Omniscience (LPO) implies excluded middle. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Jul-2023.) |
Omni EXMID | ||
Theorem | ctinfomlemom 12382* | Lemma for ctinfom 12383. Converting between and . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Aug-2023.) |
frec | ||
Theorem | ctinfom 12383* | A condition for a set being countably infinite. Restates ennnfone 12380 in terms of and function image. Like ennnfone 12380 the condition can be summarized as being countable, infinite, and having decidable equality. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Aug-2023.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | inffinp1 12384* | An infinite set contains an element not contained in a given finite subset. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Aug-2023.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | ctinf 12385* | A set is countably infinite if and only if it has decidable equality, is countable, and is infinite. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Aug-2023.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | qnnen 12386 | The rational numbers are countably infinite. Corollary 8.1.23 of [AczelRathjen], p. 75. This is Metamath 100 proof #3. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Aug-2023.) |
Theorem | enctlem 12387* | Lemma for enct 12388. One direction of the biconditional. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Dec-2023.) |
⊔ ⊔ | ||
Theorem | enct 12388* | Countability is invariant relative to equinumerosity. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Dec-2023.) |
⊔ ⊔ | ||
Theorem | ctiunctlemu1st 12389* | Lemma for ctiunct 12395. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Oct-2023.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | ctiunctlemu2nd 12390* | Lemma for ctiunct 12395. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Oct-2023.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | ctiunctlemuom 12391 | Lemma for ctiunct 12395. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Oct-2023.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | ctiunctlemudc 12392* | Lemma for ctiunct 12395. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Oct-2023.) |
DECID DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | ctiunctlemf 12393* | Lemma for ctiunct 12395. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Oct-2023.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | ctiunctlemfo 12394* | Lemma for ctiunct 12395. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Oct-2023.) |
DECID DECID | ||
Theorem | ctiunct 12395* |
A sequence of enumerations gives an enumeration of the union. We refer
to "sequence of enumerations" rather than "countably many
countable
sets" because the hypothesis provides more than countability for
each
: it refers to together with the
which enumerates it. Theorem 8.1.19 of [AczelRathjen], p. 74.
For "countably many countable sets" the key hypothesis would be ⊔ . This is almost omiunct 12399 (which uses countable choice) although that is for a countably infinite collection not any countable collection. Compare with the case of two sets instead of countably many, as seen at unct 12397, which says that the union of two countable sets is countable . The proof proceeds by mapping a natural number to a pair of natural numbers (by xpomen 12350) and using the first number to map to an element of and the second number to map to an element of B(x) . In this way we are able to map to every element of . Although it would be possible to work directly with countability expressed as ⊔ , we instead use functions from subsets of the natural numbers via ctssdccl 7088 and ctssdc 7090. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Oct-2023.) |
⊔ ⊔ ⊔ | ||
Theorem | ctiunctal 12396* | Variation of ctiunct 12395 which allows to be present in . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2024.) |
⊔ ⊔ ⊔ | ||
Theorem | unct 12397* | The union of two countable sets is countable. Corollary 8.1.20 of [AczelRathjen], p. 75. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Nov-2023.) |
⊔ ⊔ ⊔ | ||
Theorem | omctfn 12398* | Using countable choice to find a sequence of enumerations for a collection of countable sets. Lemma 8.1.27 of [AczelRathjen], p. 77. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Apr-2024.) |
CCHOICE ⊔ ⊔ | ||
Theorem | omiunct 12399* | The union of a countably infinite collection of countable sets is countable. Theorem 8.1.28 of [AczelRathjen], p. 78. Compare with ctiunct 12395 which has a stronger hypothesis but does not require countable choice. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2024.) |
CCHOICE ⊔ ⊔ | ||
Theorem | ssomct 12400* | A decidable subset of is countable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Sep-2024.) |
DECID ⊔ |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |