Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 44 of 140) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | sotricim 4301 | One direction of sotritric 4302 holds for all weakly linear orders. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Sep-2019.) |
Theorem | sotritric 4302 | A trichotomy relationship, given a trichotomous order. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Sep-2019.) |
Theorem | sotritrieq 4303 | A trichotomy relationship, given a trichotomous order. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Dec-2019.) |
Theorem | so0 4304 | Any relation is a strict ordering of the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
Syntax | wfrfor 4305 | Extend wff notation to include the well-founded predicate. |
FrFor | ||
Syntax | wfr 4306 | Extend wff notation to include the well-founded predicate. Read: ' is a well-founded relation on .' |
Syntax | wse 4307 | Extend wff notation to include the set-like predicate. Read: ' is set-like on .' |
Se | ||
Syntax | wwe 4308 | Extend wff notation to include the well-ordering predicate. Read: ' well-orders .' |
Definition | df-frfor 4309* | Define the well-founded relation predicate where might be a proper class. By passing in we allow it potentially to be a proper class rather than a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon and Mario Carneiro, 22-Sep-2021.) |
FrFor | ||
Definition | df-frind 4310* | Define the well-founded relation predicate. In the presence of excluded middle, there are a variety of equivalent ways to define this. In our case, this definition, in terms of an inductive principle, works better than one along the lines of "there is an element which is minimal when A is ordered by R". Because is constrained to be a set (not a proper class) here, sometimes it may be necessary to use FrFor directly rather than via . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon and Mario Carneiro, 21-Sep-2021.) |
FrFor | ||
Definition | df-se 4311* | Define the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 19-Nov-2014.) |
Se | ||
Definition | df-wetr 4312* | Define the well-ordering predicate. It is unusual to define "well-ordering" in the absence of excluded middle, but we mean an ordering which is like the ordering which we have for ordinals (for example, it does not entail trichotomy because ordinals do not have that as seen at ordtriexmid 4498). Given excluded middle, well-ordering is usually defined to require trichotomy (and the definition of is typically also different). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 23-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | seex 4313* | The -preimage of an element of the base set in a set-like relation is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 19-Nov-2014.) |
Se | ||
Theorem | exse 4314 | Any relation on a set is set-like on it. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
Se | ||
Theorem | sess1 4315 | Subset theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
Se Se | ||
Theorem | sess2 4316 | Subset theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
Se Se | ||
Theorem | seeq1 4317 | Equality theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
Se Se | ||
Theorem | seeq2 4318 | Equality theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
Se Se | ||
Theorem | nfse 4319 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for set-like relations. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
Se | ||
Theorem | epse 4320 | The epsilon relation is set-like on any class. (This is the origin of the term "set-like": a set-like relation "acts like" the epsilon relation of sets and their elements.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
Se | ||
Theorem | frforeq1 4321 | Equality theorem for the well-founded predicate. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Sep-2021.) |
FrFor FrFor | ||
Theorem | freq1 4322 | Equality theorem for the well-founded predicate. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.) |
Theorem | frforeq2 4323 | Equality theorem for the well-founded predicate. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Sep-2021.) |
FrFor FrFor | ||
Theorem | freq2 4324 | Equality theorem for the well-founded predicate. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | frforeq3 4325 | Equality theorem for the well-founded predicate. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Sep-2021.) |
FrFor FrFor | ||
Theorem | nffrfor 4326 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for well-founded relations. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
FrFor | ||
Theorem | nffr 4327 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for well-founded relations. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | frirrg 4328 | A well-founded relation is irreflexive. This is the case where exists. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | fr0 4329 | Any relation is well-founded on the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1993.) |
Theorem | frind 4330* | Induction over a well-founded set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | efrirr 4331 | Irreflexivity of the epsilon relation: a class founded by epsilon is not a member of itself. (Contributed by NM, 18-Apr-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
Theorem | tz7.2 4332 | Similar to Theorem 7.2 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 35, of except that the Axiom of Regularity is not required due to antecedent . (Contributed by NM, 4-May-1994.) |
Theorem | nfwe 4333 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for well-orderings. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | weeq1 4334 | Equality theorem for the well-ordering predicate. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.) |
Theorem | weeq2 4335 | Equality theorem for the well-ordering predicate. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | wefr 4336 | A well-ordering is well-founded. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | wepo 4337 | A well-ordering is a partial ordering. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | wetrep 4338* | An epsilon well-ordering is a transitive relation. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | we0 4339 | Any relation is a well-ordering of the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) |
Syntax | word 4340 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the ordinal predicate. |
Syntax | con0 4341 | Extend the definition of a class to include the class of all ordinal numbers. (The 0 in the name prevents creating a file called con.html, which causes problems in Windows.) |
Syntax | wlim 4342 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the limit ordinal predicate. |
Syntax | csuc 4343 | Extend class notation to include the successor function. |
Definition | df-iord 4344* |
Define the ordinal predicate, which is true for a class that is
transitive and whose elements are transitive. Definition of ordinal in
[Crosilla], p. "Set-theoretic
principles incompatible with
intuitionistic logic".
Some sources will define a notation for ordinal order corresponding to and but we just use and respectively. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Oct-2018.) Use its alias dford3 4345 instead for naming consistency with set.mm. (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | dford3 4345* | Alias for df-iord 4344. Use it instead of df-iord 4344 for naming consistency with set.mm. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Oct-2018.) |
Definition | df-on 4346 | Define the class of all ordinal numbers. Definition 7.11 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 38. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-1994.) |
Definition | df-ilim 4347 | Define the limit ordinal predicate, which is true for an ordinal that has the empty set as an element and is not a successor (i.e. that is the union of itself). Our definition combines the definition of Lim of [BellMachover] p. 471 and Exercise 1 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 42, and then changes to (which would be equivalent given the law of the excluded middle, but which is not for us). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Nov-2018.) Use its alias dflim2 4348 instead for naming consistency with set.mm. (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | dflim2 4348 | Alias for df-ilim 4347. Use it instead of df-ilim 4347 for naming consistency with set.mm. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2004.) |
Definition | df-suc 4349 | Define the successor of a class. When applied to an ordinal number, the successor means the same thing as "plus 1". Definition 7.22 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 41, who use "+ 1" to denote this function. Our definition is a generalization to classes. Although it is not conventional to use it with proper classes, it has no effect on a proper class (sucprc 4390). Some authors denote the successor operation with a prime (apostrophe-like) symbol, such as Definition 6 of [Suppes] p. 134 and the definition of successor in [Mendelson] p. 246 (who uses the symbol "Suc" as a predicate to mean "is a successor ordinal"). The definition of successor of [Enderton] p. 68 denotes the operation with a plus-sign superscript. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | ordeq 4350 | Equality theorem for the ordinal predicate. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1993.) |
Theorem | elong 4351 | An ordinal number is an ordinal set. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-1994.) |
Theorem | elon 4352 | An ordinal number is an ordinal set. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-1994.) |
Theorem | eloni 4353 | An ordinal number has the ordinal property. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-1994.) |
Theorem | elon2 4354 | An ordinal number is an ordinal set. (Contributed by NM, 8-Feb-2004.) |
Theorem | limeq 4355 | Equality theorem for the limit predicate. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | ordtr 4356 | An ordinal class is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | ordelss 4357 | An element of an ordinal class is a subset of it. (Contributed by NM, 30-May-1994.) |
Theorem | trssord 4358 | A transitive subclass of an ordinal class is ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-1994.) |
Theorem | ordelord 4359 | An element of an ordinal class is ordinal. Proposition 7.6 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 36. (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-1994.) |
Theorem | tron 4360 | The class of all ordinal numbers is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 4-May-2009.) |
Theorem | ordelon 4361 | An element of an ordinal class is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.) |
Theorem | onelon 4362 | An element of an ordinal number is an ordinal number. Theorem 2.2(iii) of [BellMachover] p. 469. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.) |
Theorem | ordin 4363 | The intersection of two ordinal classes is ordinal. Proposition 7.9 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 37. (Contributed by NM, 9-May-1994.) |
Theorem | onin 4364 | The intersection of two ordinal numbers is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | onelss 4365 | An element of an ordinal number is a subset of the number. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | ordtr1 4366 | Transitive law for ordinal classes. (Contributed by NM, 12-Dec-2004.) |
Theorem | ontr1 4367 | Transitive law for ordinal numbers. Theorem 7M(b) of [Enderton] p. 192. (Contributed by NM, 11-Aug-1994.) |
Theorem | onintss 4368* | If a property is true for an ordinal number, then the minimum ordinal number for which it is true is smaller or equal. Theorem Schema 61 of [Suppes] p. 228. (Contributed by NM, 3-Oct-2003.) |
Theorem | ord0 4369 | The empty set is an ordinal class. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1994.) |
Theorem | 0elon 4370 | The empty set is an ordinal number. Corollary 7N(b) of [Enderton] p. 193. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1993.) |
Theorem | inton 4371 | The intersection of the class of ordinal numbers is the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 20-Oct-2003.) |
Theorem | nlim0 4372 | The empty set is not a limit ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-1995.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | limord 4373 | A limit ordinal is ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 4-May-1995.) |
Theorem | limuni 4374 | A limit ordinal is its own supremum (union). (Contributed by NM, 4-May-1995.) |
Theorem | limuni2 4375 | The union of a limit ordinal is a limit ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 19-Sep-2006.) |
Theorem | 0ellim 4376 | A limit ordinal contains the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 15-May-1994.) |
Theorem | limelon 4377 | A limit ordinal class that is also a set is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 26-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | onn0 4378 | The class of all ordinal numbers is not empty. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1995.) |
Theorem | onm 4379 | The class of all ordinal numbers is inhabited. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 6-Mar-2019.) |
Theorem | suceq 4380 | Equality of successors. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | elsuci 4381 | Membership in a successor. This one-way implication does not require that either or be sets. (Contributed by NM, 6-Jun-1994.) |
Theorem | elsucg 4382 | Membership in a successor. Exercise 5 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 17. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1995.) |
Theorem | elsuc2g 4383 | Variant of membership in a successor, requiring that rather than be a set. (Contributed by NM, 28-Oct-2003.) |
Theorem | elsuc 4384 | Membership in a successor. Exercise 5 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 17. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) |
Theorem | elsuc2 4385 | Membership in a successor. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) |
Theorem | nfsuc 4386 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for successor. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) |
Theorem | elelsuc 4387 | Membership in a successor. (Contributed by NM, 20-Jun-1998.) |
Theorem | sucel 4388* | Membership of a successor in another class. (Contributed by NM, 29-Jun-2004.) |
Theorem | suc0 4389 | The successor of the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 1-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | sucprc 4390 | A proper class is its own successor. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | unisuc 4391 | A transitive class is equal to the union of its successor. Combines Theorem 4E of [Enderton] p. 72 and Exercise 6 of [Enderton] p. 73. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | unisucg 4392 | A transitive class is equal to the union of its successor. Combines Theorem 4E of [Enderton] p. 72 and Exercise 6 of [Enderton] p. 73. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Aug-2019.) |
Theorem | sssucid 4393 | A class is included in its own successor. Part of Proposition 7.23 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 41 (generalized to arbitrary classes). (Contributed by NM, 31-May-1994.) |
Theorem | sucidg 4394 | Part of Proposition 7.23 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 41 (generalized). (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-1995.) (Proof shortened by Scott Fenton, 20-Feb-2012.) |
Theorem | sucid 4395 | A set belongs to its successor. (Contributed by NM, 22-Jun-1994.) (Proof shortened by Alan Sare, 18-Feb-2012.) (Proof shortened by Scott Fenton, 20-Feb-2012.) |
Theorem | nsuceq0g 4396 | No successor is empty. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Oct-2018.) |
Theorem | eqelsuc 4397 | A set belongs to the successor of an equal set. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1994.) |
Theorem | iunsuc 4398* | Inductive definition for the indexed union at a successor. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Feb-2013.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 18-Nov-2016.) |
Theorem | suctr 4399 | The successor of a transitive class is transitive. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 11-Apr-2009.) |
Theorem | trsuc 4400 | A set whose successor belongs to a transitive class also belongs. (Contributed by NM, 5-Sep-2003.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |