Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 21 of 140) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | hbsb4t 2001 | A variable not free remains so after substitution with a distinct variable (closed form of hbsb4 2000). (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | nfsb4t 2002 | A variable not free remains so after substitution with a distinct variable (closed form of hbsb4 2000). (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 9-May-2018.) |
Theorem | dvelimf 2003 | Version of dvelim 2005 without any variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2002.) |
Theorem | dvelimdf 2004 | Deduction form of dvelimf 2003. This version may be useful if we want to avoid ax-17 1514 and use ax-16 1802 instead. (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2018.) |
Theorem | dvelim 2005* |
This theorem can be used to eliminate a distinct variable restriction on
and and replace it with the
"distinctor"
as an antecedent. normally has free and can be read
, and
substitutes for and can be read
. We don't require that and be
distinct: if
they aren't, the distinctor will become false (in multiple-element
domains of discourse) and "protect" the consequent.
To obtain a closed-theorem form of this inference, prefix the hypotheses with , conjoin them, and apply dvelimdf 2004. Other variants of this theorem are dvelimf 2003 (with no distinct variable restrictions) and dvelimALT 1998 (that avoids ax-10 1493). (Contributed by NM, 23-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | dvelimor 2006* | Disjunctive distinct variable constraint elimination. A user of this theorem starts with a formula (containing ) and a distinct variable constraint between and . The theorem makes it possible to replace the distinct variable constraint with the disjunct ( is just a version of with substituted for ). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.) |
Theorem | dveeq1 2007* | Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 19-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sbal2 2008* | Move quantifier in and out of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
Theorem | nfsb4or 2009 | A variable not free remains so after substitution with a distinct variable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfd2 2010 | Deduce that is not free in in a context. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | hbe1a 2011 | Dual statement of hbe1 1483. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 15-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | nf5-1 2012 | One direction of nf5 . (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | nf5d 2013 | Deduce that is not free in in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Syntax | weu 2014 | Extend wff definition to include existential uniqueness ("there exists a unique such that "). |
Syntax | wmo 2015 | Extend wff definition to include uniqueness ("there exists at most one such that "). |
Theorem | eujust 2016* | A soundness justification theorem for df-eu 2017, showing that the definition is equivalent to itself with its dummy variable renamed. Note that and needn't be distinct variables. (Contributed by NM, 11-Mar-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Definition | df-eu 2017* | Define existential uniqueness, i.e., "there exists exactly one such that ". Definition 10.1 of [BellMachover] p. 97; also Definition *14.02 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 175. Other possible definitions are given by eu1 2039, eu2 2058, eu3 2060, and eu5 2061 (which in some cases we show with a hypothesis in place of a distinct variable condition on and ). Double uniqueness is tricky: does not mean "exactly one and one " (see 2eu4 2107). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Definition | df-mo 2018 | Define "there exists at most one such that ". Here we define it in terms of existential uniqueness. Notation of [BellMachover] p. 460, whose definition we show as mo3 2068. For another possible definition see mo4 2075. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | euf 2019* | A version of the existential uniqueness definition with a hypothesis instead of a distinct variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | eubidh 2020 | Formula-building rule for unique existential quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eubid 2021 | Formula-building rule for unique existential quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eubidv 2022* | Formula-building rule for unique existential quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eubii 2023 | Introduce unique existential quantifier to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | hbeu1 2024 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | nfeu1 2025 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | nfmo1 2026 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sb8eu 2027 | Variable substitution in unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sb8mo 2028 | Variable substitution for "at most one". (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
Theorem | nfeudv 2029* | Deduction version of nfeu 2033. Similar to nfeud 2030 but has the additional constraint that and must be distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfeud 2030 | Deduction version of nfeu 2033. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 25-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfmod 2031 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2016.) |
Theorem | nfeuv 2032* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for existential uniqueness. This is similar to nfeu 2033 but has the additional condition that and must be distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfeu 2033 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for existential uniqueness. Note that and needn't be distinct. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 23-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfmo 2034 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | hbeu 2035 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for uniqueness. Note that and needn't be distinct. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 24-May-2018.) |
Theorem | hbeud 2036 | Deduction version of hbeu 2035. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2013.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 25-May-2018.) |
Theorem | sb8euh 2037 | Variable substitution in unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | cbveu 2038 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 25-Nov-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | eu1 2039* | An alternate way to express uniqueness used by some authors. Exercise 2(b) of [Margaris] p. 110. (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | euor 2040 | Introduce a disjunct into a unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2005.) |
Theorem | euorv 2041* | Introduce a disjunct into a unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mo2n 2042* | There is at most one of something which does not exist. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2018.) |
Theorem | mon 2043 | There is at most one of something which does not exist. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Jul-2018.) |
Theorem | euex 2044 | Existential uniqueness implies existence. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | eumo0 2045* | Existential uniqueness implies "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eumo 2046 | Existential uniqueness implies "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 27-May-2018.) |
Theorem | eumoi 2047 | "At most one" inferred from existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | mobidh 2048 | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mobid 2049 | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mobidv 2050* | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | mobii 2051 | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (inference form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | hbmo1 2052 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | hbmo 2053 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | cbvmo 2054 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | mo23 2055* | An implication between two definitions of "there exists at most one." (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | mor 2056* | Converse of mo23 2055 with an additional condition. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | modc 2057* | Equivalent definitions of "there exists at most one," given decidable existence. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Jul-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | eu2 2058* | An alternate way of defining existential uniqueness. Definition 6.10 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 26. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eu3h 2059* | An alternate way to express existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | eu3 2060* | An alternate way to express existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eu5 2061 | Uniqueness in terms of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 27-May-2018.) |
Theorem | exmoeu2 2062 | Existence implies "at most one" is equivalent to uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | moabs 2063 | Absorption of existence condition by "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2002.) |
Theorem | exmodc 2064 | If existence is decidable, something exists or at most one exists. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jun-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | exmonim 2065 | There is at most one of something which does not exist. Unlike exmodc 2064 there is no decidability condition. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Sep-2018.) |
Theorem | mo2r 2066* | A condition which implies "at most one". (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2018.) |
Theorem | mo3h 2067* | Alternate definition of "at most one". Definition of [BellMachover] p. 460, except that definition has the side condition that not occur in in place of our hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | mo3 2068* | Alternate definition of "at most one". Definition of [BellMachover] p. 460, except that definition has the side condition that not occur in in place of our hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mo2dc 2069* | Alternate definition of "at most one" where existence is decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | euan 2070 | Introduction of a conjunct into unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 19-Feb-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | euanv 2071* | Introduction of a conjunct into unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | euor2 2072 | Introduce or eliminate a disjunct in a unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | sbmo 2073* | Substitution into "at most one". (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
Theorem | mo4f 2074* | "At most one" expressed using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 10-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | mo4 2075* | "At most one" expressed using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | eu4 2076* | Uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | exmoeudc 2077 | Existence in terms of "at most one" and uniqueness. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 3-Jul-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | moim 2078 | "At most one" is preserved through implication (notice wff reversal). (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | moimi 2079 | "At most one" is preserved through implication (notice wff reversal). (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2006.) |
Theorem | moimv 2080* | Move antecedent outside of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 28-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | euimmo 2081 | Uniqueness implies "at most one" through implication. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | euim 2082 | Add existential unique existential quantifiers to an implication. Note the reversed implication in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 19-Oct-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 14-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | moan 2083 | "At most one" is still the case when a conjunct is added. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | moani 2084 | "At most one" is still true when a conjunct is added. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | moor 2085 | "At most one" is still the case when a disjunct is removed. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | mooran1 2086 | "At most one" imports disjunction to conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | mooran2 2087 | "At most one" exports disjunction to conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | moanim 2088 | Introduction of a conjunct into at-most-one quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 3-Dec-2001.) |
Theorem | moanimv 2089* | Introduction of a conjunct into at-most-one quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | moaneu 2090 | Nested at-most-one and unique existential quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jan-2006.) |
Theorem | moanmo 2091 | Nested at-most-one quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jan-2006.) |
Theorem | mopick 2092 | "At most one" picks a variable value, eliminating an existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 27-Jan-1997.) |
Theorem | eupick 2093 | Existential uniqueness "picks" a variable value for which another wff is true. If there is only one thing such that is true, and there is also an (actually the same one) such that and are both true, then implies regardless of . This theorem can be useful for eliminating existential quantifiers in a hypothesis. Compare Theorem *14.26 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 192. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eupicka 2094 | Version of eupick 2093 with closed formulas. (Contributed by NM, 6-Sep-2008.) |
Theorem | eupickb 2095 | Existential uniqueness "pick" showing wff equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 25-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | eupickbi 2096 | Theorem *14.26 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 192. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | mopick2 2097 | "At most one" can show the existence of a common value. In this case we can infer existence of conjunction from a conjunction of existence, and it is one way to achieve the converse of 19.40 1619. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | moexexdc 2098 | "At most one" double quantification. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Jul-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | euexex 2099 | Existential uniqueness and "at most one" double quantification. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Dec-2018.) |
Theorem | 2moex 2100 | Double quantification with "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 3-Dec-2001.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |