Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 21 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Browser slow? Try the
Unicode version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | exsb 2001* | An equivalent expression for existence. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | 2exsb 2002* | An equivalent expression for double existence. (Contributed by NM, 2-Feb-2005.) |
Theorem | dvelimALT 2003* | Version of dvelim 2010 that doesn't use ax-10 1498. Because it has different distinct variable constraints than dvelim 2010 and is used in important proofs, it would be better if it had a name which does not end in ALT (ideally more close to set.mm naming). (Contributed by NM, 17-May-2008.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | dvelimfv 2004* | Like dvelimf 2008 but with a distinct variable constraint on and . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 6-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | hbsb4 2005 | A variable not free remains so after substitution with a distinct variable. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 23-Mar-2018.) |
Theorem | hbsb4t 2006 | A variable not free remains so after substitution with a distinct variable (closed form of hbsb4 2005). (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
Theorem | nfsb4t 2007 | A variable not free remains so after substitution with a distinct variable (closed form of hbsb4 2005). (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 9-May-2018.) |
Theorem | dvelimf 2008 | Version of dvelim 2010 without any variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2002.) |
Theorem | dvelimdf 2009 | Deduction form of dvelimf 2008. This version may be useful if we want to avoid ax-17 1519 and use ax-16 1807 instead. (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2018.) |
Theorem | dvelim 2010* |
This theorem can be used to eliminate a distinct variable restriction on
and and replace it with the
"distinctor"
as an antecedent. normally has free and can be read
, and
substitutes for and can be read
. We don't require that and be
distinct: if
they aren't, the distinctor will become false (in multiple-element
domains of discourse) and "protect" the consequent.
To obtain a closed-theorem form of this inference, prefix the hypotheses with , conjoin them, and apply dvelimdf 2009. Other variants of this theorem are dvelimf 2008 (with no distinct variable restrictions) and dvelimALT 2003 (that avoids ax-10 1498). (Contributed by NM, 23-Nov-1994.) |
Theorem | dvelimor 2011* | Disjunctive distinct variable constraint elimination. A user of this theorem starts with a formula (containing ) and a distinct variable constraint between and . The theorem makes it possible to replace the distinct variable constraint with the disjunct ( is just a version of with substituted for ). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.) |
Theorem | dveeq1 2012* | Quantifier introduction when one pair of variables is distinct. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 19-Feb-2018.) |
Theorem | sbal2 2013* | Move quantifier in and out of substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
Theorem | nfsb4or 2014 | A variable not free remains so after substitution with a distinct variable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfd2 2015 | Deduce that is not free in in a context. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | hbe1a 2016 | Dual statement of hbe1 1488. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 15-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | nf5-1 2017 | One direction of nf5 . (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Sep-2021.) |
Theorem | nf5d 2018 | Deduce that is not free in in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
Syntax | weu 2019 | Extend wff definition to include existential uniqueness ("there exists a unique such that "). |
Syntax | wmo 2020 | Extend wff definition to include uniqueness ("there exists at most one such that "). |
Theorem | eujust 2021* | A soundness justification theorem for df-eu 2022, showing that the definition is equivalent to itself with its dummy variable renamed. Note that and needn't be distinct variables. (Contributed by NM, 11-Mar-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Definition | df-eu 2022* | Define existential uniqueness, i.e., "there exists exactly one such that ". Definition 10.1 of [BellMachover] p. 97; also Definition *14.02 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 175. Other possible definitions are given by eu1 2044, eu2 2063, eu3 2065, and eu5 2066 (which in some cases we show with a hypothesis in place of a distinct variable condition on and ). Double uniqueness is tricky: does not mean "exactly one and one " (see 2eu4 2112). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Definition | df-mo 2023 | Define "there exists at most one such that ". Here we define it in terms of existential uniqueness. Notation of [BellMachover] p. 460, whose definition we show as mo3 2073. For another possible definition see mo4 2080. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | euf 2024* | A version of the existential uniqueness definition with a hypothesis instead of a distinct variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | eubidh 2025 | Formula-building rule for unique existential quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eubid 2026 | Formula-building rule for unique existential quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eubidv 2027* | Formula-building rule for unique existential quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eubii 2028 | Introduce unique existential quantifier to both sides of an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | hbeu1 2029 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | nfeu1 2030 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | nfmo1 2031 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sb8eu 2032 | Variable substitution in unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | sb8mo 2033 | Variable substitution for "at most one". (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
Theorem | nfeudv 2034* | Deduction version of nfeu 2038. Similar to nfeud 2035 but has the additional constraint that and must be distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfeud 2035 | Deduction version of nfeu 2038. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 25-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfmod 2036 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2016.) |
Theorem | nfeuv 2037* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for existential uniqueness. This is similar to nfeu 2038 but has the additional condition that and must be distinct. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfeu 2038 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for existential uniqueness. Note that and needn't be distinct. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 23-May-2018.) |
Theorem | nfmo 2039 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | hbeu 2040 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for uniqueness. Note that and needn't be distinct. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 24-May-2018.) |
Theorem | hbeud 2041 | Deduction version of hbeu 2040. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2013.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 25-May-2018.) |
Theorem | sb8euh 2042 | Variable substitution in unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | cbveu 2043 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 25-Nov-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | eu1 2044* | An alternate way to express uniqueness used by some authors. Exercise 2(b) of [Margaris] p. 110. (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-1993.) |
Theorem | euor 2045 | Introduce a disjunct into a unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2005.) |
Theorem | euorv 2046* | Introduce a disjunct into a unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mo2n 2047* | There is at most one of something which does not exist. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2018.) |
Theorem | mon 2048 | There is at most one of something which does not exist. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-Jul-2018.) |
Theorem | euex 2049 | Existential uniqueness implies existence. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | eumo0 2050* | Existential uniqueness implies "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eumo 2051 | Existential uniqueness implies "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 27-May-2018.) |
Theorem | eumoi 2052 | "At most one" inferred from existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | mobidh 2053 | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mobid 2054 | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mobidv 2055* | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (deduction form). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | mobii 2056 | Formula-building rule for "at most one" quantifier (inference form). (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Oct-2016.) |
Theorem | hbmo1 2057 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | hbmo 2058 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | cbvmo 2059 | Rule used to change bound variables, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | mo23 2060* | An implication between two definitions of "there exists at most one." (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | mor 2061* | Converse of mo23 2060 with an additional condition. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2018.) |
Theorem | modc 2062* | Equivalent definitions of "there exists at most one," given decidable existence. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Jul-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | eu2 2063* | An alternate way of defining existential uniqueness. Definition 6.10 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 26. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eu3h 2064* | An alternate way to express existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | eu3 2065* | An alternate way to express existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eu5 2066 | Uniqueness in terms of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 27-May-2018.) |
Theorem | exmoeu2 2067 | Existence implies "at most one" is equivalent to uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | moabs 2068 | Absorption of existence condition by "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2002.) |
Theorem | exmodc 2069 | If existence is decidable, something exists or at most one exists. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jun-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | exmonim 2070 | There is at most one of something which does not exist. Unlike exmodc 2069 there is no decidability condition. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Sep-2018.) |
Theorem | mo2r 2071* | A condition which implies "at most one". (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2018.) |
Theorem | mo3h 2072* | Alternate definition of "at most one". Definition of [BellMachover] p. 460, except that definition has the side condition that not occur in in place of our hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
Theorem | mo3 2073* | Alternate definition of "at most one". Definition of [BellMachover] p. 460, except that definition has the side condition that not occur in in place of our hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | mo2dc 2074* | Alternate definition of "at most one" where existence is decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Jul-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | euan 2075 | Introduction of a conjunct into unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 19-Feb-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | euanv 2076* | Introduction of a conjunct into unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | euor2 2077 | Introduce or eliminate a disjunct in a unique existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | sbmo 2078* | Substitution into "at most one". (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
Theorem | mo4f 2079* | "At most one" expressed using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 10-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | mo4 2080* | "At most one" expressed using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | eu4 2081* | Uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | exmoeudc 2082 | Existence in terms of "at most one" and uniqueness. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 3-Jul-2018.) |
DECID | ||
Theorem | moim 2083 | "At most one" is preserved through implication (notice wff reversal). (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | moimi 2084 | "At most one" is preserved through implication (notice wff reversal). (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2006.) |
Theorem | moimv 2085* | Move antecedent outside of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 28-Jul-1995.) |
Theorem | euimmo 2086 | Uniqueness implies "at most one" through implication. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | euim 2087 | Add existential unique existential quantifiers to an implication. Note the reversed implication in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 19-Oct-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 14-Jun-2011.) |
Theorem | moan 2088 | "At most one" is still the case when a conjunct is added. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1995.) |
Theorem | moani 2089 | "At most one" is still true when a conjunct is added. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | moor 2090 | "At most one" is still the case when a disjunct is removed. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
Theorem | mooran1 2091 | "At most one" imports disjunction to conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | mooran2 2092 | "At most one" exports disjunction to conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
Theorem | moanim 2093 | Introduction of a conjunct into at-most-one quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 3-Dec-2001.) |
Theorem | moanimv 2094* | Introduction of a conjunct into at-most-one quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 23-Mar-1995.) |
Theorem | moaneu 2095 | Nested at-most-one and unique existential quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jan-2006.) |
Theorem | moanmo 2096 | Nested at-most-one quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jan-2006.) |
Theorem | mopick 2097 | "At most one" picks a variable value, eliminating an existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 27-Jan-1997.) |
Theorem | eupick 2098 | Existential uniqueness "picks" a variable value for which another wff is true. If there is only one thing such that is true, and there is also an (actually the same one) such that and are both true, then implies regardless of . This theorem can be useful for eliminating existential quantifiers in a hypothesis. Compare Theorem *14.26 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 192. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jul-1994.) |
Theorem | eupicka 2099 | Version of eupick 2098 with closed formulas. (Contributed by NM, 6-Sep-2008.) |
Theorem | eupickb 2100 | Existential uniqueness "pick" showing wff equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 25-Nov-1994.) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |