Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 14 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | 3jaodan 1301 | Disjunction of 3 antecedents (deduction). (Contributed by NM, 14-Oct-2005.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜏) → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∨ 𝜃 ∨ 𝜏)) → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | mpjao3dan 1302 | Eliminate a 3-way disjunction in a deduction. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 13-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜏) → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ∨ 𝜃 ∨ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | 3jaao 1303 | Inference conjoining and disjoining the antecedents of three implications. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 15-Aug-2009.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → (𝜏 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜂 → (𝜁 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜂) → ((𝜓 ∨ 𝜏 ∨ 𝜁) → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 3ianorr 1304 | Triple disjunction implies negated triple conjunction. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 ∨ ¬ 𝜓 ∨ ¬ 𝜒) → ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | syl3an9b 1305 | Nested syllogism inference conjoining 3 dissimilar antecedents. (Contributed by NM, 1-May-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜂 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜁)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜂) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | 3orbi123d 1306 | Deduction joining 3 equivalences to form equivalence of disjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 20-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∨ 𝜃 ∨ 𝜂) ↔ (𝜒 ∨ 𝜏 ∨ 𝜁))) | ||
Theorem | 3anbi123d 1307 | Deduction joining 3 equivalences to form equivalence of conjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜂) ↔ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜏 ∧ 𝜁))) | ||
Theorem | 3anbi12d 1308 | Deduction conjoining and adding a conjunct to equivalences. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜂) ↔ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜏 ∧ 𝜂))) | ||
Theorem | 3anbi13d 1309 | Deduction conjoining and adding a conjunct to equivalences. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜂 ∧ 𝜃) ↔ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜂 ∧ 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | 3anbi23d 1310 | Deduction conjoining and adding a conjunct to equivalences. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜂 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) ↔ (𝜂 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | 3anbi1d 1311 | Deduction adding conjuncts to an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜏) ↔ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | 3anbi2d 1312 | Deduction adding conjuncts to an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜃 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜏) ↔ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | 3anbi3d 1313 | Deduction adding conjuncts to an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 8-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜃 ∧ 𝜏 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏 ∧ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | 3anim123d 1314 | Deduction joining 3 implications to form implication of conjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜂 → 𝜁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜂) → (𝜒 ∧ 𝜏 ∧ 𝜁))) | ||
Theorem | 3orim123d 1315 | Deduction joining 3 implications to form implication of disjunctions. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-1997.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜂 → 𝜁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∨ 𝜃 ∨ 𝜂) → (𝜒 ∨ 𝜏 ∨ 𝜁))) | ||
Theorem | an6 1316 | Rearrangement of 6 conjuncts. (Contributed by NM, 13-Mar-1995.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ (𝜃 ∧ 𝜏 ∧ 𝜂)) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜃) ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜏) ∧ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜂))) | ||
Theorem | 3an6 1317 | Analog of an4 581 for triple conjunction. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-May-2011.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) ∧ (𝜏 ∧ 𝜂)) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜏) ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜃 ∧ 𝜂))) | ||
Theorem | 3or6 1318 | Analog of or4 766 for triple conjunction. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Mar-2011.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ∨ (𝜒 ∨ 𝜃) ∨ (𝜏 ∨ 𝜂)) ↔ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜒 ∨ 𝜏) ∨ (𝜓 ∨ 𝜃 ∨ 𝜂))) | ||
Theorem | mp3an1 1319 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mp3an2 1320 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.) |
⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mp3an3 1321 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.) |
⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mp3an12 1322 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jul-2005.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mp3an13 1323 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-Jul-2005.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mp3an23 1324 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-Jul-2005.) |
⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mp3an1i 1325 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jul-2005.) |
⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | mp3anl1 1326 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3anl2 1327 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3anl3 1328 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3anr1 1329 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2006.) |
⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3anr2 1330 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-2006.) |
⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3anr3 1331 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 19-Oct-2007.) |
⊢ 𝜃 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3an 1332 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1999.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜃 | ||
Theorem | mpd3an3 1333 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2007.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mpd3an23 1334 | An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 4-Dec-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | mp3and 1335 | A deduction based on modus ponens. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3an12i 1336 | mp3an 1332 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with one hypothesis an implication. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜃) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3an2i 1337 | mp3an 1332 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with two hypotheses which are implications. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜃) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | mp3an3an 1338 | mp3an 1332 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with two hypotheses which are implications. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜃 → 𝜏) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜏) → 𝜂) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜂) | ||
Theorem | mp3an2ani 1339 | An elimination deduction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 17-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜒) & ⊢ ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜏) → 𝜂) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜂) | ||
Theorem | biimp3a 1340 | Infer implication from a logical equivalence. Similar to biimpa 294. (Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2005.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | biimp3ar 1341 | Infer implication from a logical equivalence. Similar to biimpar 295. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2009.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | 3anandis 1342 | Inference that undistributes a triple conjunction in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 18-Apr-2007.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | 3anandirs 1343 | Inference that undistributes a triple conjunction in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jul-2006.) (Revised by NM, 18-Apr-2007.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜃) ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜃) ∧ (𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) → 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | ecased 1344 | Deduction form of disjunctive syllogism. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ∨ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | ecase23d 1345 | Variation of ecased 1344 with three disjuncts instead of two. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 9-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ∨ 𝜒 ∨ 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Even though it is not ordinarily part of propositional calculus, the universal quantifier ∀ is introduced here so that the soundness of Definition df-tru 1351 can be checked by the same algorithm that is used for predicate calculus. Its first real use is in Axiom ax-5 1440 in the predicate calculus section below. For those who want propositional calculus to be self-contained, i.e., to use wff variables only, the alternate Definition dftru2 1356 may be adopted and this subsection moved down to the start of the subsection with wex 1485 below. However, the use of dftru2 1356 as a definition requires a more elaborate definition checking algorithm that we prefer to avoid. | ||
Syntax | wal 1346 | Extend wff definition to include the universal quantifier ("for all"). ∀𝑥𝜑 is read "𝜑 (phi) is true for all 𝑥". Typically, in its final application 𝜑 would be replaced with a wff containing a (free) occurrence of the variable 𝑥, for example 𝑥 = 𝑦. In a universe with a finite number of objects, "for all" is equivalent to a big conjunction (AND) with one wff for each possible case of 𝑥. When the universe is infinite (as with set theory), such a propositional-calculus equivalent is not possible because an infinitely long formula has no meaning, but conceptually the idea is the same. |
wff ∀𝑥𝜑 | ||
Even though it is not ordinarily part of propositional calculus, the equality predicate = is introduced here so that the soundness of definition df-tru 1351 can be checked by the same algorithm as is used for predicate calculus. Its first real use is in Axiom ax-8 1497 in the predicate calculus section below. For those who want propositional calculus to be self-contained, i.e., to use wff variables only, the alternate definition dftru2 1356 may be adopted and this subsection moved down to just above weq 1496 below. However, the use of dftru2 1356 as a definition requires a more elaborate definition checking algorithm that we prefer to avoid. | ||
Syntax | cv 1347 |
This syntax construction states that a variable 𝑥, which has been
declared to be a setvar variable by $f statement vx, is also a class
expression. This can be justified informally as follows. We know that
the class builder {𝑦 ∣ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥} is a class by cab 2156.
Since (when
𝑦 is distinct from 𝑥) we
have 𝑥 =
{𝑦 ∣ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥} by
cvjust 2165, we can argue that the syntax "class 𝑥 " can be viewed as
an abbreviation for "class {𝑦 ∣ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥}". See the discussion
under the definition of class in [Jech] p.
4 showing that "Every set can
be considered to be a class."
While it is tempting and perhaps occasionally useful to view cv 1347 as a "type conversion" from a setvar variable to a class variable, keep in mind that cv 1347 is intrinsically no different from any other class-building syntax such as cab 2156, cun 3119, or c0 3414. For a general discussion of the theory of classes and the role of cv 1347, see https://us.metamath.org/mpeuni/mmset.html#class 1347. (The description above applies to set theory, not predicate calculus. The purpose of introducing class 𝑥 here, and not in set theory where it belongs, is to allow us to express i.e. "prove" the weq 1496 of predicate calculus from the wceq 1348 of set theory, so that we don't overload the = connective with two syntax definitions. This is done to prevent ambiguity that would complicate some Metamath parsers.) |
class 𝑥 | ||
Syntax | wceq 1348 |
Extend wff definition to include class equality.
For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see https://us.metamath.org/mpeuni/mmset.html#class. (The purpose of introducing wff 𝐴 = 𝐵 here, and not in set theory where it belongs, is to allow us to express i.e. "prove" the weq 1496 of predicate calculus in terms of the wceq 1348 of set theory, so that we don't "overload" the = connective with two syntax definitions. This is done to prevent ambiguity that would complicate some Metamath parsers. For example, some parsers - although not the Metamath program - stumble on the fact that the = in 𝑥 = 𝑦 could be the = of either weq 1496 or wceq 1348, although mathematically it makes no difference. The class variables 𝐴 and 𝐵 are introduced temporarily for the purpose of this definition but otherwise not used in predicate calculus. See df-cleq 2163 for more information on the set theory usage of wceq 1348.) |
wff 𝐴 = 𝐵 | ||
Syntax | wtru 1349 | ⊤ is a wff. |
wff ⊤ | ||
Theorem | trujust 1350 | Soundness justification theorem for df-tru 1351. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-Nov-2013.) (Revised by NM, 11-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥 → ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥) ↔ (∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑦)) | ||
Definition | df-tru 1351 | Definition of the truth value "true", or "verum", denoted by ⊤. This is a tautology, as proved by tru 1352. In this definition, an instance of id 19 is used as the definiens, although any tautology, such as an axiom, can be used in its place. This particular id 19 instance was chosen so this definition can be checked by the same algorithm that is used for predicate calculus. This definition should be referenced directly only by tru 1352, and other proofs should depend on tru 1352 (directly or indirectly) instead of this definition, since there are many alternate ways to define ⊤. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) (Revised by NM, 11-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (⊤ ↔ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥 → ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | tru 1352 | The truth value ⊤ is provable. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ⊤ | ||
Syntax | wfal 1353 | ⊥ is a wff. |
wff ⊥ | ||
Definition | df-fal 1354 | Definition of the truth value "false", or "falsum", denoted by ⊥. See also df-tru 1351. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ (⊥ ↔ ¬ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | fal 1355 | The truth value ⊥ is refutable. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 11-Mar-2012.) |
⊢ ¬ ⊥ | ||
Theorem | dftru2 1356 | An alternate definition of "true". (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) (Revised by BJ, 12-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (⊤ ↔ (𝜑 → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mptru 1357 | Eliminate ⊤ as an antecedent. A proposition implied by ⊤ is true. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Mar-2014.) |
⊢ (⊤ → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | tbtru 1358 | A proposition is equivalent to itself being equivalent to ⊤. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 14-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 ↔ ⊤)) | ||
Theorem | nbfal 1359 | The negation of a proposition is equivalent to itself being equivalent to ⊥. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 14-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥)) | ||
Theorem | bitru 1360 | A theorem is equivalent to truth. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | bifal 1361 | A contradiction is equivalent to falsehood. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | falim 1362 | The truth value ⊥ implies anything. Also called the principle of explosion, or "ex falso quodlibet". (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Anthony Hart, 1-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (⊥ → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | falimd 1363 | The truth value ⊥ implies anything. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ⊥) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | a1tru 1364 | Anything implies ⊤. (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Anthony Hart, 1-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ⊤) | ||
Theorem | truan 1365 | True can be removed from a conjunction. (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | dfnot 1366 | Given falsum, we can define the negation of a wff 𝜑 as the statement that a contradiction follows from assuming 𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 → ⊥)) | ||
Theorem | inegd 1367 | Negation introduction rule from natural deduction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → ⊥) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | pm2.21fal 1368 | If a wff and its negation are provable, then falsum is provable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ⊥) | ||
Theorem | pclem6 1369 | Negation inferred from embedded conjunct. (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)) → ¬ 𝜓) | ||
Syntax | wxo 1370 | Extend wff definition to include exclusive disjunction ('xor'). |
wff (𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) | ||
Definition | df-xor 1371 | Define exclusive disjunction (logical 'xor'). Return true if either the left or right, but not both, are true. Contrast with ∧ (wa 103), ∨ (wo 703), and → (wi 4) . (Contributed by FL, 22-Nov-2010.) (Modified by Jim Kingdon, 1-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | xoranor 1372 | One way of defining exclusive or. Equivalent to df-xor 1371. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon and Mario Carneiro, 1-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ∧ (¬ 𝜑 ∨ ¬ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | excxor 1373 | This tautology shows that xor is really exclusive. (Contributed by FL, 22-Nov-2010.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | xoror 1374 | XOR implies OR. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) → (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | xorbi2d 1375 | Deduction joining an equivalence and a left operand to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜃 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜃 ⊻ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | xorbi1d 1376 | Deduction joining an equivalence and a right operand to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ⊻ 𝜃) ↔ (𝜒 ⊻ 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | xorbi12d 1377 | Deduction joining two equivalences to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ⊻ 𝜃) ↔ (𝜒 ⊻ 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | xorbi12i 1378 | Equality property for XOR. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | xorbin 1379 | A consequence of exclusive or. In classical logic the converse also holds. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 8-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) → (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | pm5.18im 1380 | One direction of pm5.18dc 878, which holds for all propositions, not just decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ¬ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | xornbi 1381 | A consequence of exclusive or. For decidable propositions this is an equivalence, as seen at xornbidc 1386. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) → ¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | xor3dc 1382 | Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)))) | ||
Theorem | xorcom 1383 | ⊻ is commutative. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 6-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | pm5.15dc 1384 | A decidable proposition is equivalent to a decidable proposition or its negation. Based on theorem *5.15 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ∨ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)))) | ||
Theorem | xor2dc 1385 | Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ∧ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓))))) | ||
Theorem | xornbidc 1386 | Exclusive or is equivalent to negated biconditional for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)))) | ||
Theorem | xordc 1387 | Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. Theorem *5.22 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜑))))) | ||
Theorem | xordc1 1388 | Exclusive or implies the left proposition is decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) → DECID 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nbbndc 1389 | Move negation outside of biconditional, for decidable propositions. Compare Theorem *5.18 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Apr-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((¬ 𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)))) | ||
Theorem | biassdc 1390 |
Associative law for the biconditional, for decidable propositions.
The classical version (without the decidability conditions) is an axiom of system DS in Vladimir Lifschitz, "On calculational proofs", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 113:207-224, 2002, http://www.cs.utexas.edu/users/ai-lab/pub-view.php?PubID=26805, and, interestingly, was not included in Principia Mathematica but was apparently first noted by Jan Lukasiewicz circa 1923. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (DECID 𝜒 → (((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ 𝜒) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)))))) | ||
Theorem | bilukdc 1391 | Lukasiewicz's shortest axiom for equivalential calculus (but modified to require decidable propositions). Storrs McCall, ed., Polish Logic 1920-1939 (Oxford, 1967), p. 96. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
⊢ (((DECID 𝜑 ∧ DECID 𝜓) ∧ DECID 𝜒) → ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | dfbi3dc 1392 | An alternate definition of the biconditional for decidable propositions. Theorem *5.23 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but with decidability conditions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓))))) | ||
Theorem | pm5.24dc 1393 | Theorem *5.24 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓)) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜑))))) | ||
Theorem | xordidc 1394 | Conjunction distributes over exclusive-or, for decidable propositions. This is one way to interpret the distributive law of multiplication over addition in modulo 2 arithmetic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (DECID 𝜒 → ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜒)) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⊻ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜒)))))) | ||
Theorem | anxordi 1395 | Conjunction distributes over exclusive-or. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜒)) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⊻ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜒))) | ||
For classical logic, truth tables can be used to define propositional logic operations, by showing the results of those operations for all possible combinations of true (⊤) and false (⊥). Although the intuitionistic logic connectives are not as simply defined, ⊤ and ⊥ do play similar roles as in classical logic and most theorems from classical logic continue to hold. Here we show that our definitions and axioms produce equivalent results for ⊤ and ⊥ as we would get from truth tables for ∧ (conjunction aka logical 'and') wa 103, ∨ (disjunction aka logical inclusive 'or') wo 703, → (implies) wi 4, ¬ (not) wn 3, ↔ (logical equivalence) df-bi 116, and ⊻ (exclusive or) df-xor 1371. | ||
Theorem | truantru 1396 | A ∧ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ∧ ⊤) ↔ ⊤) | ||
Theorem | truanfal 1397 | A ∧ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ∧ ⊥) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | falantru 1398 | A ∧ identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 23-Feb-2018.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ∧ ⊤) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | falanfal 1399 | A ∧ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ∧ ⊥) ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | truortru 1400 | A ∨ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ ((⊤ ∨ ⊤) ↔ ⊤) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |