HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 14 of 133)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 1301-1400   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theorem3or6 1301 Analog of or4 760 for triple conjunction. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Mar-2011.)
(((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (𝜒𝜃) ∨ (𝜏𝜂)) ↔ ((𝜑𝜒𝜏) ∨ (𝜓𝜃𝜂)))
 
Theoremmp3an1 1302 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.)
𝜑    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremmp3an2 1303 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.)
𝜓    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜒) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremmp3an3 1304 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 21-Nov-1994.)
𝜒    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremmp3an12 1305 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jul-2005.)
𝜑    &   𝜓    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       (𝜒𝜃)
 
Theoremmp3an13 1306 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-Jul-2005.)
𝜑    &   𝜒    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       (𝜓𝜃)
 
Theoremmp3an23 1307 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-Jul-2005.)
𝜓    &   𝜒    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       (𝜑𝜃)
 
Theoremmp3an1i 1308 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jul-2005.)
𝜓    &   (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒𝜃) → 𝜏))       (𝜑 → ((𝜒𝜃) → 𝜏))
 
Theoremmp3anl1 1309 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.)
𝜑    &   (((𝜑𝜓𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)       (((𝜓𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3anl2 1310 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.)
𝜓    &   (((𝜑𝜓𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)       (((𝜑𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3anl3 1311 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Feb-2005.)
𝜒    &   (((𝜑𝜓𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)       (((𝜑𝜓) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3anr1 1312 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2006.)
𝜓    &   ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒𝜃)) → 𝜏)       ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜒𝜃)) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3anr2 1313 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-2006.)
𝜒    &   ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒𝜃)) → 𝜏)       ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜃)) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3anr3 1314 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 19-Oct-2007.)
𝜃    &   ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒𝜃)) → 𝜏)       ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒)) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3an 1315 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 14-May-1999.)
𝜑    &   𝜓    &   𝜒    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       𝜃
 
Theoremmpd3an3 1316 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 8-Nov-2007.)
((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremmpd3an23 1317 An inference based on modus ponens. (Contributed by NM, 4-Dec-2006.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜑𝜒)    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)       (𝜑𝜃)
 
Theoremmp3and 1318 A deduction based on modus ponens. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Dec-2016.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜑𝜒)    &   (𝜑𝜃)    &   (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒𝜃) → 𝜏))       (𝜑𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3an12i 1319 mp3an 1315 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with one hypothesis an implication. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.)
𝜑    &   𝜓    &   (𝜒𝜃)    &   ((𝜑𝜓𝜃) → 𝜏)       (𝜒𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3an2i 1320 mp3an 1315 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with two hypotheses which are implications. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.)
𝜑    &   (𝜓𝜒)    &   (𝜓𝜃)    &   ((𝜑𝜒𝜃) → 𝜏)       (𝜓𝜏)
 
Theoremmp3an3an 1321 mp3an 1315 with antecedents in standard conjunction form and with two hypotheses which are implications. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 28-Aug-2016.)
𝜑    &   (𝜓𝜒)    &   (𝜃𝜏)    &   ((𝜑𝜒𝜏) → 𝜂)       ((𝜓𝜃) → 𝜂)
 
Theoremmp3an2ani 1322 An elimination deduction. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 17-Oct-2017.)
𝜑    &   (𝜓𝜒)    &   ((𝜓𝜃) → 𝜏)    &   ((𝜑𝜒𝜏) → 𝜂)       ((𝜓𝜃) → 𝜂)
 
Theorembiimp3a 1323 Infer implication from a logical equivalence. Similar to biimpa 294. (Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2005.)
((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜒𝜃))       ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)
 
Theorembiimp3ar 1324 Infer implication from a logical equivalence. Similar to biimpar 295. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2009.)
((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜒𝜃))       ((𝜑𝜓𝜃) → 𝜒)
 
Theorem3anandis 1325 Inference that undistributes a triple conjunction in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 18-Apr-2007.)
(((𝜑𝜓) ∧ (𝜑𝜒) ∧ (𝜑𝜃)) → 𝜏)       ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒𝜃)) → 𝜏)
 
Theorem3anandirs 1326 Inference that undistributes a triple conjunction in the antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jul-2006.) (Revised by NM, 18-Apr-2007.)
(((𝜑𝜃) ∧ (𝜓𝜃) ∧ (𝜒𝜃)) → 𝜏)       (((𝜑𝜓𝜒) ∧ 𝜃) → 𝜏)
 
Theoremecased 1327 Deduction form of disjunctive syllogism. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 9-Dec-2017.)
(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremecase23d 1328 Variation of ecased 1327 with three disjuncts instead of two. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 9-Dec-2017.)
(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜃)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒𝜃))       (𝜑𝜓)
 
1.2.12  True and false constants
 
1.2.12.1  Universal quantifier for use by df-tru

Even though it isn't ordinarily part of propositional calculus, the universal quantifier is introduced here so that the soundness of definition df-tru 1334 can be checked by the same algorithm that is used for predicate calculus. Its first real use is in axiom ax-5 1423 in the predicate calculus section below. For those who want propositional calculus to be self-contained i.e. to use wff variables only, the alternate definition dftru2 1339 may be adopted and this subsection moved down to the start of the subsection with wex 1468 below. However, the use of dftru2 1339 as a definition requires a more elaborate definition checking algorithm that we prefer to avoid.

 
Syntaxwal 1329 Extend wff definition to include the universal quantifier ('for all'). 𝑥𝜑 is read "𝜑 (phi) is true for all 𝑥." Typically, in its final application 𝜑 would be replaced with a wff containing a (free) occurrence of the variable 𝑥, for example 𝑥 = 𝑦. In a universe with a finite number of objects, "for all" is equivalent to a big conjunction (AND) with one wff for each possible case of 𝑥. When the universe is infinite (as with set theory), such a propositional-calculus equivalent is not possible because an infinitely long formula has no meaning, but conceptually the idea is the same.
wff 𝑥𝜑
 
1.2.12.2  Equality predicate for use by df-tru

Even though it isn't ordinarily part of propositional calculus, the equality predicate = is introduced here so that the soundness of definition df-tru 1334 can be checked by the same algorithm as is used for predicate calculus. Its first real use is in axiom ax-8 1482 in the predicate calculus section below. For those who want propositional calculus to be self-contained i.e. to use wff variables only, the alternate definition dftru2 1339 may be adopted and this subsection moved down to just above weq 1479 below. However, the use of dftru2 1339 as a definition requires a more elaborate definition checking algorithm that we prefer to avoid.

 
Syntaxcv 1330 This syntax construction states that a variable 𝑥, which has been declared to be a setvar variable by $f statement vx, is also a class expression. This can be justified informally as follows. We know that the class builder {𝑦𝑦𝑥} is a class by cab 2125. Since (when 𝑦 is distinct from 𝑥) we have 𝑥 = {𝑦𝑦𝑥} by cvjust 2134, we can argue that the syntax "class 𝑥 " can be viewed as an abbreviation for "class {𝑦𝑦𝑥}". See the discussion under the definition of class in [Jech] p. 4 showing that "Every set can be considered to be a class."

While it is tempting and perhaps occasionally useful to view cv 1330 as a "type conversion" from a setvar variable to a class variable, keep in mind that cv 1330 is intrinsically no different from any other class-building syntax such as cab 2125, cun 3069, or c0 3363.

For a general discussion of the theory of classes and the role of cv 1330, see https://us.metamath.org/mpeuni/mmset.html#class 1330.

(The description above applies to set theory, not predicate calculus. The purpose of introducing class 𝑥 here, and not in set theory where it belongs, is to allow us to express i.e. "prove" the weq 1479 of predicate calculus from the wceq 1331 of set theory, so that we don't overload the = connective with two syntax definitions. This is done to prevent ambiguity that would complicate some Metamath parsers.)

class 𝑥
 
Syntaxwceq 1331 Extend wff definition to include class equality.

For a general discussion of the theory of classes, see https://us.metamath.org/mpeuni/mmset.html#class.

(The purpose of introducing wff 𝐴 = 𝐵 here, and not in set theory where it belongs, is to allow us to express i.e. "prove" the weq 1479 of predicate calculus in terms of the wceq 1331 of set theory, so that we don't "overload" the = connective with two syntax definitions. This is done to prevent ambiguity that would complicate some Metamath parsers. For example, some parsers - although not the Metamath program - stumble on the fact that the = in 𝑥 = 𝑦 could be the = of either weq 1479 or wceq 1331, although mathematically it makes no difference. The class variables 𝐴 and 𝐵 are introduced temporarily for the purpose of this definition but otherwise not used in predicate calculus. See df-cleq 2132 for more information on the set theory usage of wceq 1331.)

wff 𝐴 = 𝐵
 
1.2.12.3  Define the true and false constants
 
Syntaxwtru 1332 is a wff.
wff
 
Theoremtrujust 1333 Soundness justification theorem for df-tru 1334. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-Nov-2013.) (Revised by NM, 11-Jul-2019.)
((∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥 → ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥) ↔ (∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑦))
 
Definitiondf-tru 1334 Definition of the truth value "true", or "verum", denoted by . This is a tautology, as proved by tru 1335. In this definition, an instance of id 19 is used as the definiens, although any tautology, such as an axiom, can be used in its place. This particular id 19 instance was chosen so this definition can be checked by the same algorithm that is used for predicate calculus. This definition should be referenced directly only by tru 1335, and other proofs should depend on tru 1335 (directly or indirectly) instead of this definition, since there are many alternate ways to define . (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) (Revised by NM, 11-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(⊤ ↔ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥 → ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑥))
 
Theoremtru 1335 The truth value is provable. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.)
 
Syntaxwfal 1336 is a wff.
wff
 
Definitiondf-fal 1337 Definition of the truth value "false", or "falsum", denoted by . See also df-tru 1334. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
(⊥ ↔ ¬ ⊤)
 
Theoremfal 1338 The truth value is refutable. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 11-Mar-2012.)
¬ ⊥
 
Theoremdftru2 1339 An alternate definition of "true". (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 13-Oct-2010.) (Revised by BJ, 12-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(⊤ ↔ (𝜑𝜑))
 
Theoremmptru 1340 Eliminate as an antecedent. A proposition implied by is true. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Mar-2014.)
(⊤ → 𝜑)       𝜑
 
Theoremtbtru 1341 A proposition is equivalent to itself being equivalent to . (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 14-Aug-2011.)
(𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 ↔ ⊤))
 
Theoremnbfal 1342 The negation of a proposition is equivalent to itself being equivalent to . (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 14-Aug-2011.)
𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 ↔ ⊥))
 
Theorembitru 1343 A theorem is equivalent to truth. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.)
𝜑       (𝜑 ↔ ⊤)
 
Theorembifal 1344 A contradiction is equivalent to falsehood. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-May-2015.)
¬ 𝜑       (𝜑 ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalim 1345 The truth value implies anything. Also called the principle of explosion, or "ex falso quodlibet". (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Anthony Hart, 1-Aug-2011.)
(⊥ → 𝜑)
 
Theoremfalimd 1346 The truth value implies anything. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.)
((𝜑 ∧ ⊥) → 𝜓)
 
Theorema1tru 1347 Anything implies . (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Anthony Hart, 1-Aug-2011.)
(𝜑 → ⊤)
 
Theoremtruan 1348 True can be removed from a conjunction. (Contributed by FL, 20-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2019.)
((⊤ ∧ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜑)
 
Theoremdfnot 1349 Given falsum, we can define the negation of a wff 𝜑 as the statement that a contradiction follows from assuming 𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2019.)
𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 → ⊥))
 
Theoreminegd 1350 Negation introduction rule from natural deduction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.)
((𝜑𝜓) → ⊥)       (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓)
 
Theorempm2.21fal 1351 If a wff and its negation are provable, then falsum is provable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓)       (𝜑 → ⊥)
 
Theorempclem6 1352 Negation inferred from embedded conjunct. (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-1993.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2018.)
((𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)) → ¬ 𝜓)
 
1.2.13  Logical 'xor'
 
Syntaxwxo 1353 Extend wff definition to include exclusive disjunction ('xor').
wff (𝜑𝜓)
 
Definitiondf-xor 1354 Define exclusive disjunction (logical 'xor'). Return true if either the left or right, but not both, are true. Contrast with (wa 103), (wo 697), and (wi 4) . (Contributed by FL, 22-Nov-2010.) (Modified by Jim Kingdon, 1-Mar-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∧ ¬ (𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theoremxoranor 1355 One way of defining exclusive or. Equivalent to df-xor 1354. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon and Mario Carneiro, 1-Mar-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∧ (¬ 𝜑 ∨ ¬ 𝜓)))
 
Theoremexcxor 1356 This tautology shows that xor is really exclusive. (Contributed by FL, 22-Nov-2010.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theoremxoror 1357 XOR implies OR. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Apr-2019.)
((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremxorbi2d 1358 Deduction joining an equivalence and a left operand to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → ((𝜃𝜓) ↔ (𝜃𝜒)))
 
Theoremxorbi1d 1359 Deduction joining an equivalence and a right operand to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜃) ↔ (𝜒𝜃)))
 
Theoremxorbi12d 1360 Deduction joining two equivalences to form equivalence of exclusive-or. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜃𝜏))       (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜃) ↔ (𝜒𝜏)))
 
Theoremxorbi12i 1361 Equality property for XOR. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜒𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜒) ↔ (𝜓𝜃))
 
Theoremxorbin 1362 A consequence of exclusive or. In classical logic the converse also holds. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 8-Mar-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓))
 
Theorempm5.18im 1363 One direction of pm5.18dc 868, which holds for all propositions, not just decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Mar-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) → ¬ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓))
 
Theoremxornbi 1364 A consequence of exclusive or. For decidable propositions this is an equivalence, as seen at xornbidc 1369. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 10-Mar-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) → ¬ (𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremxor3dc 1365 Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Apr-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ (𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓))))
 
Theoremxorcom 1366 is commutative. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 6-Oct-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜓𝜑))
 
Theorempm5.15dc 1367 A decidable proposition is equivalent to a decidable proposition or its negation. Based on theorem *5.15 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Apr-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓))))
 
Theoremxor2dc 1368 Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Apr-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ (𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∧ ¬ (𝜑𝜓)))))
 
Theoremxornbidc 1369 Exclusive or is equivalent to negated biconditional for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Apr-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑𝜓))))
 
Theoremxordc 1370 Two ways to express "exclusive or" between decidable propositions. Theorem *5.22 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ (𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)))))
 
Theoremxordc1 1371 Exclusive or implies the left proposition is decidable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Mar-2018.)
((𝜑𝜓) → DECID 𝜑)
 
Theoremnbbndc 1372 Move negation outside of biconditional, for decidable propositions. Compare Theorem *5.18 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Apr-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((¬ 𝜑𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑𝜓))))
 
Theorembiassdc 1373 Associative law for the biconditional, for decidable propositions.

The classical version (without the decidability conditions) is an axiom of system DS in Vladimir Lifschitz, "On calculational proofs", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 113:207-224, 2002, http://www.cs.utexas.edu/users/ai-lab/pub-view.php?PubID=26805, and, interestingly, was not included in Principia Mathematica but was apparently first noted by Jan Lukasiewicz circa 1923. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 4-May-2018.)

(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (DECID 𝜒 → (((𝜑𝜓) ↔ 𝜒) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜓𝜒))))))
 
Theorembilukdc 1374 Lukasiewicz's shortest axiom for equivalential calculus (but modified to require decidable propositions). Storrs McCall, ed., Polish Logic 1920-1939 (Oxford, 1967), p. 96. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.)
(((DECID 𝜑DECID 𝜓) ∧ DECID 𝜒) → ((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜒𝜓) ↔ (𝜑𝜒))))
 
Theoremdfbi3dc 1375 An alternate definition of the biconditional for decidable propositions. Theorem *5.23 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but with decidability conditions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓)))))
 
Theorempm5.24dc 1376 Theorem *5.24 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124, but for decidable propositions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (¬ ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓)) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ ¬ 𝜑)))))
 
Theoremxordidc 1377 Conjunction distributes over exclusive-or, for decidable propositions. This is one way to interpret the distributive law of multiplication over addition in modulo 2 arithmetic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Jul-2018.)
(DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → (DECID 𝜒 → ((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒)) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ⊻ (𝜑𝜒))))))
 
Theoremanxordi 1378 Conjunction distributes over exclusive-or. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2018.)
((𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒)) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ⊻ (𝜑𝜒)))
 
1.2.14  Truth tables: Operations on true and false constants

For classical logic, truth tables can be used to define propositional logic operations, by showing the results of those operations for all possible combinations of true () and false ().

Although the intuitionistic logic connectives are not as simply defined, and do play similar roles as in classical logic and most theorems from classical logic continue to hold.

Here we show that our definitions and axioms produce equivalent results for and as we would get from truth tables for (conjunction aka logical 'and') wa 103, (disjunction aka logical inclusive 'or') wo 697, (implies) wi 4, ¬ (not) wn 3, (logical equivalence) df-bi 116, and (exclusive or) df-xor 1354.

 
Theoremtruantru 1379 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊤ ∧ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtruanfal 1380 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊤ ∧ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalantru 1381 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 23-Feb-2018.)
((⊥ ∧ ⊤) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalanfal 1382 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊥ ∧ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremtruortru 1383 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊤ ∨ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtruorfal 1384 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊤ ∨ ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalortru 1385 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊥ ∨ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalorfal 1386 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊥ ∨ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremtruimtru 1387 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊤ → ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtruimfal 1388 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊤ → ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalimtru 1389 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊥ → ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalimfal 1390 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
((⊥ → ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremnottru 1391 A ¬ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.)
(¬ ⊤ ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremnotfal 1392 A ¬ identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
(¬ ⊥ ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtrubitru 1393 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊤ ↔ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtrubifal 1394 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 23-Feb-2018.)
((⊤ ↔ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalbitru 1395 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊥ ↔ ⊤) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremfalbifal 1396 A identity. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
((⊥ ↔ ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremtruxortru 1397 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊤ ⊻ ⊤) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremtruxorfal 1398 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊤ ⊻ ⊥) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalxortru 1399 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊥ ⊻ ⊤) ↔ ⊤)
 
Theoremfalxorfal 1400 A identity. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 2-Mar-2018.)
((⊥ ⊻ ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13250
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >