![]() |
Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 16 of 156) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | hb3and 1501 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hb3an 1561. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → ∀𝑥𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃) → ∀𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | hbald 1502 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbal 1488. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑦𝜓 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Syntax | wex 1503 | Extend wff definition to include the existential quantifier ("there exists"). |
wff ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Axiom | ax-ie1 1504 | 𝑥 is bound in ∃𝑥𝜑. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-ie2 1505 | Define existential quantification. ∃𝑥𝜑 means "there exists at least one set 𝑥 such that 𝜑 is true". One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | hbe1 1506 | 𝑥 is not free in ∃𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfe1 1507 | 𝑥 is not free in ∃𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | 19.23ht 1508 | Closed form of Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2005.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | 19.23h 1509 | Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 1-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | alnex 1510 | Theorem 19.7 of [Margaris] p. 89. To read this intuitionistically, think of it as "if 𝜑 can be refuted for all 𝑥, then it is not possible to find an 𝑥 for which 𝜑 holds" (and likewise for the converse). Comparing this with dfexdc 1512 illustrates that statements which look similar (to someone used to classical logic) can be different intuitionistically due to different placement of negations. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 1-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-May-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑 ↔ ¬ ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nex 1511 | Generalization rule for negated wff. (Contributed by NM, 18-May-1994.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ¬ ∃𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | dfexdc 1512 | Defining ∃𝑥𝜑 given decidability. It is common in classical logic to define ∃𝑥𝜑 as ¬ ∀𝑥¬ 𝜑 but in intuitionistic logic without a decidability condition, that is only an implication not an equivalence, as seen at exalim 1513. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ (DECID ∃𝑥𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜑 ↔ ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | exalim 1513 | One direction of a classical definition of existential quantification. One direction of Definition of [Margaris] p. 49. For a decidable proposition, this is an equivalence, as seen as dfexdc 1512. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑) | ||
The equality predicate was introduced above in wceq 1364 for use by df-tru 1367. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it. | ||
Theorem | weq 1514 |
Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas using the equality
predicate.
(Instead of introducing weq 1514 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wceq 1364. This lets us avoid overloading the = connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically weq 1514 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wceq 1364. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "show proof weq /all" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.) |
wff 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Axiom | ax-8 1515 |
Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms of
predicate calculus with equality. This is similar to, but not quite, a
transitive law for equality (proved later as equtr 1720). Axiom scheme C8'
in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint).
Also appears as Axiom C7 of
[Monk2] p. 105.
Axioms ax-8 1515 through ax-16 1825 are the axioms having to do with equality, substitution, and logical properties of our binary predicate ∈ (which later in set theory will mean "is a member of"). Note that all axioms except ax-16 1825 and ax-17 1537 are still valid even when 𝑥, 𝑦, and 𝑧 are replaced with the same variable because they do not have any distinct variable (Metamath's $d) restrictions. Distinct variable restrictions are required for ax-16 1825 and ax-17 1537 only. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑧 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) | ||
Axiom | ax-10 1516 |
Axiom of Quantifier Substitution. One of the equality and substitution
axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Appears as Lemma L12 in
[Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint).
The original version of this axiom was ax-10o 1727 ("o" for "old") and was replaced with this shorter ax-10 1516 in May 2008. The old axiom is proved from this one as Theorem ax10o 1726. Conversely, this axiom is proved from ax-10o 1727 as Theorem ax10 1728. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥) | ||
Axiom | ax-11 1517 |
Axiom of Variable Substitution. One of the 5 equality axioms of predicate
calculus. The final consequent ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) is a way of
expressing "𝑦 substituted for 𝑥 in wff
𝜑
" (cf. sb6 1898). It
is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and
Axiom C8 of [Monk2] p. 105,
from which it can be proved by cases.
Variants of this axiom which are equivalent in classical logic but which have not been shown to be equivalent for intuitionistic logic are ax11v 1838, ax11v2 1831 and ax-11o 1834. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑))) | ||
Axiom | ax-i12 1518 |
Axiom of Quantifier Introduction. One of the equality and substitution
axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Informally, it says that
whenever 𝑧 is distinct from 𝑥 and
𝑦,
and 𝑥 =
𝑦 is true,
then 𝑥 = 𝑦 quantified with 𝑧 is also
true. In other words, 𝑧
is irrelevant to the truth of 𝑥 = 𝑦. Axiom scheme C9' in [Megill]
p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear
in the literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by
cases.
This axiom has been modified from the original ax12 1523 for compatibility with intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) Use its alias ax12or 1519 instead, for labeling consistency. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | ax12or 1519 | Alias for ax-i12 1518, to be used in place of it for labeling consistency. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Axiom | ax-bndl 1520 |
Axiom of bundling. The general idea of this axiom is that two variables
are either distinct or non-distinct. That idea could be expressed as
∀𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ ¬ ∀𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥. However, we instead choose an axiom
which has many of the same consequences, but which is different with
respect to a universe which contains only one object. ∀𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥 holds
if 𝑧 and 𝑥 are the same variable,
likewise for 𝑧 and 𝑦,
and ∀𝑥∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧𝑥 = 𝑦) holds if 𝑧 is distinct from
the others (and the universe has at least two objects).
As with other statements of the form "x is decidable (either true or false)", this does not entail the full Law of the Excluded Middle (which is the proposition that all statements are decidable), but instead merely the assertion that particular kinds of statements are decidable (or in this case, an assertion similar to decidability). This axiom implies ax-i12 1518 as can be seen at axi12 1525. Whether ax-bndl 1520 can be proved from the remaining axioms including ax-i12 1518 is not known. The reason we call this "bundling" is that a statement without a distinct variable constraint "bundles" together two statements, one in which the two variables are the same and one in which they are different. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑥∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Axiom | ax-4 1521 |
Axiom of Specialization. A quantified wff implies the wff without a
quantifier (i.e. an instance, or special case, of the generalized wff).
In other words if something is true for all 𝑥, it is true for any
specific 𝑥 (that would typically occur as a free
variable in the wff
substituted for 𝜑). (A free variable is one that does
not occur in
the scope of a quantifier: 𝑥 and 𝑦 are both free in 𝑥 = 𝑦,
but only 𝑥 is free in ∀𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦.) Axiom scheme C5' in [Megill]
p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom B5 of [Tarski]
p. 67 (under his system S2, defined in the last paragraph on p. 77).
Note that the converse of this axiom does not hold in general, but a weaker inference form of the converse holds and is expressed as rule ax-gen 1460. Conditional forms of the converse are given by ax12 1523, ax-16 1825, and ax-17 1537. Unlike the more general textbook Axiom of Specialization, we cannot choose a variable different from 𝑥 for the special case. For use, that requires the assistance of equality axioms, and we deal with it later after we introduce the definition of proper substitution - see stdpc4 1786. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sp 1522 | Specialization. Another name for ax-4 1521. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-2008.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | ax12 1523 | Rederive the original version of the axiom from ax-i12 1518. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 → (¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | hbequid 1524 |
Bound-variable hypothesis builder for 𝑥 = 𝑥. This theorem tells us
that any variable, including 𝑥, is effectively not free in
𝑥 =
𝑥, even though 𝑥 is
technically free according to the
traditional definition of free variable.
The proof uses only ax-8 1515 and ax-i12 1518 on top of (the FOL analogue of) modal logic KT. This shows that this can be proved without ax-i9 1541, even though Theorem equid 1712 cannot. A shorter proof using ax-i9 1541 is obtainable from equid 1712 and hbth 1474. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 23-Mar-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑥 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 = 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | axi12 1525 | Proof that ax-i12 1518 follows from ax-bndl 1520. So that we can track which theorems rely on ax-bndl 1520, proofs should reference ax12or 1519 rather than this theorem. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Aug-2018.) (New usage is discouraged). (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | alequcom 1526 | Commutation law for identical variable specifiers. The antecedent and consequent are true when 𝑥 and 𝑦 are substituted with the same variable. Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | alequcoms 1527 | A commutation rule for identical variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nalequcoms 1528 | A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfr 1529 | Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | nfri 1530 | Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfrd 1531 | Consequence of the definition of not-free in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | alimd 1532 | Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | alrimi 1533 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfd 1534 | Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfdh 1535 | Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfrimi 1536 | Moving an antecedent outside Ⅎ. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Axiom | ax-17 1537* |
Axiom to quantify a variable over a formula in which it does not occur.
Axiom C5 in [Megill] p. 444 (p. 11 of the
preprint). Also appears as
Axiom B6 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski]
p. 77 and Axiom C5-1 of
[Monk2] p. 113.
(Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | a17d 1538* | ax-17 1537 with antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfv 1539* | If 𝑥 is not present in 𝜑, then 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfvd 1540* | nfv 1539 with antecedent. Useful in proofs of deduction versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders such as nfimd 1596. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Axiom | ax-i9 1541 | Axiom of Existence. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. One thing this axiom tells us is that at least one thing exists (although ax-4 1521 and possibly others also tell us that, i.e. they are not valid in the empty domain of a "free logic"). In this form (not requiring that 𝑥 and 𝑦 be distinct) it was used in an axiom system of Tarski (see Axiom B7' in footnote 1 of [KalishMontague] p. 81.) Another name for this theorem is a9e 1707, which has additional remarks. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | ax-9 1542 | Derive ax-9 1542 from ax-i9 1541, the modified version for intuitionistic logic. Although ax-9 1542 does hold intuistionistically, in intuitionistic logic it is weaker than ax-i9 1541. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | equidqe 1543 | equid 1712 with some quantification and negation without using ax-4 1521 or ax-17 1537. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 27-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ¬ ∀𝑦 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥 | ||
Theorem | ax4sp1 1544 | A special case of ax-4 1521 without using ax-4 1521 or ax-17 1537. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥 → ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥) | ||
Axiom | ax-ial 1545 | 𝑥 is not free in ∀𝑥𝜑. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-i5r 1546 | Axiom of quantifier collection. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | spi 1547 | Inference reversing generalization (specialization). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ ∀𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | sps 1548 | Generalization of antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | spsd 1549 | Deduction generalizing antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 17-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfbidf 1550 | An equality theorem for effectively not free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ↔ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | hba1 1551 | 𝑥 is not free in ∀𝑥𝜑. Example in Appendix in [Megill] p. 450 (p. 19 of the preprint). Also Lemma 22 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfa1 1552 | 𝑥 is not free in ∀𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | axc4i 1553 | Inference version of 19.21 1594. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | a5i 1554 | Inference generalizing a consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfnf1 1555 | 𝑥 is not free in Ⅎ𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | hbim 1556 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 → 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 3-Mar-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hbor 1557 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hban 1558 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hbbi 1559 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hb3or 1560 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | hb3an 1561 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | hba2 1562 | Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | hbia1 1563 | Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.3h 1564 | A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-May-2007.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.3 1565 | A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.16 1566 | Theorem 19.16 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.17 1567 | Theorem 19.17 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.21h 1568 | Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". New proofs should use 19.21 1594 instead. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.21bi 1569 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.21bbi 1570 | Inference removing double quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 20-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.27h 1571 | Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.27 1572 | Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.28h 1573 | Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.28 1574 | Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfan1 1575 | A closed form of nfan 1576. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfan 1576 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nf3an 1577 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | nford 1578 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜓 ∨ 𝜒). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Oct-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ∨ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfand 1579 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nf3and 1580 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder nf3an 1577. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | hbim1 1581 | A closed form of hbim 1556. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfim1 1582 | A closed form of nfim 1583. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfim 1583 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 → 𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | hbimd 1584 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbim 1556. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | nfor 1585 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | hbbid 1586 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbbi 1559. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ↔ 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | nfal 1587 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in ∀𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) Remove dependency on ax-4 1521. (Revised by GG, 25-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfnf 1588 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in Ⅎ𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfalt 1589 | Closed form of nfal 1587. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfa2 1590 | Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfia1 1591 | Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.21ht 1592 | Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | 19.21t 1593 | Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) |
⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | 19.21 1594 | Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | stdpc5 1595 | An axiom scheme of standard predicate calculus that emulates Axiom 5 of [Mendelson] p. 69. The hypothesis Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 can be thought of as emulating "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". With this definition, the meaning of "not free" is less restrictive than the usual textbook definition; for example 𝑥 would not (for us) be free in 𝑥 = 𝑥 by nfequid 1713. This theorem scheme can be proved as a metatheorem of Mendelson's axiom system, even though it is slightly stronger than his Axiom 5. (Contributed by NM, 22-Sep-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 1-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfimd 1596 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜓 → 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | aaanh 1597 | Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | aaan 1598 | Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfbid 1599 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 29-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfbi 1600 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, then it is not free in (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |