Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 16 of 144) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
The equality predicate was introduced above in wceq 1353 for use by df-tru 1356. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it. | ||
Theorem | weq 1501 |
Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas using the equality
predicate.
(Instead of introducing weq 1501 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wceq 1353. This lets us avoid overloading the = connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically weq 1501 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wceq 1353. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "show proof weq /all" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.) |
wff 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Axiom | ax-8 1502 |
Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms of
predicate calculus with equality. This is similar to, but not quite, a
transitive law for equality (proved later as equtr 1707). Axiom scheme C8'
in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint).
Also appears as Axiom C7 of
[Monk2] p. 105.
Axioms ax-8 1502 through ax-16 1812 are the axioms having to do with equality, substitution, and logical properties of our binary predicate ∈ (which later in set theory will mean "is a member of"). Note that all axioms except ax-16 1812 and ax-17 1524 are still valid even when 𝑥, 𝑦, and 𝑧 are replaced with the same variable because they do not have any distinct variable (Metamath's $d) restrictions. Distinct variable restrictions are required for ax-16 1812 and ax-17 1524 only. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑧 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) | ||
Axiom | ax-10 1503 |
Axiom of Quantifier Substitution. One of the equality and substitution
axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Appears as Lemma L12 in
[Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint).
The original version of this axiom was ax-10o 1714 ("o" for "old") and was replaced with this shorter ax-10 1503 in May 2008. The old axiom is proved from this one as Theorem ax10o 1713. Conversely, this axiom is proved from ax-10o 1714 as Theorem ax10 1715. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥) | ||
Axiom | ax-11 1504 |
Axiom of Variable Substitution. One of the 5 equality axioms of predicate
calculus. The final consequent ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) is a way of
expressing "𝑦 substituted for 𝑥 in wff
𝜑
" (cf. sb6 1884). It
is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and
Axiom C8 of [Monk2] p. 105,
from which it can be proved by cases.
Variants of this axiom which are equivalent in classical logic but which have not been shown to be equivalent for intuitionistic logic are ax11v 1825, ax11v2 1818 and ax-11o 1821. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑))) | ||
Axiom | ax-i12 1505 |
Axiom of Quantifier Introduction. One of the equality and substitution
axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Informally, it says that
whenever 𝑧 is distinct from 𝑥 and
𝑦,
and 𝑥 =
𝑦 is true,
then 𝑥 = 𝑦 quantified with 𝑧 is also
true. In other words, 𝑧
is irrelevant to the truth of 𝑥 = 𝑦. Axiom scheme C9' in [Megill]
p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear
in the literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by
cases.
This axiom has been modified from the original ax12 1510 for compatibility with intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) Use its alias ax12or 1506 instead, for labeling consistency. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | ax12or 1506 | Alias for ax-i12 1505, to be used in place of it for labeling consistency. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Axiom | ax-bndl 1507 |
Axiom of bundling. The general idea of this axiom is that two variables
are either distinct or non-distinct. That idea could be expressed as
∀𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ ¬ ∀𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥. However, we instead choose an axiom
which has many of the same consequences, but which is different with
respect to a universe which contains only one object. ∀𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥 holds
if 𝑧 and 𝑥 are the same variable,
likewise for 𝑧 and 𝑦,
and ∀𝑥∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧𝑥 = 𝑦) holds if 𝑧 is distinct from
the others (and the universe has at least two objects).
As with other statements of the form "x is decidable (either true or false)", this does not entail the full Law of the Excluded Middle (which is the proposition that all statements are decidable), but instead merely the assertion that particular kinds of statements are decidable (or in this case, an assertion similar to decidability). This axiom implies ax-i12 1505 as can be seen at axi12 1512. Whether ax-bndl 1507 can be proved from the remaining axioms including ax-i12 1505 is not known. The reason we call this "bundling" is that a statement without a distinct variable constraint "bundles" together two statements, one in which the two variables are the same and one in which they are different. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑥∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Axiom | ax-4 1508 |
Axiom of Specialization. A quantified wff implies the wff without a
quantifier (i.e. an instance, or special case, of the generalized wff).
In other words if something is true for all 𝑥, it is true for any
specific 𝑥 (that would typically occur as a free
variable in the wff
substituted for 𝜑). (A free variable is one that does
not occur in
the scope of a quantifier: 𝑥 and 𝑦 are both free in 𝑥 = 𝑦,
but only 𝑥 is free in ∀𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦.) Axiom scheme C5' in [Megill]
p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom B5 of [Tarski]
p. 67 (under his system S2, defined in the last paragraph on p. 77).
Note that the converse of this axiom does not hold in general, but a weaker inference form of the converse holds and is expressed as rule ax-gen 1447. Conditional forms of the converse are given by ax12 1510, ax-16 1812, and ax-17 1524. Unlike the more general textbook Axiom of Specialization, we cannot choose a variable different from 𝑥 for the special case. For use, that requires the assistance of equality axioms, and we deal with it later after we introduce the definition of proper substitution - see stdpc4 1773. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sp 1509 | Specialization. Another name for ax-4 1508. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-2008.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | ax12 1510 | Rederive the original version of the axiom from ax-i12 1505. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 → (¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | hbequid 1511 |
Bound-variable hypothesis builder for 𝑥 = 𝑥. This theorem tells us
that any variable, including 𝑥, is effectively not free in
𝑥 =
𝑥, even though 𝑥 is
technically free according to the
traditional definition of free variable.
The proof uses only ax-8 1502 and ax-i12 1505 on top of (the FOL analogue of) modal logic KT. This shows that this can be proved without ax-i9 1528, even though Theorem equid 1699 cannot. A shorter proof using ax-i9 1528 is obtainable from equid 1699 and hbth 1461. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 23-Mar-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑥 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 = 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | axi12 1512 | Proof that ax-i12 1505 follows from ax-bndl 1507. So that we can track which theorems rely on ax-bndl 1507, proofs should reference ax12or 1506 rather than this theorem. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Aug-2018.) (New usage is discouraged). (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | alequcom 1513 | Commutation law for identical variable specifiers. The antecedent and consequent are true when 𝑥 and 𝑦 are substituted with the same variable. Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | alequcoms 1514 | A commutation rule for identical variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nalequcoms 1515 | A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfr 1516 | Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | nfri 1517 | Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfrd 1518 | Consequence of the definition of not-free in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | alimd 1519 | Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | alrimi 1520 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfd 1521 | Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfdh 1522 | Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfrimi 1523 | Moving an antecedent outside Ⅎ. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Axiom | ax-17 1524* |
Axiom to quantify a variable over a formula in which it does not occur.
Axiom C5 in [Megill] p. 444 (p. 11 of the
preprint). Also appears as
Axiom B6 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski]
p. 77 and Axiom C5-1 of
[Monk2] p. 113.
(Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | a17d 1525* | ax-17 1524 with antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfv 1526* | If 𝑥 is not present in 𝜑, then 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfvd 1527* | nfv 1526 with antecedent. Useful in proofs of deduction versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders such as nfimd 1583. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) | ||
Axiom | ax-i9 1528 | Axiom of Existence. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. One thing this axiom tells us is that at least one thing exists (although ax-4 1508 and possibly others also tell us that, i.e. they are not valid in the empty domain of a "free logic"). In this form (not requiring that 𝑥 and 𝑦 be distinct) it was used in an axiom system of Tarski (see Axiom B7' in footnote 1 of [KalishMontague] p. 81.) Another name for this theorem is a9e 1694, which has additional remarks. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | ax-9 1529 | Derive ax-9 1529 from ax-i9 1528, the modified version for intuitionistic logic. Although ax-9 1529 does hold intuistionistically, in intuitionistic logic it is weaker than ax-i9 1528. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ ¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | equidqe 1530 | equid 1699 with some quantification and negation without using ax-4 1508 or ax-17 1524. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 27-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ¬ ∀𝑦 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥 | ||
Theorem | ax4sp1 1531 | A special case of ax-4 1508 without using ax-4 1508 or ax-17 1524. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥 → ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥) | ||
Axiom | ax-ial 1532 | 𝑥 is not free in ∀𝑥𝜑. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-i5r 1533 | Axiom of quantifier collection. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | spi 1534 | Inference reversing generalization (specialization). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ ∀𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | sps 1535 | Generalization of antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | spsd 1536 | Deduction generalizing antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 17-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfbidf 1537 | An equality theorem for effectively not free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ↔ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | hba1 1538 | 𝑥 is not free in ∀𝑥𝜑. Example in Appendix in [Megill] p. 450 (p. 19 of the preprint). Also Lemma 22 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfa1 1539 | 𝑥 is not free in ∀𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | axc4i 1540 | Inference version of 19.21 1581. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | a5i 1541 | Inference generalizing a consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfnf1 1542 | 𝑥 is not free in Ⅎ𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | hbim 1543 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 → 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 3-Mar-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hbor 1544 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hban 1545 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hbbi 1546 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hb3or 1547 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | hb3an 1548 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | hba2 1549 | Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | hbia1 1550 | Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.3h 1551 | A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-May-2007.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.3 1552 | A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.16 1553 | Theorem 19.16 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.17 1554 | Theorem 19.17 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.21h 1555 | Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". New proofs should use 19.21 1581 instead. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.21bi 1556 | Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.21bbi 1557 | Inference removing double quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 20-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.27h 1558 | Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.27 1559 | Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.28h 1560 | Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 19.28 1561 | Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfan1 1562 | A closed form of nfan 1563. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfan 1563 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nf3an 1564 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | nford 1565 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜓 ∨ 𝜒). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Oct-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ∨ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfand 1566 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nf3and 1567 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder nf3an 1564. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒 ∧ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | hbim1 1568 | A closed form of hbim 1543. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfim1 1569 | A closed form of nfim 1570. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | nfim 1570 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 → 𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | hbimd 1571 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbim 1543. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | nfor 1572 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | hbbid 1573 | Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbbi 1546. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ↔ 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | nfal 1574 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in ∀𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) Remove dependency on ax-4 1508. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 25-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfnf 1575 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in Ⅎ𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfalt 1576 | Closed form of nfal 1574. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfa2 1577 | Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜑 | ||
Theorem | nfia1 1578 | Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.21ht 1579 | Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | 19.21t 1580 | Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) |
⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | 19.21 1581 | Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | stdpc5 1582 | An axiom scheme of standard predicate calculus that emulates Axiom 5 of [Mendelson] p. 69. The hypothesis Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 can be thought of as emulating "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". With this definition, the meaning of "not free" is less restrictive than the usual textbook definition; for example 𝑥 would not (for us) be free in 𝑥 = 𝑥 by nfequid 1700. This theorem scheme can be proved as a metatheorem of Mendelson's axiom system, even though it is slightly stronger than his Axiom 5. (Contributed by NM, 22-Sep-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 1-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfimd 1583 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜓 → 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | aaanh 1584 | Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | aaan 1585 | Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfbid 1586 | If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 29-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | nfbi 1587 | If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, then it is not free in (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.8a 1588 | If a wff is true, then it is true for at least one instance. Special case of Theorem 19.8 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 19.8ad 1589 | If a wff is true, it is true for at least one instance. Deduction form of 19.8a 1588. (Contributed by DAW, 13-Feb-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 19.23bi 1590 | Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | exlimih 1591 | Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | exlimi 1592 | Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | exlimd2 1593 | Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. Similar to exlimdh 1594 but with one slightly different hypothesis. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Dec-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | exlimdh 1594 | Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 28-Jan-1997.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | exlimd 1595 | Deduction from Theorem 19.9 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | exlimiv 1596* |
Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p.
90.
This inference, along with our many variants is used to implement a metatheorem called "Rule C" that is given in many logic textbooks. See, for example, Rule C in [Mendelson] p. 81, Rule C in [Margaris] p. 40, or Rule C in Hirst and Hirst's A Primer for Logic and Proof p. 59 (PDF p. 65) at http://www.mathsci.appstate.edu/~jlh/primer/hirst.pdf. In informal proofs, the statement "Let C be an element such that..." almost always means an implicit application of Rule C. In essence, Rule C states that if we can prove that some element 𝑥 exists satisfying a wff, i.e. ∃𝑥𝜑(𝑥) where 𝜑(𝑥) has 𝑥 free, then we can use 𝜑( C ) as a hypothesis for the proof where C is a new (ficticious) constant not appearing previously in the proof, nor in any axioms used, nor in the theorem to be proved. The purpose of Rule C is to get rid of the existential quantifier. We cannot do this in Metamath directly. Instead, we use the original 𝜑 (containing 𝑥) as an antecedent for the main part of the proof. We eventually arrive at (𝜑 → 𝜓) where 𝜓 is the theorem to be proved and does not contain 𝑥. Then we apply exlimiv 1596 to arrive at (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓). Finally, we separately prove ∃𝑥𝜑 and detach it with modus ponens ax-mp 5 to arrive at the final theorem 𝜓. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 25-Jul-2012.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | exim 1597 | Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | eximi 1598 | Inference adding existential quantifier to antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 2eximi 1599 | Inference adding 2 existential quantifiers to antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜑 → ∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | eximii 1600 | Inference associated with eximi 1598. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Feb-2018.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑥𝜓 |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |