HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 16 of 144)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 1501-1600   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
1.3.2  Equality predicate (continued)

The equality predicate was introduced above in wceq 1353 for use by df-tru 1356. See the comments in that section. In this section, we continue with the first "real" use of it.

 
Theoremweq 1501 Extend wff definition to include atomic formulas using the equality predicate.

(Instead of introducing weq 1501 as an axiomatic statement, as was done in an older version of this database, we introduce it by "proving" a special case of set theory's more general wceq 1353. This lets us avoid overloading the = connective, thus preventing ambiguity that would complicate certain Metamath parsers. However, logically weq 1501 is considered to be a primitive syntax, even though here it is artificially "derived" from wceq 1353. Note: To see the proof steps of this syntax proof, type "show proof weq /all" in the Metamath program.) (Contributed by NM, 24-Jan-2006.)

wff 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Axiomax-8 1502 Axiom of Equality. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. This is similar to, but not quite, a transitive law for equality (proved later as equtr 1707). Axiom scheme C8' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom C7 of [Monk2] p. 105.

Axioms ax-8 1502 through ax-16 1812 are the axioms having to do with equality, substitution, and logical properties of our binary predicate (which later in set theory will mean "is a member of"). Note that all axioms except ax-16 1812 and ax-17 1524 are still valid even when 𝑥, 𝑦, and 𝑧 are replaced with the same variable because they do not have any distinct variable (Metamath's $d) restrictions. Distinct variable restrictions are required for ax-16 1812 and ax-17 1524 only. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑧𝑦 = 𝑧))
 
Axiomax-10 1503 Axiom of Quantifier Substitution. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Appears as Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint).

The original version of this axiom was ax-10o 1714 ("o" for "old") and was replaced with this shorter ax-10 1503 in May 2008. The old axiom is proved from this one as Theorem ax10o 1713. Conversely, this axiom is proved from ax-10o 1714 as Theorem ax10 1715. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥)
 
Axiomax-11 1504 Axiom of Variable Substitution. One of the 5 equality axioms of predicate calculus. The final consequent 𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) is a way of expressing "𝑦 substituted for 𝑥 in wff 𝜑 " (cf. sb6 1884). It is based on Lemma 16 of [Tarski] p. 70 and Axiom C8 of [Monk2] p. 105, from which it can be proved by cases.

Variants of this axiom which are equivalent in classical logic but which have not been shown to be equivalent for intuitionistic logic are ax11v 1825, ax11v2 1818 and ax-11o 1821. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)))
 
Axiomax-i12 1505 Axiom of Quantifier Introduction. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. Informally, it says that whenever 𝑧 is distinct from 𝑥 and 𝑦, and 𝑥 = 𝑦 is true, then 𝑥 = 𝑦 quantified with 𝑧 is also true. In other words, 𝑧 is irrelevant to the truth of 𝑥 = 𝑦. Axiom scheme C9' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). It apparently does not otherwise appear in the literature but is easily proved from textbook predicate calculus by cases.

This axiom has been modified from the original ax12 1510 for compatibility with intuitionistic logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.) Use its alias ax12or 1506 instead, for labeling consistency. (New usage is discouraged.)

(∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremax12or 1506 Alias for ax-i12 1505, to be used in place of it for labeling consistency. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.)
(∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Axiomax-bndl 1507 Axiom of bundling. The general idea of this axiom is that two variables are either distinct or non-distinct. That idea could be expressed as 𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ ¬ ∀𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥. However, we instead choose an axiom which has many of the same consequences, but which is different with respect to a universe which contains only one object. 𝑧𝑧 = 𝑥 holds if 𝑧 and 𝑥 are the same variable, likewise for 𝑧 and 𝑦, and 𝑥𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧𝑥 = 𝑦) holds if 𝑧 is distinct from the others (and the universe has at least two objects).

As with other statements of the form "x is decidable (either true or false)", this does not entail the full Law of the Excluded Middle (which is the proposition that all statements are decidable), but instead merely the assertion that particular kinds of statements are decidable (or in this case, an assertion similar to decidability).

This axiom implies ax-i12 1505 as can be seen at axi12 1512. Whether ax-bndl 1507 can be proved from the remaining axioms including ax-i12 1505 is not known.

The reason we call this "bundling" is that a statement without a distinct variable constraint "bundles" together two statements, one in which the two variables are the same and one in which they are different. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 14-Mar-2018.)

(∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑥𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Axiomax-4 1508 Axiom of Specialization. A quantified wff implies the wff without a quantifier (i.e. an instance, or special case, of the generalized wff). In other words if something is true for all 𝑥, it is true for any specific 𝑥 (that would typically occur as a free variable in the wff substituted for 𝜑). (A free variable is one that does not occur in the scope of a quantifier: 𝑥 and 𝑦 are both free in 𝑥 = 𝑦, but only 𝑥 is free in 𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦.) Axiom scheme C5' in [Megill] p. 448 (p. 16 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom B5 of [Tarski] p. 67 (under his system S2, defined in the last paragraph on p. 77).

Note that the converse of this axiom does not hold in general, but a weaker inference form of the converse holds and is expressed as rule ax-gen 1447. Conditional forms of the converse are given by ax12 1510, ax-16 1812, and ax-17 1524.

Unlike the more general textbook Axiom of Specialization, we cannot choose a variable different from 𝑥 for the special case. For use, that requires the assistance of equality axioms, and we deal with it later after we introduce the definition of proper substitution - see stdpc4 1773.

(Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(∀𝑥𝜑𝜑)
 
Theoremsp 1509 Specialization. Another name for ax-4 1508. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-2008.)
(∀𝑥𝜑𝜑)
 
Theoremax12 1510 Rederive the original version of the axiom from ax-i12 1505. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Feb-2015.)
(¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 → (¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremhbequid 1511 Bound-variable hypothesis builder for 𝑥 = 𝑥. This theorem tells us that any variable, including 𝑥, is effectively not free in 𝑥 = 𝑥, even though 𝑥 is technically free according to the traditional definition of free variable.

The proof uses only ax-8 1502 and ax-i12 1505 on top of (the FOL analogue of) modal logic KT. This shows that this can be proved without ax-i9 1528, even though Theorem equid 1699 cannot. A shorter proof using ax-i9 1528 is obtainable from equid 1699 and hbth 1461. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 23-Mar-2014.)

(𝑥 = 𝑥 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 = 𝑥)
 
Theoremaxi12 1512 Proof that ax-i12 1505 follows from ax-bndl 1507. So that we can track which theorems rely on ax-bndl 1507, proofs should reference ax12or 1506 rather than this theorem. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Aug-2018.) (New usage is discouraged). (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∨ (∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦 ∨ ∀𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑧 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremalequcom 1513 Commutation law for identical variable specifiers. The antecedent and consequent are true when 𝑥 and 𝑦 are substituted with the same variable. Lemma L12 in [Megill] p. 445 (p. 12 of the preprint). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥)
 
Theoremalequcoms 1514 A commutation rule for identical variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       (∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnalequcoms 1515 A commutation rule for distinct variable specifiers. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnfr 1516 Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Sep-2016.)
(Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑))
 
Theoremnfri 1517 Consequence of the definition of not-free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝜑       (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnfrd 1518 Consequence of the definition of not-free in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
(𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)       (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremalimd 1519 Deduction from Theorem 19.20 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜒))
 
Theoremalrimi 1520 Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremnfd 1521 Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremnfdh 1522 Deduce that 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 in a context. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremnfrimi 1523 Moving an antecedent outside . (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Mar-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑥(𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)
 
1.3.3  Axiom ax-17 - first use of the $d distinct variable statement
 
Axiomax-17 1524* Axiom to quantify a variable over a formula in which it does not occur. Axiom C5 in [Megill] p. 444 (p. 11 of the preprint). Also appears as Axiom B6 (p. 75) of system S2 of [Tarski] p. 77 and Axiom C5-1 of [Monk2] p. 113.

(Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)

(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)
 
Theorema17d 1525* ax-17 1524 with antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 1-Mar-2013.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremnfv 1526* If 𝑥 is not present in 𝜑, then 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremnfvd 1527* nfv 1526 with antecedent. Useful in proofs of deduction versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders such as nfimd 1583. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2016.)
(𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)
 
1.3.4  Introduce Axiom of Existence
 
Axiomax-i9 1528 Axiom of Existence. One of the equality and substitution axioms of predicate calculus with equality. One thing this axiom tells us is that at least one thing exists (although ax-4 1508 and possibly others also tell us that, i.e. they are not valid in the empty domain of a "free logic"). In this form (not requiring that 𝑥 and 𝑦 be distinct) it was used in an axiom system of Tarski (see Axiom B7' in footnote 1 of [KalishMontague] p. 81.) Another name for this theorem is a9e 1694, which has additional remarks. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Theoremax-9 1529 Derive ax-9 1529 from ax-i9 1528, the modified version for intuitionistic logic. Although ax-9 1529 does hold intuistionistically, in intuitionistic logic it is weaker than ax-i9 1528. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2015.)
¬ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦
 
Theoremequidqe 1530 equid 1699 with some quantification and negation without using ax-4 1508 or ax-17 1524. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 27-Feb-2014.)
¬ ∀𝑦 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥
 
Theoremax4sp1 1531 A special case of ax-4 1508 without using ax-4 1508 or ax-17 1524. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2011.)
(∀𝑦 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥 → ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑥)
 
1.3.5  Additional intuitionistic axioms
 
Axiomax-ial 1532 𝑥 is not free in 𝑥𝜑. One of the axioms of predicate logic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑥𝜑)
 
Axiomax-i5r 1533 Axiom of quantifier collection. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2015.)
((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑𝜓))
 
1.3.6  Predicate calculus including ax-4, without distinct variables
 
Theoremspi 1534 Inference reversing generalization (specialization). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
𝑥𝜑       𝜑
 
Theoremsps 1535 Generalization of antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremspsd 1536 Deduction generalizing antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 17-Aug-1994.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremnfbidf 1537 An equality theorem for effectively not free. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Oct-2016.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ↔ Ⅎ𝑥𝜒))
 
Theoremhba1 1538 𝑥 is not free in 𝑥𝜑. Example in Appendix in [Megill] p. 450 (p. 19 of the preprint). Also Lemma 22 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremnfa1 1539 𝑥 is not free in 𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremaxc4i 1540 Inference version of 19.21 1581. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.)
(∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorema5i 1541 Inference generalizing a consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremnfnf1 1542 𝑥 is not free in 𝑥𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremhbim 1543 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by O'Cat, 3-Mar-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       ((𝜑𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremhbor 1544 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       ((𝜑𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremhban 1545 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-Feb-2015.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       ((𝜑𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremhbbi 1546 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       ((𝜑𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremhb3or 1547 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓𝜒). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)       ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremhb3an 1548 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓𝜒). (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)       ((𝜑𝜓𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremhba2 1549 Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.)
(∀𝑦𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑦𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremhbia1 1550 Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by NM, 29-May-2008.)
((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theorem19.3h 1551 A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 21-May-2007.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜑)
 
Theorem19.3 1552 A wff may be quantified with a variable not free in it. Theorem 19.3 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥𝜑       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜑)
 
Theorem19.16 1553 Theorem 19.16 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.)
𝑥𝜑       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) → (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theorem19.17 1554 Theorem 19.17 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.)
𝑥𝜓       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓))
 
Theorem19.21h 1555 Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". New proofs should use 19.21 1581 instead. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theorem19.21bi 1556 Inference from Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       (𝜑𝜓)
 
Theorem19.21bbi 1557 Inference removing double quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 20-Apr-1994.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑦𝜓)       (𝜑𝜓)
 
Theorem19.27h 1558 Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓))
 
Theorem19.27 1559 Theorem 19.27 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
𝑥𝜓       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓))
 
Theorem19.28h 1560 Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theorem19.28 1561 Theorem 19.28 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
𝑥𝜑       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremnfan1 1562 A closed form of nfan 1563. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2016.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)       𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremnfan 1563 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Jan-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓       𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremnf3an 1564 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, 𝜓, and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓    &   𝑥𝜒       𝑥(𝜑𝜓𝜒)
 
Theoremnford 1565 If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜓𝜒). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Oct-2019.)
(𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremnfand 1566 If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, it is not free in (𝜓𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Oct-2016.)
(𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremnf3and 1567 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder nf3an 1564. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Oct-2016.)
(𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜃)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓𝜒𝜃))
 
Theoremhbim1 1568 A closed form of hbim 1543. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))       ((𝜑𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremnfim1 1569 A closed form of nfim 1570. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)       𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremnfim 1570 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓       𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremhbimd 1571 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbim 1543. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) (Revised by NM, 2-Feb-2015.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒))       (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremnfor 1572 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-Mar-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓       𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremhbbid 1573 Deduction form of bound-variable hypothesis builder hbbi 1546. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒))       (𝜑 → ((𝜓𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremnfal 1574 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in 𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) Remove dependency on ax-4 1508. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 25-Aug-2024.)
𝑥𝜑       𝑥𝑦𝜑
 
Theoremnfnf 1575 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑, it is not free in 𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.)
𝑥𝜑       𝑥𝑦𝜑
 
Theoremnfalt 1576 Closed form of nfal 1574. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 11-May-2018.)
(∀𝑦𝑥𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝑦𝜑)
 
Theoremnfa2 1577 Lemma 24 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥𝑦𝑥𝜑
 
Theoremnfia1 1578 Lemma 23 of [Monk2] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorem19.21ht 1579 Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) → (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)))
 
Theorem19.21t 1580 Closed form of Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 27-May-1997.)
(Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)))
 
Theorem19.21 1581 Theorem 19.21 of [Margaris] p. 90. The hypothesis can be thought of as "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥𝜑       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremstdpc5 1582 An axiom scheme of standard predicate calculus that emulates Axiom 5 of [Mendelson] p. 69. The hypothesis 𝑥𝜑 can be thought of as emulating "𝑥 is not free in 𝜑". With this definition, the meaning of "not free" is less restrictive than the usual textbook definition; for example 𝑥 would not (for us) be free in 𝑥 = 𝑥 by nfequid 1700. This theorem scheme can be proved as a metatheorem of Mendelson's axiom system, even though it is slightly stronger than his Axiom 5. (Contributed by NM, 22-Sep-1993.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 1-Jan-2018.)
𝑥𝜑       (∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremnfimd 1583 If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜓𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 30-Dec-2017.)
(𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremaaanh 1584 Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑)    &   (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝑦(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremaaan 1585 Rearrange universal quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1993.)
𝑦𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓       (∀𝑥𝑦(𝜑𝜓) ↔ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremnfbid 1586 If in a context 𝑥 is not free in 𝜓 and 𝜒, then it is not free in (𝜓𝜒). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 29-Dec-2017.)
(𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒)       (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremnfbi 1587 If 𝑥 is not free in 𝜑 and 𝜓, then it is not free in (𝜑𝜓). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 2-Jan-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑥𝜓       𝑥(𝜑𝜓)
 
1.3.7  The existential quantifier
 
Theorem19.8a 1588 If a wff is true, then it is true for at least one instance. Special case of Theorem 19.8 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑)
 
Theorem19.8ad 1589 If a wff is true, it is true for at least one instance. Deduction form of 19.8a 1588. (Contributed by DAW, 13-Feb-2017.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorem19.23bi 1590 Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(∃𝑥𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremexlimih 1591 Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.)
(𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)    &   (𝜑𝜓)       (∃𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremexlimi 1592 Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.)
𝑥𝜓    &   (𝜑𝜓)       (∃𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremexlimd2 1593 Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. Similar to exlimdh 1594 but with one slightly different hypothesis. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 30-Dec-2017.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremexlimdh 1594 Deduction from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 28-Jan-1997.)
(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑)    &   (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜒)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremexlimd 1595 Deduction from Theorem 19.9 of [Margaris] p. 89. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2016.) (Proof rewritten by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jun-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑥𝜒    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremexlimiv 1596* Inference from Theorem 19.23 of [Margaris] p. 90.

This inference, along with our many variants is used to implement a metatheorem called "Rule C" that is given in many logic textbooks. See, for example, Rule C in [Mendelson] p. 81, Rule C in [Margaris] p. 40, or Rule C in Hirst and Hirst's A Primer for Logic and Proof p. 59 (PDF p. 65) at http://www.mathsci.appstate.edu/~jlh/primer/hirst.pdf.

In informal proofs, the statement "Let C be an element such that..." almost always means an implicit application of Rule C.

In essence, Rule C states that if we can prove that some element 𝑥 exists satisfying a wff, i.e. 𝑥𝜑(𝑥) where 𝜑(𝑥) has 𝑥 free, then we can use 𝜑( C ) as a hypothesis for the proof where C is a new (ficticious) constant not appearing previously in the proof, nor in any axioms used, nor in the theorem to be proved. The purpose of Rule C is to get rid of the existential quantifier.

We cannot do this in Metamath directly. Instead, we use the original 𝜑 (containing 𝑥) as an antecedent for the main part of the proof. We eventually arrive at (𝜑𝜓) where 𝜓 is the theorem to be proved and does not contain 𝑥. Then we apply exlimiv 1596 to arrive at (∃𝑥𝜑𝜓). Finally, we separately prove 𝑥𝜑 and detach it with modus ponens ax-mp 5 to arrive at the final theorem 𝜓. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Revised by NM, 25-Jul-2012.)

(𝜑𝜓)       (∃𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremexim 1597 Theorem 19.22 of [Margaris] p. 90. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 4-Jul-2014.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝜓) → (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremeximi 1598 Inference adding existential quantifier to antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∃𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorem2eximi 1599 Inference adding 2 existential quantifiers to antecedent and consequent. (Contributed by NM, 3-Feb-2005.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∃𝑥𝑦𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝑦𝜓)
 
Theoremeximii 1600 Inference associated with eximi 1598. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Feb-2018.)
𝑥𝜑    &   (𝜑𝜓)       𝑥𝜓
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13300 134 13301-13400 135 13401-13500 136 13501-13600 137 13601-13700 138 13701-13800 139 13801-13900 140 13901-14000 141 14001-14100 142 14101-14200 143 14201-14300 144 14301-14399
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >