Home | Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 122 of 142) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | isprm6 12101* | A number is prime iff it satisfies Euclid's lemma euclemma 12100. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑃 ∈ ℙ ↔ (𝑃 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ℤ ∀𝑦 ∈ ℤ (𝑃 ∥ (𝑥 · 𝑦) → (𝑃 ∥ 𝑥 ∨ 𝑃 ∥ 𝑦)))) | ||
Theorem | prmdvdsexp 12102 | A prime divides a positive power of an integer iff it divides the integer. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Feb-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) → (𝑃 ∥ (𝐴↑𝑁) ↔ 𝑃 ∥ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | prmdvdsexpb 12103 | A prime divides a positive power of another iff they are equal. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 30-Nov-2012.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝑄 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) → (𝑃 ∥ (𝑄↑𝑁) ↔ 𝑃 = 𝑄)) | ||
Theorem | prmdvdsexpr 12104 | If a prime divides a nonnegative power of another, then they are equal. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝑄 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑃 ∥ (𝑄↑𝑁) → 𝑃 = 𝑄)) | ||
Theorem | prmexpb 12105 | Two positive prime powers are equal iff the primes and the powers are equal. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 30-Nov-2012.) |
⊢ (((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝑄 ∈ ℙ) ∧ (𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ)) → ((𝑃↑𝑀) = (𝑄↑𝑁) ↔ (𝑃 = 𝑄 ∧ 𝑀 = 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | prmfac1 12106 | The factorial of a number only contains primes less than the base. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Mar-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝑃 ∥ (!‘𝑁)) → 𝑃 ≤ 𝑁) | ||
Theorem | rpexp 12107 | If two numbers 𝐴 and 𝐵 are relatively prime, then they are still relatively prime if raised to a power. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) → (((𝐴↑𝑁) gcd 𝐵) = 1 ↔ (𝐴 gcd 𝐵) = 1)) | ||
Theorem | rpexp1i 12108 | Relative primality passes to asymmetric powers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 27-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℕ0) → ((𝐴 gcd 𝐵) = 1 → ((𝐴↑𝑀) gcd 𝐵) = 1)) | ||
Theorem | rpexp12i 12109 | Relative primality passes to symmetric powers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 27-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝑀 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0)) → ((𝐴 gcd 𝐵) = 1 → ((𝐴↑𝑀) gcd (𝐵↑𝑁)) = 1)) | ||
Theorem | prmndvdsfaclt 12110 | A prime number does not divide the factorial of a nonnegative integer less than the prime number. (Contributed by AV, 13-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑁 < 𝑃 → ¬ 𝑃 ∥ (!‘𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | cncongrprm 12111 | Corollary 2 of Cancellability of Congruences: Two products with a common factor are congruent modulo a prime number not dividing the common factor iff the other factors are congruent modulo the prime number. (Contributed by AV, 13-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ℤ) ∧ (𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ ¬ 𝑃 ∥ 𝐶)) → (((𝐴 · 𝐶) mod 𝑃) = ((𝐵 · 𝐶) mod 𝑃) ↔ (𝐴 mod 𝑃) = (𝐵 mod 𝑃))) | ||
Theorem | isevengcd2 12112 | The predicate "is an even number". An even number and 2 have 2 as greatest common divisor. (Contributed by AV, 1-Jul-2020.) (Revised by AV, 8-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ (𝑍 ∈ ℤ → (2 ∥ 𝑍 ↔ (2 gcd 𝑍) = 2)) | ||
Theorem | isoddgcd1 12113 | The predicate "is an odd number". An odd number and 2 have 1 as greatest common divisor. (Contributed by AV, 1-Jul-2020.) (Revised by AV, 8-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ (𝑍 ∈ ℤ → (¬ 2 ∥ 𝑍 ↔ (2 gcd 𝑍) = 1)) | ||
Theorem | 3lcm2e6 12114 | The least common multiple of three and two is six. The operands are unequal primes and thus coprime, so the result is (the absolute value of) their product. (Contributed by Steve Rodriguez, 20-Jan-2020.) (Proof shortened by AV, 27-Aug-2020.) |
⊢ (3 lcm 2) = 6 | ||
Theorem | sqrt2irrlem 12115 | Lemma for sqrt2irr 12116. This is the core of the proof: - if 𝐴 / 𝐵 = √(2), then 𝐴 and 𝐵 are even, so 𝐴 / 2 and 𝐵 / 2 are smaller representatives, which is absurd by the method of infinite descent (here implemented by strong induction). (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-2001.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℤ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (√‘2) = (𝐴 / 𝐵)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝐴 / 2) ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐵 / 2) ∈ ℕ)) | ||
Theorem | sqrt2irr 12116 |
The square root of 2 is not rational. That is, for any rational number,
(√‘2) does not equal it. However,
if we were to say "the
square root of 2 is irrational" that would mean something stronger:
"for any rational number, (√‘2)
is apart from it" (the two
statements are equivalent given excluded middle). See sqrt2irrap 12134 for
the proof that the square root of two is irrational.
The proof's core is proven in sqrt2irrlem 12115, which shows that if 𝐴 / 𝐵 = √(2), then 𝐴 and 𝐵 are even, so 𝐴 / 2 and 𝐵 / 2 are smaller representatives, which is absurd. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 12-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (√‘2) ∉ ℚ | ||
Theorem | sqrt2re 12117 | The square root of 2 exists and is a real number. (Contributed by NM, 3-Dec-2004.) |
⊢ (√‘2) ∈ ℝ | ||
Theorem | sqrt2irr0 12118 | The square root of 2 is not rational. (Contributed by AV, 23-Dec-2022.) |
⊢ (√‘2) ∈ (ℝ ∖ ℚ) | ||
Theorem | pw2dvdslemn 12119* | Lemma for pw2dvds 12120. If a natural number has some power of two which does not divide it, there is a highest power of two which does divide it. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℕ ∧ ¬ (2↑𝐴) ∥ 𝑁) → ∃𝑚 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑚) ∥ 𝑁 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑚 + 1)) ∥ 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | pw2dvds 12120* | A natural number has a highest power of two which divides it. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → ∃𝑚 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑚) ∥ 𝑁 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑚 + 1)) ∥ 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | pw2dvdseulemle 12121 | Lemma for pw2dvdseu 12122. Powers of two which do and do not divide a natural number. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℕ0) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℕ0) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (2↑𝐴) ∥ 𝑁) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ (2↑(𝐵 + 1)) ∥ 𝑁) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | pw2dvdseu 12122* | A natural number has a unique highest power of two which divides it. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → ∃!𝑚 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑚) ∥ 𝑁 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑚 + 1)) ∥ 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | oddpwdclemxy 12123* | Lemma for oddpwdc 12128. Another way of stating that decomposing a natural number into a power of two and an odd number is unique. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ ((((𝑋 ∈ ℕ ∧ ¬ 2 ∥ 𝑋) ∧ 𝑌 ∈ ℕ0) ∧ 𝐴 = ((2↑𝑌) · 𝑋)) → (𝑋 = (𝐴 / (2↑(℩𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑧) ∥ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑧 + 1)) ∥ 𝐴)))) ∧ 𝑌 = (℩𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑧) ∥ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑧 + 1)) ∥ 𝐴)))) | ||
Theorem | oddpwdclemdvds 12124* | Lemma for oddpwdc 12128. A natural number is divisible by the highest power of two which divides it. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ → (2↑(℩𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑧) ∥ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑧 + 1)) ∥ 𝐴))) ∥ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | oddpwdclemndvds 12125* | Lemma for oddpwdc 12128. A natural number is not divisible by one more than the highest power of two which divides it. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ → ¬ (2↑((℩𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑧) ∥ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑧 + 1)) ∥ 𝐴)) + 1)) ∥ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | oddpwdclemodd 12126* | Lemma for oddpwdc 12128. Removing the powers of two from a natural number produces an odd number. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ → ¬ 2 ∥ (𝐴 / (2↑(℩𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑧) ∥ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑧 + 1)) ∥ 𝐴))))) | ||
Theorem | oddpwdclemdc 12127* | Lemma for oddpwdc 12128. Decomposing a number into odd and even parts. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ ((((𝑋 ∈ ℕ ∧ ¬ 2 ∥ 𝑋) ∧ 𝑌 ∈ ℕ0) ∧ 𝐴 = ((2↑𝑌) · 𝑋)) ↔ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ ∧ (𝑋 = (𝐴 / (2↑(℩𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑧) ∥ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑧 + 1)) ∥ 𝐴)))) ∧ 𝑌 = (℩𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ((2↑𝑧) ∥ 𝐴 ∧ ¬ (2↑(𝑧 + 1)) ∥ 𝐴))))) | ||
Theorem | oddpwdc 12128* | The function 𝐹 that decomposes a number into its "odd" and "even" parts, which is to say the largest power of two and largest odd divisor of a number, is a bijection from pairs of a nonnegative integer and an odd number to positive integers. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 15-Aug-2017.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = {𝑧 ∈ ℕ ∣ ¬ 2 ∥ 𝑧} & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐽, 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((2↑𝑦) · 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:(𝐽 × ℕ0)–1-1-onto→ℕ | ||
Theorem | sqpweven 12129* | The greatest power of two dividing the square of an integer is an even power of two. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = {𝑧 ∈ ℕ ∣ ¬ 2 ∥ 𝑧} & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐽, 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((2↑𝑦) · 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ → 2 ∥ (2nd ‘(◡𝐹‘(𝐴↑2)))) | ||
Theorem | 2sqpwodd 12130* | The greatest power of two dividing twice the square of an integer is an odd power of two. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = {𝑧 ∈ ℕ ∣ ¬ 2 ∥ 𝑧} & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐽, 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((2↑𝑦) · 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ → ¬ 2 ∥ (2nd ‘(◡𝐹‘(2 · (𝐴↑2))))) | ||
Theorem | sqne2sq 12131 | The square of a natural number can never be equal to two times the square of a natural number. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → (𝐴↑2) ≠ (2 · (𝐵↑2))) | ||
Theorem | znege1 12132 | The absolute value of the difference between two unequal integers is at least one. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jan-2022.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) → 1 ≤ (abs‘(𝐴 − 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | sqrt2irraplemnn 12133 | Lemma for sqrt2irrap 12134. The square root of 2 is apart from a positive rational expressed as a numerator and denominator. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → (√‘2) # (𝐴 / 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | sqrt2irrap 12134 | The square root of 2 is irrational. That is, for any rational number, (√‘2) is apart from it. In the absence of excluded middle, we can distinguish between this and "the square root of 2 is not rational" which is sqrt2irr 12116. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 2-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝑄 ∈ ℚ → (√‘2) # 𝑄) | ||
Syntax | cnumer 12135 | Extend class notation to include canonical numerator function. |
class numer | ||
Syntax | cdenom 12136 | Extend class notation to include canonical denominator function. |
class denom | ||
Definition | df-numer 12137* | The canonical numerator of a rational is the numerator of the rational's reduced fraction representation (no common factors, denominator positive). (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ numer = (𝑦 ∈ ℚ ↦ (1st ‘(℩𝑥 ∈ (ℤ × ℕ)(((1st ‘𝑥) gcd (2nd ‘𝑥)) = 1 ∧ 𝑦 = ((1st ‘𝑥) / (2nd ‘𝑥)))))) | ||
Definition | df-denom 12138* | The canonical denominator of a rational is the denominator of the rational's reduced fraction representation (no common factors, denominator positive). (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ denom = (𝑦 ∈ ℚ ↦ (2nd ‘(℩𝑥 ∈ (ℤ × ℕ)(((1st ‘𝑥) gcd (2nd ‘𝑥)) = 1 ∧ 𝑦 = ((1st ‘𝑥) / (2nd ‘𝑥)))))) | ||
Theorem | qnumval 12139* | Value of the canonical numerator function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (numer‘𝐴) = (1st ‘(℩𝑥 ∈ (ℤ × ℕ)(((1st ‘𝑥) gcd (2nd ‘𝑥)) = 1 ∧ 𝐴 = ((1st ‘𝑥) / (2nd ‘𝑥)))))) | ||
Theorem | qdenval 12140* | Value of the canonical denominator function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (denom‘𝐴) = (2nd ‘(℩𝑥 ∈ (ℤ × ℕ)(((1st ‘𝑥) gcd (2nd ‘𝑥)) = 1 ∧ 𝐴 = ((1st ‘𝑥) / (2nd ‘𝑥)))))) | ||
Theorem | qnumdencl 12141 | Lemma for qnumcl 12142 and qdencl 12143. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → ((numer‘𝐴) ∈ ℤ ∧ (denom‘𝐴) ∈ ℕ)) | ||
Theorem | qnumcl 12142 | The canonical numerator of a rational is an integer. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (numer‘𝐴) ∈ ℤ) | ||
Theorem | qdencl 12143 | The canonical denominator is a positive integer. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (denom‘𝐴) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | fnum 12144 | Canonical numerator defines a function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ numer:ℚ⟶ℤ | ||
Theorem | fden 12145 | Canonical denominator defines a function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ denom:ℚ⟶ℕ | ||
Theorem | qnumdenbi 12146 | Two numbers are the canonical representation of a rational iff they are coprime and have the right quotient. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℚ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ℕ) → (((𝐵 gcd 𝐶) = 1 ∧ 𝐴 = (𝐵 / 𝐶)) ↔ ((numer‘𝐴) = 𝐵 ∧ (denom‘𝐴) = 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | qnumdencoprm 12147 | The canonical representation of a rational is fully reduced. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → ((numer‘𝐴) gcd (denom‘𝐴)) = 1) | ||
Theorem | qeqnumdivden 12148 | Recover a rational number from its canonical representation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → 𝐴 = ((numer‘𝐴) / (denom‘𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | qmuldeneqnum 12149 | Multiplying a rational by its denominator results in an integer. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (𝐴 · (denom‘𝐴)) = (numer‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | divnumden 12150 | Calculate the reduced form of a quotient using gcd. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → ((numer‘(𝐴 / 𝐵)) = (𝐴 / (𝐴 gcd 𝐵)) ∧ (denom‘(𝐴 / 𝐵)) = (𝐵 / (𝐴 gcd 𝐵)))) | ||
Theorem | divdenle 12151 | Reducing a quotient never increases the denominator. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → (denom‘(𝐴 / 𝐵)) ≤ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | qnumgt0 12152 | A rational is positive iff its canonical numerator is. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (0 < 𝐴 ↔ 0 < (numer‘𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | qgt0numnn 12153 | A rational is positive iff its canonical numerator is a positive integer. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℚ ∧ 0 < 𝐴) → (numer‘𝐴) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | nn0gcdsq 12154 | Squaring commutes with GCD, in particular two coprime numbers have coprime squares. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ0) → ((𝐴 gcd 𝐵)↑2) = ((𝐴↑2) gcd (𝐵↑2))) | ||
Theorem | zgcdsq 12155 | nn0gcdsq 12154 extended to integers by symmetry. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ) → ((𝐴 gcd 𝐵)↑2) = ((𝐴↑2) gcd (𝐵↑2))) | ||
Theorem | numdensq 12156 | Squaring a rational squares its canonical components. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → ((numer‘(𝐴↑2)) = ((numer‘𝐴)↑2) ∧ (denom‘(𝐴↑2)) = ((denom‘𝐴)↑2))) | ||
Theorem | numsq 12157 | Square commutes with canonical numerator. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (numer‘(𝐴↑2)) = ((numer‘𝐴)↑2)) | ||
Theorem | densq 12158 | Square commutes with canonical denominator. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → (denom‘(𝐴↑2)) = ((denom‘𝐴)↑2)) | ||
Theorem | qden1elz 12159 | A rational is an integer iff it has denominator 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℚ → ((denom‘𝐴) = 1 ↔ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ)) | ||
Theorem | nn0sqrtelqelz 12160 | If a nonnegative integer has a rational square root, that root must be an integer. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-May-2022.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (√‘𝐴) ∈ ℚ) → (√‘𝐴) ∈ ℤ) | ||
Theorem | nonsq 12161 | Any integer strictly between two adjacent squares has a non-rational square root. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ0) ∧ ((𝐵↑2) < 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 < ((𝐵 + 1)↑2))) → ¬ (√‘𝐴) ∈ ℚ) | ||
Syntax | codz 12162 | Extend class notation with the order function on the class of integers modulo N. |
class odℤ | ||
Syntax | cphi 12163 | Extend class notation with the Euler phi function. |
class ϕ | ||
Definition | df-odz 12164* | Define the order function on the class of integers modulo N. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) (Revised by AV, 26-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ odℤ = (𝑛 ∈ ℕ ↦ (𝑥 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ ℤ ∣ (𝑥 gcd 𝑛) = 1} ↦ inf({𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∣ 𝑛 ∥ ((𝑥↑𝑚) − 1)}, ℝ, < ))) | ||
Definition | df-phi 12165* | Define the Euler phi function (also called "Euler totient function"), which counts the number of integers less than 𝑛 and coprime to it, see definition in [ApostolNT] p. 25. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ϕ = (𝑛 ∈ ℕ ↦ (♯‘{𝑥 ∈ (1...𝑛) ∣ (𝑥 gcd 𝑛) = 1})) | ||
Theorem | phivalfi 12166* | Finiteness of an expression used to define the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Jim Kingon, 28-May-2022.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → {𝑥 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∣ (𝑥 gcd 𝑁) = 1} ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | phival 12167* | Value of the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → (ϕ‘𝑁) = (♯‘{𝑥 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∣ (𝑥 gcd 𝑁) = 1})) | ||
Theorem | phicl2 12168 | Bounds and closure for the value of the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → (ϕ‘𝑁) ∈ (1...𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | phicl 12169 | Closure for the value of the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → (ϕ‘𝑁) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | phibndlem 12170* | Lemma for phibnd 12171. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → {𝑥 ∈ (1...𝑁) ∣ (𝑥 gcd 𝑁) = 1} ⊆ (1...(𝑁 − 1))) | ||
Theorem | phibnd 12171 | A slightly tighter bound on the value of the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (ϕ‘𝑁) ≤ (𝑁 − 1)) | ||
Theorem | phicld 12172 | Closure for the value of the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-May-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (ϕ‘𝑁) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | phi1 12173 | Value of the Euler ϕ function at 1. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ (ϕ‘1) = 1 | ||
Theorem | dfphi2 12174* | Alternate definition of the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-May-2016.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → (ϕ‘𝑁) = (♯‘{𝑥 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑥 gcd 𝑁) = 1})) | ||
Theorem | hashdvds 12175* | The number of numbers in a given residue class in a finite set of integers. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Mar-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 7-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℤ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ (ℤ≥‘(𝐴 − 1))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℤ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (♯‘{𝑥 ∈ (𝐴...𝐵) ∣ 𝑁 ∥ (𝑥 − 𝐶)}) = ((⌊‘((𝐵 − 𝐶) / 𝑁)) − (⌊‘(((𝐴 − 1) − 𝐶) / 𝑁)))) | ||
Theorem | phiprmpw 12176 | Value of the Euler ϕ function at a prime power. Theorem 2.5(a) in [ApostolNT] p. 28. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝐾 ∈ ℕ) → (ϕ‘(𝑃↑𝐾)) = ((𝑃↑(𝐾 − 1)) · (𝑃 − 1))) | ||
Theorem | phiprm 12177 | Value of the Euler ϕ function at a prime. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑃 ∈ ℙ → (ϕ‘𝑃) = (𝑃 − 1)) | ||
Theorem | crth 12178* | The Chinese Remainder Theorem: the function that maps 𝑥 to its remainder classes mod 𝑀 and mod 𝑁 is 1-1 and onto when 𝑀 and 𝑁 are coprime. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Feb-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-May-2016.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = (0..^(𝑀 · 𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑇 = ((0..^𝑀) × (0..^𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ 〈(𝑥 mod 𝑀), (𝑥 mod 𝑁)〉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ (𝑀 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝑆–1-1-onto→𝑇) | ||
Theorem | phimullem 12179* | Lemma for phimul 12180. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = (0..^(𝑀 · 𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝑇 = ((0..^𝑀) × (0..^𝑁)) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ 〈(𝑥 mod 𝑀), (𝑥 mod 𝑁)〉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ (𝑀 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) & ⊢ 𝑈 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑀) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑀) = 1} & ⊢ 𝑉 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑁) = 1} & ⊢ 𝑊 = {𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∣ (𝑦 gcd (𝑀 · 𝑁)) = 1} ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (ϕ‘(𝑀 · 𝑁)) = ((ϕ‘𝑀) · (ϕ‘𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | phimul 12180 | The Euler ϕ function is a multiplicative function, meaning that it distributes over multiplication at relatively prime arguments. Theorem 2.5(c) in [ApostolNT] p. 28. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ (𝑀 gcd 𝑁) = 1) → (ϕ‘(𝑀 · 𝑁)) = ((ϕ‘𝑀) · (ϕ‘𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | eulerthlem1 12181* | Lemma for eulerth 12187. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑁) = 1} & ⊢ 𝑇 = (1...(ϕ‘𝑁)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝑇–1-1-onto→𝑆) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝑇 ↦ ((𝐴 · (𝐹‘𝑥)) mod 𝑁)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺:𝑇⟶𝑆) | ||
Theorem | eulerthlemfi 12182* | Lemma for eulerth 12187. The set 𝑆 is finite. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 7-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑁) = 1} ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | eulerthlemrprm 12183* | Lemma for eulerth 12187. 𝑁 and ∏𝑥 ∈ (1...(ϕ‘𝑁))(𝐹‘𝑥) are relatively prime. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 2-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑁) = 1} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(1...(ϕ‘𝑁))–1-1-onto→𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁 gcd ∏𝑥 ∈ (1...(ϕ‘𝑁))(𝐹‘𝑥)) = 1) | ||
Theorem | eulerthlema 12184* | Lemma for eulerth 12187. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 2-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑁) = 1} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(1...(ϕ‘𝑁))–1-1-onto→𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (((𝐴↑(ϕ‘𝑁)) · ∏𝑥 ∈ (1...(ϕ‘𝑁))(𝐹‘𝑥)) mod 𝑁) = (∏𝑥 ∈ (1...(ϕ‘𝑁))((𝐴 · (𝐹‘𝑥)) mod 𝑁) mod 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | eulerthlemh 12185* | Lemma for eulerth 12187. A permutation of (1...(ϕ‘𝑁)). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 5-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑁) = 1} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(1...(ϕ‘𝑁))–1-1-onto→𝑆) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (◡𝐹 ∘ (𝑦 ∈ (1...(ϕ‘𝑁)) ↦ ((𝐴 · (𝐹‘𝑦)) mod 𝑁))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐻:(1...(ϕ‘𝑁))–1-1-onto→(1...(ϕ‘𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | eulerthlemth 12186* | Lemma for eulerth 12187. The result. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 2-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^𝑁) ∣ (𝑦 gcd 𝑁) = 1} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:(1...(ϕ‘𝑁))–1-1-onto→𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝐴↑(ϕ‘𝑁)) mod 𝑁) = (1 mod 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | eulerth 12187 | Euler's theorem, a generalization of Fermat's little theorem. If 𝐴 and 𝑁 are coprime, then 𝐴↑ϕ(𝑁)≡1 (mod 𝑁). This is Metamath 100 proof #10. Also called Euler-Fermat theorem, see theorem 5.17 in [ApostolNT] p. 113. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1) → ((𝐴↑(ϕ‘𝑁)) mod 𝑁) = (1 mod 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | fermltl 12188 | Fermat's little theorem. When 𝑃 is prime, 𝐴↑𝑃≡𝐴 (mod 𝑃) for any 𝐴, see theorem 5.19 in [ApostolNT] p. 114. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 19-Mar-2022.) |
⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ) → ((𝐴↑𝑃) mod 𝑃) = (𝐴 mod 𝑃)) | ||
Theorem | prmdiv 12189 | Show an explicit expression for the modular inverse of 𝐴 mod 𝑃. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑅 = ((𝐴↑(𝑃 − 2)) mod 𝑃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ ¬ 𝑃 ∥ 𝐴) → (𝑅 ∈ (1...(𝑃 − 1)) ∧ 𝑃 ∥ ((𝐴 · 𝑅) − 1))) | ||
Theorem | prmdiveq 12190 | The modular inverse of 𝐴 mod 𝑃 is unique. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑅 = ((𝐴↑(𝑃 − 2)) mod 𝑃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ ¬ 𝑃 ∥ 𝐴) → ((𝑆 ∈ (0...(𝑃 − 1)) ∧ 𝑃 ∥ ((𝐴 · 𝑆) − 1)) ↔ 𝑆 = 𝑅)) | ||
Theorem | prmdivdiv 12191 | The (modular) inverse of the inverse of a number is itself. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑅 = ((𝐴↑(𝑃 − 2)) mod 𝑃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑃 ∈ ℙ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (1...(𝑃 − 1))) → 𝐴 = ((𝑅↑(𝑃 − 2)) mod 𝑃)) | ||
Theorem | hashgcdlem 12192* | A correspondence between elements of specific GCD and relative primes in a smaller ring. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 12-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑦 ∈ (0..^(𝑀 / 𝑁)) ∣ (𝑦 gcd (𝑀 / 𝑁)) = 1} & ⊢ 𝐵 = {𝑧 ∈ (0..^𝑀) ∣ (𝑧 gcd 𝑀) = 𝑁} & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝑥 · 𝑁)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∥ 𝑀) → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | hashgcdeq 12193* | Number of initial positive integers with specified divisors. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 12-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) → (♯‘{𝑥 ∈ (0..^𝑀) ∣ (𝑥 gcd 𝑀) = 𝑁}) = if(𝑁 ∥ 𝑀, (ϕ‘(𝑀 / 𝑁)), 0)) | ||
Theorem | phisum 12194* | The divisor sum identity of the totient function. Theorem 2.2 in [ApostolNT] p. 26. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 12-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ → Σ𝑑 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ ℕ ∣ 𝑥 ∥ 𝑁} (ϕ‘𝑑) = 𝑁) | ||
Theorem | odzval 12195* | Value of the order function. This is a function of functions; the inner argument selects the base (i.e., mod 𝑁 for some 𝑁, often prime) and the outer argument selects the integer or equivalence class (if you want to think about it that way) from the integers mod 𝑁. In order to ensure the supremum is well-defined, we only define the expression when 𝐴 and 𝑁 are coprime. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.) (Revised by AV, 26-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1) → ((odℤ‘𝑁)‘𝐴) = inf({𝑛 ∈ ℕ ∣ 𝑁 ∥ ((𝐴↑𝑛) − 1)}, ℝ, < )) | ||
Theorem | odzcllem 12196 | - Lemma for odzcl 12197, showing existence of a recurrent point for the exponential. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 26-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1) → (((odℤ‘𝑁)‘𝐴) ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∥ ((𝐴↑((odℤ‘𝑁)‘𝐴)) − 1))) | ||
Theorem | odzcl 12197 | The order of a group element is an integer. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1) → ((odℤ‘𝑁)‘𝐴) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | odzid 12198 | Any element raised to the power of its order is 1. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1) → 𝑁 ∥ ((𝐴↑((odℤ‘𝑁)‘𝐴)) − 1)) | ||
Theorem | odzdvds 12199 | The only powers of 𝐴 that are congruent to 1 are the multiples of the order of 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 26-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1) ∧ 𝐾 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑁 ∥ ((𝐴↑𝐾) − 1) ↔ ((odℤ‘𝑁)‘𝐴) ∥ 𝐾)) | ||
Theorem | odzphi 12200 | The order of any group element is a divisor of the Euler ϕ function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Feb-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐴 gcd 𝑁) = 1) → ((odℤ‘𝑁)‘𝐴) ∥ (ϕ‘𝑁)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |