Type | Label | Description |
Statement |
|
Theorem | ecelqsg 6601 |
Membership of an equivalence class in a quotient set. (Contributed by
Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝑅 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → [𝐵]𝑅 ∈ (𝐴 / 𝑅)) |
|
Theorem | ecelqsi 6602 |
Membership of an equivalence class in a quotient set. (Contributed by
NM, 25-Jul-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝑅 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → [𝐵]𝑅 ∈ (𝐴 / 𝑅)) |
|
Theorem | ecopqsi 6603 |
"Closure" law for equivalence class of ordered pairs. (Contributed
by
NM, 25-Mar-1996.)
|
⊢ 𝑅 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 = ((𝐴 × 𝐴) / 𝑅) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴) → [⟨𝐵, 𝐶⟩]𝑅 ∈ 𝑆) |
|
Theorem | qsexg 6604 |
A quotient set exists. (Contributed by FL, 19-May-2007.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 / 𝑅) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | qsex 6605 |
A quotient set exists. (Contributed by NM, 14-Aug-1995.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 / 𝑅) ∈ V |
|
Theorem | uniqs 6606 |
The union of a quotient set. (Contributed by NM, 9-Dec-2008.)
|
⊢ (𝑅 ∈ 𝑉 → ∪ (𝐴 / 𝑅) = (𝑅 “ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | qsss 6607 |
A quotient set is a set of subsets of the base set. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
12-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 / 𝑅) ⊆ 𝒫 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | uniqs2 6608 |
The union of a quotient set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
11-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝐴)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∪ (𝐴 / 𝑅) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | snec 6609 |
The singleton of an equivalence class. (Contributed by NM,
29-Jan-1999.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ {[𝐴]𝑅} = ({𝐴} / 𝑅) |
|
Theorem | ecqs 6610 |
Equivalence class in terms of quotient set. (Contributed by NM,
29-Jan-1999.)
|
⊢ 𝑅 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ [𝐴]𝑅 = ∪ ({𝐴} / 𝑅) |
|
Theorem | ecid 6611 |
A set is equal to its converse epsilon coset. (Note: converse epsilon
is not an equivalence relation.) (Contributed by NM, 13-Aug-1995.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ [𝐴]◡
E = 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | ecidg 6612 |
A set is equal to its converse epsilon coset. (Note: converse epsilon
is not an equivalence relation.) (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
8-Jan-2020.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → [𝐴]◡
E = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | qsid 6613 |
A set is equal to its quotient set mod converse epsilon. (Note:
converse epsilon is not an equivalence relation.) (Contributed by NM,
13-Aug-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 / ◡ E ) = 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | ectocld 6614* |
Implicit substitution of class for equivalence class. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝑆 = (𝐵 / 𝑅)
& ⊢ ([𝑥]𝑅 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ ((𝜒 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜒 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑆) → 𝜓) |
|
Theorem | ectocl 6615* |
Implicit substitution of class for equivalence class. (Contributed by
NM, 23-Jul-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝑆 = (𝐵 / 𝑅)
& ⊢ ([𝑥]𝑅 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 → 𝜓) |
|
Theorem | elqsn0m 6616* |
An element of a quotient set is inhabited. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
21-Aug-2019.)
|
⊢ ((dom 𝑅 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝐴 / 𝑅)) → ∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | elqsn0 6617 |
A quotient set doesn't contain the empty set. (Contributed by NM,
24-Aug-1995.)
|
⊢ ((dom 𝑅 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝐴 / 𝑅)) → 𝐵 ≠ ∅) |
|
Theorem | ecelqsdm 6618 |
Membership of an equivalence class in a quotient set. (Contributed by
NM, 30-Jul-1995.)
|
⊢ ((dom 𝑅 = 𝐴 ∧ [𝐵]𝑅 ∈ (𝐴 / 𝑅)) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | xpider 6619 |
A square Cartesian product is an equivalence relation (in general it's not
a poset). (Contributed by FL, 31-Jul-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
12-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 × 𝐴) Er 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | iinerm 6620* |
The intersection of a nonempty family of equivalence relations is an
equivalence relation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ ((∃𝑦 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑅 Er 𝐵) → ∩ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑅 Er 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | riinerm 6621* |
The relative intersection of a family of equivalence relations is an
equivalence relation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ ((∃𝑦 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑅 Er 𝐵) → ((𝐵 × 𝐵) ∩ ∩
𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑅) Er 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | erinxp 6622 |
A restricted equivalence relation is an equivalence relation.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jul-2015.) (Revised by Mario
Carneiro, 12-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝐴)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 ∩ (𝐵 × 𝐵)) Er 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | ecinxp 6623 |
Restrict the relation in an equivalence class to a base set. (Contributed
by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jul-2015.)
|
⊢ (((𝑅 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → [𝐵]𝑅 = [𝐵](𝑅 ∩ (𝐴 × 𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | qsinxp 6624 |
Restrict the equivalence relation in a quotient set to the base set.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝑅 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴 → (𝐴 / 𝑅) = (𝐴 / (𝑅 ∩ (𝐴 × 𝐴)))) |
|
Theorem | qsel 6625 |
If an element of a quotient set contains a given element, it is equal to
the equivalence class of the element. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
12-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝑅 Er 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝐴 / 𝑅) ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐵 = [𝐶]𝑅) |
|
Theorem | qliftlem 6626* |
𝐹,
a function lift, is a subset of 𝑅 × 𝑆. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → [𝑥]𝑅 ∈ (𝑋 / 𝑅)) |
|
Theorem | qliftrel 6627* |
𝐹,
a function lift, is a subset of 𝑅 × 𝑆. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ⊆ ((𝑋 / 𝑅) × 𝑌)) |
|
Theorem | qliftel 6628* |
Elementhood in the relation 𝐹. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ([𝐶]𝑅𝐹𝐷 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 (𝐶𝑅𝑥 ∧ 𝐷 = 𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | qliftel1 6629* |
Elementhood in the relation 𝐹. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → [𝑥]𝑅𝐹𝐴) |
|
Theorem | qliftfun 6630* |
The function 𝐹 is the unique function defined by
𝐹‘[𝑥] = 𝐴, provided that the well-definedness
condition
holds. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Fun 𝐹 ↔ ∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝑥𝑅𝑦 → 𝐴 = 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | qliftfund 6631* |
The function 𝐹 is the unique function defined by
𝐹‘[𝑥] = 𝐴, provided that the well-definedness
condition
holds. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐴 = 𝐵)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥𝑅𝑦) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | qliftfuns 6632* |
The function 𝐹 is the unique function defined by
𝐹‘[𝑥] = 𝐴, provided that the well-definedness
condition holds.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Fun 𝐹 ↔ ∀𝑦∀𝑧(𝑦𝑅𝑧 → ⦋𝑦 / 𝑥⦌𝐴 = ⦋𝑧 / 𝑥⦌𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | qliftf 6633* |
The domain and codomain of the function 𝐹. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Fun 𝐹 ↔ 𝐹:(𝑋 / 𝑅)⟶𝑌)) |
|
Theorem | qliftval 6634* |
The value of the function 𝐹. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
23-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ ⟨[𝑥]𝑅, 𝐴⟩) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐶 → 𝐴 = 𝐵)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐹‘[𝐶]𝑅) = 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | ecoptocl 6635* |
Implicit substitution of class for equivalence class of ordered pair.
(Contributed by NM, 23-Jul-1995.)
|
⊢ 𝑆 = ((𝐵 × 𝐶) / 𝑅)
& ⊢ ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩]𝑅 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 → 𝜓) |
|
Theorem | 2ecoptocl 6636* |
Implicit substitution of classes for equivalence classes of ordered
pairs. (Contributed by NM, 23-Jul-1995.)
|
⊢ 𝑆 = ((𝐶 × 𝐷) / 𝑅)
& ⊢ ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩]𝑅 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩]𝑅 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐷) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝐷)) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) → 𝜒) |
|
Theorem | 3ecoptocl 6637* |
Implicit substitution of classes for equivalence classes of ordered
pairs. (Contributed by NM, 9-Aug-1995.)
|
⊢ 𝑆 = ((𝐷 × 𝐷) / 𝑅)
& ⊢ ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩]𝑅 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩]𝑅 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ ([⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩]𝑅 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐷) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝐷) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐷)) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑆) → 𝜃) |
|
Theorem | brecop 6638* |
Binary relation on a quotient set. Lemma for real number construction.
(Contributed by NM, 29-Jan-1996.)
|
⊢ ∼ ∈
V
& ⊢ ∼ Er (𝐺 × 𝐺)
& ⊢ 𝐻 = ((𝐺 × 𝐺) / ∼ ) & ⊢ ≤ =
{⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐻 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐻) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) ∧ 𝜑))} & ⊢ ((((𝑧 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝐺) ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐺)) ∧ ((𝑣 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐺) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐺))) → (([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ = [⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ ∧ [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ = [⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐺) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐺)) → ([⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ ≤ [⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ↔ 𝜓)) |
|
Theorem | eroveu 6639* |
Lemma for eroprf 6641. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / 𝑅)
& ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐵 / 𝑆)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑍)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑈)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Er 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Er 𝑊)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑊)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐶)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐵))) → ((𝑟𝑅𝑠 ∧ 𝑡𝑆𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡)𝑇(𝑠 + 𝑢))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐽 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐾)) → ∃!𝑧∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑋 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑌 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)) |
|
Theorem | erovlem 6640* |
Lemma for eroprf 6641. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Dec-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / 𝑅)
& ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐵 / 𝑆)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑍)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑈)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Er 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Er 𝑊)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑊)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐶)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐵))) → ((𝑟𝑅𝑠 ∧ 𝑡𝑆𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡)𝑇(𝑠 + 𝑢))) & ⊢ ⨣ =
{⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑥 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ⨣ = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐽, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐾 ↦ (℩𝑧∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑥 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)))) |
|
Theorem | eroprf 6641* |
Functionality of an operation defined on equivalence classes.
(Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
30-Dec-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / 𝑅)
& ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐵 / 𝑆)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑍)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑈)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Er 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Er 𝑊)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑊)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐶)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐵))) → ((𝑟𝑅𝑠 ∧ 𝑡𝑆𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡)𝑇(𝑠 + 𝑢))) & ⊢ ⨣ =
{⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑥 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ 𝑋)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑌)
& ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝐶 / 𝑇) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ⨣ :(𝐽 × 𝐾)⟶𝐿) |
|
Theorem | eroprf2 6642* |
Functionality of an operation defined on equivalence classes.
(Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.)
|
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / ∼ ) & ⊢ ⨣ =
{⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝑥 = [𝑝] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)] ∼ )} & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∼ ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∼ Er 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐴)⟶𝐴)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐴))) → ((𝑟 ∼ 𝑠 ∧ 𝑡 ∼ 𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡) ∼ (𝑠 + 𝑢))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ⨣ :(𝐽 × 𝐽)⟶𝐽) |
|
Theorem | ecopoveq 6643* |
This is the first of several theorems about equivalence relations of
the kind used in construction of fractions and signed reals, involving
operations on equivalent classes of ordered pairs. This theorem
expresses the relation ∼ (specified
by the hypothesis) in terms
of its operation 𝐹. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-1995.)
|
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∼ ⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩ ↔ (𝐴 + 𝐷) = (𝐵 + 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | ecopovsym 6644* |
Assuming the operation 𝐹 is commutative, show that the
relation
∼, specified
by the first hypothesis, is symmetric.
(Contributed by NM, 27-Aug-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∼ 𝐵 → 𝐵 ∼ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | ecopovtrn 6645* |
Assuming that operation 𝐹 is commutative (second hypothesis),
closed (third hypothesis), associative (fourth hypothesis), and has
the cancellation property (fifth hypothesis), show that the relation
∼, specified
by the first hypothesis, is transitive.
(Contributed by NM, 11-Feb-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 + 𝑦) + 𝑧) = (𝑥 + (𝑦 + 𝑧))
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑥 + 𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∼ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∼ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | ecopover 6646* |
Assuming that operation 𝐹 is commutative (second hypothesis),
closed (third hypothesis), associative (fourth hypothesis), and has
the cancellation property (fifth hypothesis), show that the relation
∼, specified
by the first hypothesis, is an equivalence
relation. (Contributed by NM, 16-Feb-1996.) (Revised by Mario
Carneiro, 12-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 + 𝑦) + 𝑧) = (𝑥 + (𝑦 + 𝑧))
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑥 + 𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆) |
|
Theorem | ecopovsymg 6647* |
Assuming the operation 𝐹 is commutative, show that the
relation
∼, specified
by the first hypothesis, is symmetric.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Sep-2019.)
|
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∼ 𝐵 → 𝐵 ∼ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | ecopovtrng 6648* |
Assuming that operation 𝐹 is commutative (second hypothesis),
closed (third hypothesis), associative (fourth hypothesis), and has
the cancellation property (fifth hypothesis), show that the relation
∼, specified
by the first hypothesis, is transitive.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Sep-2019.)
|
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥))
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) + 𝑧) = (𝑥 + (𝑦 + 𝑧))) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑥 + 𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∼ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∼ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | ecopoverg 6649* |
Assuming that operation 𝐹 is commutative (second hypothesis),
closed (third hypothesis), associative (fourth hypothesis), and has
the cancellation property (fifth hypothesis), show that the relation
∼, specified
by the first hypothesis, is an equivalence
relation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Sep-2019.)
|
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥))
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) + 𝑧) = (𝑥 + (𝑦 + 𝑧))) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑥 + 𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆) |
|
Theorem | th3qlem1 6650* |
Lemma for Exercise 44 version of Theorem 3Q of [Enderton] p. 60. The
third hypothesis is the compatibility assumption. (Contributed by NM,
3-Aug-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.)
|
⊢ ∼ Er 𝑆 & ⊢ (((𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑆)) → ((𝑦 ∼ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑧 ∼ 𝑣) → (𝑦 + 𝑧) ∼ (𝑤 + 𝑣))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝑆 / ∼ ) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝑆 / ∼ )) →
∃*𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧((𝐴 = [𝑦] ∼ ∧ 𝐵 = [𝑧] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑥 = [(𝑦 + 𝑧)] ∼
)) |
|
Theorem | th3qlem2 6651* |
Lemma for Exercise 44 version of Theorem 3Q of [Enderton] p. 60,
extended to operations on ordered pairs. The fourth hypothesis is the
compatibility assumption. (Contributed by NM, 4-Aug-1995.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ ∼ ∈
V
& ⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆)
& ⊢ ((((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑆)) ∧ ((𝑠 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑓 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑔 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ ℎ ∈ 𝑆))) → ((⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ ∼ ⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩ ∧ ⟨𝑠, 𝑓⟩ ∼ ⟨𝑔, ℎ⟩) → (⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ + ⟨𝑠, 𝑓⟩) ∼ (⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩ + ⟨𝑔, ℎ⟩))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ )) →
∃*𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢∃𝑡((𝐴 = [⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩] ∼ ∧ 𝐵 = [⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑧 = [(⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ + ⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩)] ∼
)) |
|
Theorem | th3qcor 6652* |
Corollary of Theorem 3Q of [Enderton] p. 60.
(Contributed by NM,
12-Nov-1995.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.)
|
⊢ ∼ ∈
V
& ⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆)
& ⊢ ((((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑆)) ∧ ((𝑠 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑓 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑔 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ ℎ ∈ 𝑆))) → ((⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ ∼ ⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩ ∧ ⟨𝑠, 𝑓⟩ ∼ ⟨𝑔, ℎ⟩) → (⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ + ⟨𝑠, 𝑓⟩) ∼ (⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩ + ⟨𝑔, ℎ⟩))) & ⊢ 𝐺 = {⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ )) ∧
∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢∃𝑡((𝑥 = [⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑧 = [(⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ + ⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩)] ∼
))} ⇒ ⊢ Fun 𝐺 |
|
Theorem | th3q 6653* |
Theorem 3Q of [Enderton] p. 60, extended to
operations on ordered
pairs. (Contributed by NM, 4-Aug-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
19-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ ∼ ∈
V
& ⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆)
& ⊢ ((((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑆)) ∧ ((𝑠 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑓 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑔 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ ℎ ∈ 𝑆))) → ((⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ ∼ ⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩ ∧ ⟨𝑠, 𝑓⟩ ∼ ⟨𝑔, ℎ⟩) → (⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ + ⟨𝑠, 𝑓⟩) ∼ (⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩ + ⟨𝑔, ℎ⟩))) & ⊢ 𝐺 = {⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ )) ∧
∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢∃𝑡((𝑥 = [⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑧 = [(⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ + ⟨𝑢, 𝑡⟩)] ∼
))} ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ 𝐺[⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ) = [(⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ + ⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩)] ∼ ) |
|
Theorem | oviec 6654* |
Express an operation on equivalence classes of ordered pairs in terms of
equivalence class of operations on ordered pairs. See iset.mm for
additional comments describing the hypotheses. (Unnecessary distinct
variable restrictions were removed by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.)
(Contributed by NM, 6-Aug-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
4-Jun-2013.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐻 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑎 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑔 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ ℎ ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐾 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑐 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑑 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐿 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) & ⊢ ∼
∈ V
& ⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆)
& ⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ 𝜑))} & ⊢ (((𝑧 = 𝑎 ∧ 𝑤 = 𝑏) ∧ (𝑣 = 𝑐 ∧ 𝑢 = 𝑑)) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (((𝑧 = 𝑔 ∧ 𝑤 = ℎ) ∧ (𝑣 = 𝑡 ∧ 𝑢 = 𝑠)) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ + =
{⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢∃𝑓((𝑥 = ⟨𝑤, 𝑣⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑢, 𝑓⟩) ∧ 𝑧 = 𝐽))} & ⊢ (((𝑤 = 𝑎 ∧ 𝑣 = 𝑏) ∧ (𝑢 = 𝑔 ∧ 𝑓 = ℎ)) → 𝐽 = 𝐾)
& ⊢ (((𝑤 = 𝑐 ∧ 𝑣 = 𝑑) ∧ (𝑢 = 𝑡 ∧ 𝑓 = 𝑠)) → 𝐽 = 𝐿)
& ⊢ (((𝑤 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝑣 = 𝐵) ∧ (𝑢 = 𝐶 ∧ 𝑓 = 𝐷)) → 𝐽 = 𝐻)
& ⊢ ⨣ =
{⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑄) ∧ ∃𝑎∃𝑏∃𝑐∃𝑑((𝑥 = [⟨𝑎, 𝑏⟩] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [⟨𝑐, 𝑑⟩] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑧 = [(⟨𝑎, 𝑏⟩ + ⟨𝑐, 𝑑⟩)] ∼ ))} & ⊢ 𝑄 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ ((((𝑎 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑐 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑑 ∈ 𝑆)) ∧ ((𝑔 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ ℎ ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝑆))) → ((𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝐾 ∼ 𝐿)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ ⨣ [⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ) = [𝐻] ∼ ) |
|
Theorem | ecovcom 6655* |
Lemma used to transfer a commutative law via an equivalence relation.
Most uses will want ecovicom 6656 instead. (Contributed by NM,
29-Aug-1995.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.)
|
⊢ 𝐶 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐷, 𝐺⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐻, 𝐽⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ 𝐷 = 𝐻
& ⊢ 𝐺 = 𝐽 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → (𝐴 + 𝐵) = (𝐵 + 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | ecovicom 6656* |
Lemma used to transfer a commutative law via an equivalence relation.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 15-Sep-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐶 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐷, 𝐺⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐻, 𝐽⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐷 = 𝐻)
& ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐺 = 𝐽) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → (𝐴 + 𝐵) = (𝐵 + 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | ecovass 6657* |
Lemma used to transfer an associative law via an equivalence relation.
In most cases ecoviass 6658 will be more useful. (Contributed by NM,
31-Aug-1995.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.)
|
⊢ 𝐷 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐺, 𝐻⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑁, 𝑄⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐻 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝐺, 𝐻⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐽, 𝐾⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑁 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑁, 𝑄⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐿, 𝑀⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝐺 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐻 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑁 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ 𝐽 = 𝐿
& ⊢ 𝐾 = 𝑀 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷) → ((𝐴 + 𝐵) + 𝐶) = (𝐴 + (𝐵 + 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | ecoviass 6658* |
Lemma used to transfer an associative law via an equivalence relation.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Sep-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐷 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐺, 𝐻⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑁, 𝑄⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐻 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝐺, 𝐻⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐽, 𝐾⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑁 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑁, 𝑄⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐿, 𝑀⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝐺 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐻 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑁 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐽 = 𝐿)
& ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐾 = 𝑀) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷) → ((𝐴 + 𝐵) + 𝐶) = (𝐴 + (𝐵 + 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | ecovdi 6659* |
Lemma used to transfer a distributive law via an equivalence relation.
Most likely ecovidi 6660 will be more helpful. (Contributed by NM,
2-Sep-1995.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.)
|
⊢ 𝐷 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑀, 𝑁⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑀 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑀, 𝑁⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐻, 𝐽⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑊, 𝑋⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑌, 𝑍⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑊 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑌 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑊, 𝑋⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑌, 𝑍⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐾, 𝐿⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑀 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑊 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑌 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ 𝐻 = 𝐾
& ⊢ 𝐽 = 𝐿 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 · (𝐵 + 𝐶)) = ((𝐴 · 𝐵) + (𝐴 · 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | ecovidi 6660* |
Lemma used to transfer a distributive law via an equivalence relation.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Sep-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐷 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑀, 𝑁⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑀 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑀, 𝑁⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐻, 𝐽⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑊, 𝑋⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑌, 𝑍⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑊 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑌 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑊, 𝑋⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑌, 𝑍⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐾, 𝐿⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑀 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑊 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑌 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐻 = 𝐾)
& ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → 𝐽 = 𝐿) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 · (𝐵 + 𝐶)) = ((𝐴 · 𝐵) + (𝐴 · 𝐶))) |
|
2.6.26 The mapping operation
|
|
Syntax | cmap 6661 |
Extend the definition of a class to include the mapping operation. (Read
for 𝐴
↑𝑚 𝐵, "the set of all functions that
map from 𝐵 to
𝐴.)
|
class ↑𝑚 |
|
Syntax | cpm 6662 |
Extend the definition of a class to include the partial mapping operation.
(Read for 𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵, "the set of all
partial functions that map from
𝐵 to 𝐴.)
|
class ↑pm |
|
Definition | df-map 6663* |
Define the mapping operation or set exponentiation. The set of all
functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴 is written (𝐴
↑𝑚 𝐵) (see
mapval 6673). Many authors write 𝐴 followed by 𝐵 as a
superscript
for this operation and rely on context to avoid confusion other
exponentiation operations (e.g., Definition 10.42 of [TakeutiZaring]
p. 95). Other authors show 𝐵 as a prefixed superscript, which is
read "𝐴 pre 𝐵 " (e.g., definition
of [Enderton] p. 52).
Definition 8.21 of [Eisenberg] p. 125
uses the notation Map(𝐵,
𝐴) for our (𝐴 ↑𝑚
𝐵). The up-arrow is
used by Donald Knuth
for iterated exponentiation (Science 194, 1235-1242, 1976). We
adopt
the first case of his notation (simple exponentiation) and subscript it
with m to distinguish it from other kinds of exponentiation.
(Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.)
|
⊢ ↑𝑚 = (𝑥 ∈ V, 𝑦 ∈ V ↦ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝑦⟶𝑥}) |
|
Definition | df-pm 6664* |
Define the partial mapping operation. A partial function from 𝐵 to
𝐴 is a function from a subset of 𝐵 to
𝐴.
The set of all
partial functions from 𝐵 to 𝐴 is written (𝐴
↑pm 𝐵) (see
pmvalg 6672). A notation for this operation apparently
does not appear in
the literature. We use ↑pm to distinguish it from the less
general
set exponentiation operation ↑𝑚 (df-map 6663) . See mapsspm 6695 for
its relationship to set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM,
15-Nov-2007.)
|
⊢ ↑pm = (𝑥 ∈ V, 𝑦 ∈ V ↦ {𝑓 ∈ 𝒫 (𝑦 × 𝑥) ∣ Fun 𝑓}) |
|
Theorem | mapprc 6665* |
When 𝐴 is a proper class, the class of all
functions mapping 𝐴
to 𝐵 is empty. Exercise 4.41 of [Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed
by NM, 8-Dec-2003.)
|
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ V → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} = ∅) |
|
Theorem | pmex 6666* |
The class of all partial functions from one set to another is a set.
(Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → {𝑓 ∣ (Fun 𝑓 ∧ 𝑓 ⊆ (𝐴 × 𝐵))} ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | mapex 6667* |
The class of all functions mapping one set to another is a set. Remark
after Definition 10.24 of [Kunen] p. 31.
(Contributed by Raph Levien,
4-Dec-2003.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | fnmap 6668 |
Set exponentiation has a universal domain. (Contributed by NM,
8-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ ↑𝑚 Fn (V ×
V) |
|
Theorem | fnpm 6669 |
Partial function exponentiation has a universal domain. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2013.)
|
⊢ ↑pm Fn (V ×
V) |
|
Theorem | reldmmap 6670 |
Set exponentiation is a well-behaved binary operator. (Contributed by
Stefan O'Rear, 27-Feb-2015.)
|
⊢ Rel dom
↑𝑚 |
|
Theorem | mapvalg 6671* |
The value of set exponentiation. (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) is the set of all
functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴. Definition 10.24 of
[Kunen]
p. 24. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐵⟶𝐴}) |
|
Theorem | pmvalg 6672* |
The value of the partial mapping operation. (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) is the set
of all partial functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴.
(Contributed by
NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) = {𝑓 ∈ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) ∣ Fun 𝑓}) |
|
Theorem | mapval 6673* |
The value of set exponentiation (inference version). (𝐴 ↑𝑚
𝐵) is
the set of all functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴.
Definition
10.24 of [Kunen] p. 24. (Contributed by
NM, 8-Dec-2003.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐵⟶𝐴} |
|
Theorem | elmapg 6674 |
Membership relation for set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM,
17-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) ↔ 𝐶:𝐵⟶𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | elmapd 6675 |
Deduction form of elmapg 6674. (Contributed by BJ, 11-Apr-2020.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) ↔ 𝐶:𝐵⟶𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | mapdm0 6676 |
The empty set is the only map with empty domain. (Contributed by Glauco
Siliprandi, 11-Oct-2020.) (Proof shortened by Thierry Arnoux,
3-Dec-2021.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐵 ↑𝑚 ∅) =
{∅}) |
|
Theorem | elpmg 6677 |
The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro,
14-Nov-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (Fun 𝐶 ∧ 𝐶 ⊆ (𝐵 × 𝐴)))) |
|
Theorem | elpm2g 6678 |
The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM,
31-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | elpm2r 6679 |
Sufficient condition for being a partial function. (Contributed by NM,
31-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ∧ (𝐹:𝐶⟶𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐵)) → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | elpmi 6680 |
A partial function is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
15-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) → (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | pmfun 6681 |
A partial function is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
30-Jan-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) → Fun 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | elmapex 6682 |
Eliminate antecedent for mapping theorems: domain can be taken to be a
set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Oct-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑𝑚 𝐶) → (𝐵 ∈ V ∧ 𝐶 ∈ V)) |
|
Theorem | elmapi 6683 |
A mapping is a function, forward direction only with superfluous
antecedent removed. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑𝑚 𝐶) → 𝐴:𝐶⟶𝐵) |
|
Theorem | elmapfn 6684 |
A mapping is a function with the appropriate domain. (Contributed by AV,
6-Apr-2019.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑𝑚 𝐶) → 𝐴 Fn 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | elmapfun 6685 |
A mapping is always a function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear,
9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 5-May-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑𝑚 𝐶) → Fun 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | elmapssres 6686 |
A restricted mapping is a mapping. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear,
9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-May-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑𝑚 𝐶) ∧ 𝐷 ⊆ 𝐶) → (𝐴 ↾ 𝐷) ∈ (𝐵 ↑𝑚 𝐷)) |
|
Theorem | fpmg 6687 |
A total function is a partial function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
31-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵) → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑pm 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | pmss12g 6688 |
Subset relation for the set of partial functions. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐷) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑊)) → (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ⊆ (𝐶 ↑pm 𝐷)) |
|
Theorem | pmresg 6689 |
Elementhood of a restricted function in the set of partial functions.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐶)) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | elmap 6690 |
Membership relation for set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM,
8-Dec-2003.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) ↔ 𝐹:𝐵⟶𝐴) |
|
Theorem | mapval2 6691* |
Alternate expression for the value of set exponentiation. (Contributed
by NM, 3-Nov-2007.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) = (𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) ∩ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓 Fn 𝐵}) |
|
Theorem | elpm 6692 |
The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM,
15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2013.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐹 ⊆ (𝐵 × 𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | elpm2 6693 |
The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM,
15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | fpm 6694 |
A total function is a partial function. (Contributed by NM,
15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵 → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑pm 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | mapsspm 6695 |
Set exponentiation is a subset of partial maps. (Contributed by NM,
15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 27-Feb-2016.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) ⊆ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | pmsspw 6696 |
Partial maps are a subset of the power set of the Cartesian product of
its arguments. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ⊆ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | mapsspw 6697 |
Set exponentiation is a subset of the power set of the Cartesian product
of its arguments. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2006.) (Revised by Mario
Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 𝐵) ⊆ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | fvmptmap 6698* |
Special case of fvmpt 5606 for operator theorems. (Contributed by NM,
27-Nov-2007.)
|
⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑅 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶)
& ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝑅 ↑𝑚 𝐷) ↦ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴:𝐷⟶𝑅 → (𝐹‘𝐴) = 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | map0e 6699 |
Set exponentiation with an empty exponent (ordinal number 0) is ordinal
number 1. Exercise 4.42(a) of [Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed by NM,
10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ↑𝑚 ∅) =
1o) |
|
Theorem | map0b 6700 |
Set exponentiation with an empty base is the empty set, provided the
exponent is nonempty. Theorem 96 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by
NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≠ ∅ → (∅
↑𝑚 𝐴) = ∅) |