![]() |
Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 127 of 156) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | omiunct 12601* | The union of a countably infinite collection of countable sets is countable. Theorem 8.1.28 of [AczelRathjen], p. 78. Compare with ctiunct 12597 which has a stronger hypothesis but does not require countable choice. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 5-May-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → CCHOICE) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ω) → ∃𝑔 𝑔:ω–onto→(𝐵 ⊔ 1o)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃ℎ ℎ:ω–onto→(∪ 𝑥 ∈ ω 𝐵 ⊔ 1o)) | ||
Theorem | ssomct 12602* | A decidable subset of ω is countable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ ω ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ω DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → ∃𝑓 𝑓:ω–onto→(𝐴 ⊔ 1o)) | ||
Theorem | ssnnctlemct 12603* | Lemma for ssnnct 12604. The result. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐺 = frec((𝑥 ∈ ℤ ↦ (𝑥 + 1)), 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → ∃𝑓 𝑓:ω–onto→(𝐴 ⊔ 1o)) | ||
Theorem | ssnnct 12604* | A decidable subset of ℕ is countable. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → ∃𝑓 𝑓:ω–onto→(𝐴 ⊔ 1o)) | ||
Theorem | nninfdclemcl 12605* | Lemma for nninfdc 12610. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐴 𝑚 < 𝑛) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑃 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑄 ∈ 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑃(𝑦 ∈ ℕ, 𝑧 ∈ ℕ ↦ inf((𝐴 ∩ (ℤ≥‘(𝑦 + 1))), ℝ, < ))𝑄) ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | nninfdclemf 12606* | Lemma for nninfdc 12610. A function from the natural numbers into 𝐴. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐴 𝑚 < 𝑛) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐽 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 1 < 𝐽)) & ⊢ 𝐹 = seq1((𝑦 ∈ ℕ, 𝑧 ∈ ℕ ↦ inf((𝐴 ∩ (ℤ≥‘(𝑦 + 1))), ℝ, < )), (𝑖 ∈ ℕ ↦ 𝐽)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ℕ⟶𝐴) | ||
Theorem | nninfdclemp1 12607* | Lemma for nninfdc 12610. Each element of the sequence 𝐹 is greater than the previous element. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐴 𝑚 < 𝑛) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐽 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 1 < 𝐽)) & ⊢ 𝐹 = seq1((𝑦 ∈ ℕ, 𝑧 ∈ ℕ ↦ inf((𝐴 ∩ (ℤ≥‘(𝑦 + 1))), ℝ, < )), (𝑖 ∈ ℕ ↦ 𝐽)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹‘𝑈) < (𝐹‘(𝑈 + 1))) | ||
Theorem | nninfdclemlt 12608* | Lemma for nninfdc 12610. The function from nninfdclemf 12606 is strictly monotonic. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐴 𝑚 < 𝑛) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐽 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 1 < 𝐽)) & ⊢ 𝐹 = seq1((𝑦 ∈ ℕ, 𝑧 ∈ ℕ ↦ inf((𝐴 ∩ (ℤ≥‘(𝑦 + 1))), ℝ, < )), (𝑖 ∈ ℕ ↦ 𝐽)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑉 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 < 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹‘𝑈) < (𝐹‘𝑉)) | ||
Theorem | nninfdclemf1 12609* | Lemma for nninfdc 12610. The function from nninfdclemf 12606 is one-to-one. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐴 𝑚 < 𝑛) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐽 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 1 < 𝐽)) & ⊢ 𝐹 = seq1((𝑦 ∈ ℕ, 𝑧 ∈ ℕ ↦ inf((𝐴 ∩ (ℤ≥‘(𝑦 + 1))), ℝ, < )), (𝑖 ∈ ℕ ↦ 𝐽)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ℕ–1-1→𝐴) | ||
Theorem | nninfdc 12610* | An unbounded decidable set of positive integers is infinite. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐴 𝑚 < 𝑛) → ω ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | unbendc 12611* | An unbounded decidable set of positive integers is infinite. (Contributed by NM, 5-May-2005.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 30-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ ℕ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ℕ DECID 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑛 ∈ 𝐴 𝑚 < 𝑛) → 𝐴 ≈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | prminf 12612 | There are an infinite number of primes. Theorem 1.7 in [ApostolNT] p. 16. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 28-Nov-2012.) |
⊢ ℙ ≈ ℕ | ||
Theorem | infpn2 12613* | There exist infinitely many prime numbers: the set of all primes 𝑆 is unbounded by infpn 12499, so by unbendc 12611 it is infinite. This is Metamath 100 proof #11. (Contributed by NM, 5-May-2005.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑛 ∈ ℕ ∣ (1 < 𝑛 ∧ ∀𝑚 ∈ ℕ ((𝑛 / 𝑚) ∈ ℕ → (𝑚 = 1 ∨ 𝑚 = 𝑛)))} ⇒ ⊢ 𝑆 ≈ ℕ | ||
An "extensible structure" (or "structure" in short, at least in this section) is used to define a specific group, ring, poset, and so on. An extensible structure can contain many components. For example, a group will have at least two components (base set and operation), although it can be further specialized by adding other components such as a multiplicative operation for rings (and still remain a group per our definition). Thus, every ring is also a group. This extensible structure approach allows theorems from more general structures (such as groups) to be reused for more specialized structures (such as rings) without having to reprove anything. Structures are common in mathematics, but in informal (natural language) proofs the details are assumed in ways that we must make explicit. An extensible structure is implemented as a function (a set of ordered pairs) on a finite (and not necessarily sequential) subset of ℕ. The function's argument is the index of a structure component (such as 1 for the base set of a group), and its value is the component (such as the base set). By convention, we normally avoid direct reference to the hard-coded numeric index and instead use structure component extractors such as ndxid 12642 and strslfv 12663. Using extractors makes it easier to change numeric indices and also makes the components' purpose clearer. See the comment of basendx 12673 for more details on numeric indices versus the structure component extractors. There are many other possible ways to handle structures. We chose this extensible structure approach because this approach (1) results in simpler notation than other approaches we are aware of, and (2) is easier to do proofs with. We cannot use an approach that uses "hidden" arguments; Metamath does not support hidden arguments, and in any case we want nothing hidden. It would be possible to use a categorical approach (e.g., something vaguely similar to Lean's mathlib). However, instances (the chain of proofs that an 𝑋 is a 𝑌 via a bunch of forgetful functors) can cause serious performance problems for automated tooling, and the resulting proofs would be painful to look at directly (in the case of Lean, they are long past the level where people would find it acceptable to look at them directly). Metamath is working under much stricter conditions than this, and it has still managed to achieve about the same level of flexibility through this "extensible structure" approach. To create a substructure of a given extensible structure, you can simply use the multifunction restriction operator for extensible structures ↾s as defined in df-iress 12626. This can be used to turn statements about rings into statements about subrings, modules into submodules, etc. This definition knows nothing about individual structures and merely truncates the Base set while leaving operators alone. Individual kinds of structures will need to handle this behavior by ignoring operators' values outside the range, defining a function using the base set and applying that, or explicitly truncating the slot before use. Extensible structures only work well when they represent concrete categories, where there is a "base set", morphisms are functions, and subobjects are subsets with induced operations. In short, they primarily work well for "sets with (some) extra structure". Extensible structures may not suffice for more complicated situations. For example, in manifolds, ↾s would not work. That said, extensible structures are sufficient for many of the structures that set.mm currently considers, and offer a good compromise for a goal-oriented formalization. | ||
Syntax | cstr 12614 | Extend class notation with the class of structures with components numbered below 𝐴. |
class Struct | ||
Syntax | cnx 12615 | Extend class notation with the structure component index extractor. |
class ndx | ||
Syntax | csts 12616 | Set components of a structure. |
class sSet | ||
Syntax | cslot 12617 | Extend class notation with the slot function. |
class Slot 𝐴 | ||
Syntax | cbs 12618 | Extend class notation with the class of all base set extractors. |
class Base | ||
Syntax | cress 12619 | Extend class notation with the extensible structure builder restriction operator. |
class ↾s | ||
Definition | df-struct 12620* |
Define a structure with components in 𝑀...𝑁. This is not a
requirement for groups, posets, etc., but it is a useful assumption for
component extraction theorems.
As mentioned in the section header, an "extensible structure should be implemented as a function (a set of ordered pairs)". The current definition, however, is less restrictive: it allows for classes which contain the empty set ∅ to be extensible structures. Because of 0nelfun 5272, such classes cannot be functions. Without the empty set, however, a structure must be a function, see structn0fun 12631: 𝐹 Struct 𝑋 → Fun (𝐹 ∖ {∅}). Allowing an extensible structure to contain the empty set ensures that expressions like {〈𝐴, 𝐵〉, 〈𝐶, 𝐷〉} are structures without asserting or implying that 𝐴, 𝐵, 𝐶 and 𝐷 are sets (if 𝐴 or 𝐵 is a proper class, then 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 = ∅, see opprc 3825). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ Struct = {〈𝑓, 𝑥〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ( ≤ ∩ (ℕ × ℕ)) ∧ Fun (𝑓 ∖ {∅}) ∧ dom 𝑓 ⊆ (...‘𝑥))} | ||
Definition | df-ndx 12621 | Define the structure component index extractor. See Theorem ndxarg 12641 to understand its purpose. The restriction to ℕ ensures that ndx is a set. The restriction to some set is necessary since I is a proper class. In principle, we could have chosen ℂ or (if we revise all structure component definitions such as df-base 12624) another set such as the set of finite ordinals ω (df-iom 4623). (Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ ndx = ( I ↾ ℕ) | ||
Definition | df-slot 12622* |
Define the slot extractor for extensible structures. The class
Slot 𝐴 is a function whose argument can be
any set, although it is
meaningful only if that set is a member of an extensible structure (such
as a partially ordered set or a group).
Note that Slot 𝐴 is implemented as "evaluation at 𝐴". That is, (Slot 𝐴‘𝑆) is defined to be (𝑆‘𝐴), where 𝐴 will typically be a small nonzero natural number. Each extensible structure 𝑆 is a function defined on specific natural number "slots", and this function extracts the value at a particular slot. The special "structure" ndx, defined as the identity function restricted to ℕ, can be used to extract the number 𝐴 from a slot, since (Slot 𝐴‘ndx) = 𝐴 (see ndxarg 12641). This is typically used to refer to the number of a slot when defining structures without having to expose the detail of what that number is (for instance, we use the expression (Base‘ndx) in theorems and proofs instead of its value 1). The class Slot cannot be defined as (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑓 ∈ V ↦ (𝑓‘𝑥))) because each Slot 𝐴 is a function on the proper class V so is itself a proper class, and the values of functions are sets (fvex 5574). It is necessary to allow proper classes as values of Slot 𝐴 since for instance the class of all (base sets of) groups is proper. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ Slot 𝐴 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑥‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | sloteq 12623 | Equality theorem for the Slot construction. The converse holds if 𝐴 (or 𝐵) is a set. (Contributed by BJ, 27-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → Slot 𝐴 = Slot 𝐵) | ||
Definition | df-base 12624 | Define the base set (also called underlying set, ground set, carrier set, or carrier) extractor for extensible structures. (Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ Base = Slot 1 | ||
Definition | df-sets 12625* | Set a component of an extensible structure. This function is useful for taking an existing structure and "overriding" one of its components. For example, df-iress 12626 adjusts the base set to match its second argument, which has the effect of making subgroups, subspaces, subrings etc. from the original structures. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ sSet = (𝑠 ∈ V, 𝑒 ∈ V ↦ ((𝑠 ↾ (V ∖ dom {𝑒})) ∪ {𝑒})) | ||
Definition | df-iress 12626* |
Define a multifunction restriction operator for extensible structures,
which can be used to turn statements about rings into statements about
subrings, modules into submodules, etc. This definition knows nothing
about individual structures and merely truncates the Base set while
leaving operators alone; individual kinds of structures will need to
handle this behavior, by ignoring operators' values outside the range,
defining a function using the base set and applying that, or explicitly
truncating the slot before use.
(Credit for this operator, as well as the 2023 modification for iset.mm, goes to Mario Carneiro.) (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 7-Oct-2023.) |
⊢ ↾s = (𝑤 ∈ V, 𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑤 sSet 〈(Base‘ndx), (𝑥 ∩ (Base‘𝑤))〉)) | ||
Theorem | brstruct 12627 | The structure relation is a relation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ Rel Struct | ||
Theorem | isstruct2im 12628 | The property of being a structure with components in (1st ‘𝑋)...(2nd ‘𝑋). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐹 Struct 𝑋 → (𝑋 ∈ ( ≤ ∩ (ℕ × ℕ)) ∧ Fun (𝐹 ∖ {∅}) ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ (...‘𝑋))) | ||
Theorem | isstruct2r 12629 | The property of being a structure with components in (1st ‘𝑋)...(2nd ‘𝑋). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (((𝑋 ∈ ( ≤ ∩ (ℕ × ℕ)) ∧ Fun (𝐹 ∖ {∅})) ∧ (𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ (...‘𝑋))) → 𝐹 Struct 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | structex 12630 | A structure is a set. (Contributed by AV, 10-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐺 Struct 𝑋 → 𝐺 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | structn0fun 12631 | A structure without the empty set is a function. (Contributed by AV, 13-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐹 Struct 𝑋 → Fun (𝐹 ∖ {∅})) | ||
Theorem | isstructim 12632 | The property of being a structure with components in 𝑀...𝑁. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐹 Struct 〈𝑀, 𝑁〉 → ((𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑀 ≤ 𝑁) ∧ Fun (𝐹 ∖ {∅}) ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ (𝑀...𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | isstructr 12633 | The property of being a structure with components in 𝑀...𝑁. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (((𝑀 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑀 ≤ 𝑁) ∧ (Fun (𝐹 ∖ {∅}) ∧ 𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ (𝑀...𝑁))) → 𝐹 Struct 〈𝑀, 𝑁〉) | ||
Theorem | structcnvcnv 12634 | Two ways to express the relational part of a structure. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐹 Struct 𝑋 → ◡◡𝐹 = (𝐹 ∖ {∅})) | ||
Theorem | structfung 12635 | The converse of the converse of a structure is a function. Closed form of structfun 12636. (Contributed by AV, 12-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐹 Struct 𝑋 → Fun ◡◡𝐹) | ||
Theorem | structfun 12636 | Convert between two kinds of structure closure. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) (Proof shortened by AV, 12-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ 𝐹 Struct 𝑋 ⇒ ⊢ Fun ◡◡𝐹 | ||
Theorem | structfn 12637 | Convert between two kinds of structure closure. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 Struct 〈𝑀, 𝑁〉 ⇒ ⊢ (Fun ◡◡𝐹 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ (1...𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | strnfvnd 12638 | Deduction version of strnfvn 12639. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = Slot 𝑁 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐸‘𝑆) = (𝑆‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | strnfvn 12639 |
Value of a structure component extractor 𝐸. Normally, 𝐸 is a
defined constant symbol such as Base (df-base 12624) and 𝑁 is a
fixed integer such as 1. 𝑆 is a structure, i.e. a
specific
member of a class of structures.
Note: Normally, this theorem shouldn't be used outside of this section, because it requires hard-coded index values. Instead, use strslfv 12663. (Contributed by NM, 9-Sep-2011.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jan-2023.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑆 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐸 = Slot 𝑁 & ⊢ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ⇒ ⊢ (𝐸‘𝑆) = (𝑆‘𝑁) | ||
Theorem | strfvssn 12640 | A structure component extractor produces a value which is contained in a set dependent on 𝑆, but not 𝐸. This is sometimes useful for showing sethood. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Aug-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 19-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = Slot 𝑁 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐸‘𝑆) ⊆ ∪ ran 𝑆) | ||
Theorem | ndxarg 12641 | Get the numeric argument from a defined structure component extractor such as df-base 12624. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = Slot 𝑁 & ⊢ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ⇒ ⊢ (𝐸‘ndx) = 𝑁 | ||
Theorem | ndxid 12642 |
A structure component extractor is defined by its own index. This
theorem, together with strslfv 12663 below, is useful for avoiding direct
reference to the hard-coded numeric index in component extractor
definitions, such as the 1 in df-base 12624, making it easier to change
should the need arise.
(Contributed by NM, 19-Oct-2012.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2013.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 27-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = Slot 𝑁 & ⊢ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ⇒ ⊢ 𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) | ||
Theorem | ndxslid 12643 | A structure component extractor is defined by its own index. That the index is a natural number will also be needed in quite a few contexts so it is included in the conclusion of this theorem which can be used as a hypothesis of theorems like strslfv 12663. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = Slot 𝑁 & ⊢ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ⇒ ⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | slotslfn 12644 | A slot is a function on sets, treated as structures. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Sep-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 10-Feb-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐸 Fn V | ||
Theorem | slotex 12645 | Existence of slot value. A corollary of slotslfn 12644. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 12-Feb-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐸‘𝐴) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | strndxid 12646 | The value of a structure component extractor is the value of the corresponding slot of the structure. (Contributed by AV, 13-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ 𝐸 = Slot 𝑁 & ⊢ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑆‘(𝐸‘ndx)) = (𝐸‘𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | reldmsets 12647 | The structure override operator is a proper operator. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ Rel dom sSet | ||
Theorem | setsvalg 12648 | Value of the structure replacement function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑆 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝑆 sSet 𝐴) = ((𝑆 ↾ (V ∖ dom {𝐴})) ∪ {𝐴})) | ||
Theorem | setsvala 12649 | Value of the structure replacement function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝑆 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝑆 sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) = ((𝑆 ↾ (V ∖ {𝐴})) ∪ {〈𝐴, 𝐵〉})) | ||
Theorem | setsex 12650 | Applying the structure replacement function yields a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝑆 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝑆 sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | strsetsid 12651 | Value of the structure replacement function. (Contributed by AV, 14-Mar-2020.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Struct 〈𝑀, 𝑁〉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ dom 𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 = (𝑆 sSet 〈(𝐸‘ndx), (𝐸‘𝑆)〉)) | ||
Theorem | fvsetsid 12652 | The value of the structure replacement function for its first argument is its second argument. (Contributed by SO, 12-Jul-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝑈) → ((𝐹 sSet 〈𝑋, 𝑌〉)‘𝑋) = 𝑌) | ||
Theorem | setsfun 12653 | A structure with replacement is a function if the original structure is a function. (Contributed by AV, 7-Jun-2021.) |
⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ Fun 𝐺) ∧ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐸 ∈ 𝑊)) → Fun (𝐺 sSet 〈𝐼, 𝐸〉)) | ||
Theorem | setsfun0 12654 | A structure with replacement without the empty set is a function if the original structure without the empty set is a function. This variant of setsfun 12653 is useful for proofs based on isstruct2r 12629 which requires Fun (𝐹 ∖ {∅}) for 𝐹 to be an extensible structure. (Contributed by AV, 7-Jun-2021.) |
⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ Fun (𝐺 ∖ {∅})) ∧ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝐸 ∈ 𝑊)) → Fun ((𝐺 sSet 〈𝐼, 𝐸〉) ∖ {∅})) | ||
Theorem | setsn0fun 12655 | The value of the structure replacement function (without the empty set) is a function if the structure (without the empty set) is a function. (Contributed by AV, 7-Jun-2021.) (Revised by AV, 16-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Struct 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐼 ∈ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐸 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun ((𝑆 sSet 〈𝐼, 𝐸〉) ∖ {∅})) | ||
Theorem | setsresg 12656 | The structure replacement function does not affect the value of 𝑆 away from 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 22-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝑆 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋) → ((𝑆 sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) ↾ (V ∖ {𝐴})) = (𝑆 ↾ (V ∖ {𝐴}))) | ||
Theorem | setsabsd 12657 | Replacing the same components twice yields the same as the second setting only. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 22-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑆 sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐶〉) = (𝑆 sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐶〉)) | ||
Theorem | setscom 12658 | Different components can be set in any order. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (((𝑆 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑋)) → ((𝑆 sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐶〉) sSet 〈𝐵, 𝐷〉) = ((𝑆 sSet 〈𝐵, 𝐷〉) sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐶〉)) | ||
Theorem | setscomd 12659 | Different components can be set in any order. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Feb-2025.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑍) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ∈ 𝑋) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑆 sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐶〉) sSet 〈𝐵, 𝐷〉) = ((𝑆 sSet 〈𝐵, 𝐷〉) sSet 〈𝐴, 𝐶〉)) | ||
Theorem | strslfvd 12660 | Deduction version of strslfv 12663. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉 ∈ 𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 = (𝐸‘𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | strslfv2d 12661 | Deduction version of strslfv 12663. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun ◡◡𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉 ∈ 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 = (𝐸‘𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | strslfv2 12662 | A variation on strslfv 12663 to avoid asserting that 𝑆 itself is a function, which involves sethood of all the ordered pair components of 𝑆. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ 𝑆 ∈ V & ⊢ Fun ◡◡𝑆 & ⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉 ∈ 𝑆 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐶 = (𝐸‘𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | strslfv 12663 | Extract a structure component 𝐶 (such as the base set) from a structure 𝑆 with a component extractor 𝐸 (such as the base set extractor df-base 12624). By virtue of ndxslid 12643, this can be done without having to refer to the hard-coded numeric index of 𝐸. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Oct-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ 𝑆 Struct 𝑋 & ⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ {〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉} ⊆ 𝑆 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐶 = (𝐸‘𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | strslfv3 12664 | Variant on strslfv 12663 for large structures. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jan-2017.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 30-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 = 𝑆) & ⊢ 𝑆 Struct 𝑋 & ⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ {〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉} ⊆ 𝑆 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ 𝐴 = (𝐸‘𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | strslssd 12665 | Deduction version of strslss 12666. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝑇) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ⊆ 𝑇) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉 ∈ 𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐸‘𝑇) = (𝐸‘𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | strslss 12666 | Propagate component extraction to a structure 𝑇 from a subset structure 𝑆. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Oct-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ 𝑇 ∈ V & ⊢ Fun 𝑇 & ⊢ 𝑆 ⊆ 𝑇 & ⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ 〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉 ∈ 𝑆 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐸‘𝑇) = (𝐸‘𝑆) | ||
Theorem | strsl0 12667 | All components of the empty set are empty sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 27-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ ∅ = (𝐸‘∅) | ||
Theorem | base0 12668 | The base set of the empty structure. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 7-Jul-2016.) |
⊢ ∅ = (Base‘∅) | ||
Theorem | setsslid 12669 | Value of the structure replacement function at a replaced index. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑊 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) → 𝐶 = (𝐸‘(𝑊 sSet 〈(𝐸‘ndx), 𝐶〉))) | ||
Theorem | setsslnid 12670 | Value of the structure replacement function at an untouched index. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Dec-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝐸‘ndx) ≠ 𝐷 & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ ℕ ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑊 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝐸‘𝑊) = (𝐸‘(𝑊 sSet 〈𝐷, 𝐶〉))) | ||
Theorem | baseval 12671 | Value of the base set extractor. (Normally it is preferred to work with (Base‘ndx) rather than the hard-coded 1 in order to make structure theorems portable. This is an example of how to obtain it when needed.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐾 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Base‘𝐾) = (𝐾‘1) | ||
Theorem | baseid 12672 | Utility theorem: index-independent form of df-base 12624. (Contributed by NM, 20-Oct-2012.) |
⊢ Base = Slot (Base‘ndx) | ||
Theorem | basendx 12673 |
Index value of the base set extractor.
Use of this theorem is discouraged since the particular value 1 for the index is an implementation detail. It is generally sufficient to work with (Base‘ndx) and use theorems such as baseid 12672 and basendxnn 12674. The main circumstance in which it is necessary to look at indices directly is when showing that a set of indices are disjoint, in proofs such as lmodstrd 12781. Although we have a few theorems such as basendxnplusgndx 12742, we do not intend to add such theorems for every pair of indices (which would be quadradically many in the number of indices). (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Aug-2013.) |
⊢ (Base‘ndx) = 1 | ||
Theorem | basendxnn 12674 | The index value of the base set extractor is a positive integer. This property should be ensured for every concrete coding because otherwise it could not be used in an extensible structure (slots must be positive integers). (Contributed by AV, 23-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (Base‘ndx) ∈ ℕ | ||
Theorem | baseslid 12675 | The base set extractor is a slot. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 31-Jan-2023.) |
⊢ (Base = Slot (Base‘ndx) ∧ (Base‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | basfn 12676 | The base set extractor is a function on V. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Jul-2015.) |
⊢ Base Fn V | ||
Theorem | basmex 12677 | A structure whose base is inhabited is a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐺 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | basmexd 12678 | A structure whose base is inhabited is a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 28-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | basm 12679* | A structure whose base is inhabited is inhabited. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 14-Jun-2025.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → ∃𝑗 𝑗 ∈ 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | relelbasov 12680 | Utility theorem: reverse closure for any structure defined as a two-argument function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Oct-2015.) |
⊢ Rel dom 𝑂 & ⊢ Rel 𝑂 & ⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑋𝑂𝑌) & ⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑆) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝑋 ∈ V ∧ 𝑌 ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | reldmress 12681 | The structure restriction is a proper operator, so it can be used with ovprc1 5954. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ Rel dom ↾s | ||
Theorem | ressvalsets 12682 | Value of structure restriction. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jan-2025.) |
⊢ ((𝑊 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌) → (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴) = (𝑊 sSet 〈(Base‘ndx), (𝐴 ∩ (Base‘𝑊))〉)) | ||
Theorem | ressex 12683 | Existence of structure restriction. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 16-Jan-2025.) |
⊢ ((𝑊 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌) → (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | ressval2 12684 | Value of nontrivial structure restriction. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑅 = (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ ((¬ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑊 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑌) → 𝑅 = (𝑊 sSet 〈(Base‘ndx), (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵)〉)) | ||
Theorem | ressbasd 12685 | Base set of a structure restriction. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 26-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 7-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑊)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = (Base‘𝑅)) | ||
Theorem | ressbas2d 12686 | Base set of a structure restriction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑊)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = (Base‘𝑅)) | ||
Theorem | ressbasssd 12687 | The base set of a restriction is a subset of the base set of the original structure. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 27-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑊)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Base‘𝑅) ⊆ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | ressbasid 12688 | The trivial structure restriction leaves the base set unchanged. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 29-Apr-2025.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑊 ∈ 𝑉 → (Base‘(𝑊 ↾s 𝐵)) = 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | strressid 12689 | Behavior of trivial restriction. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 17-Jan-2025.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑊)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 Struct 〈𝑀, 𝑁〉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (Base‘ndx) ∈ dom 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑊 ↾s 𝐵) = 𝑊) | ||
Theorem | ressval3d 12690 | Value of structure restriction, deduction version. (Contributed by AV, 14-Mar-2020.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 17-Jan-2025.) |
⊢ 𝑅 = (𝑆 ↾s 𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑆) & ⊢ 𝐸 = (Base‘ndx) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐸 ∈ dom 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = (𝑆 sSet 〈𝐸, 𝐴〉)) | ||
Theorem | resseqnbasd 12691 | The components of an extensible structure except the base set remain unchanged on a structure restriction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Dec-2014.) (Revised by AV, 19-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑅 = (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐶 = (𝐸‘𝑊) & ⊢ (𝐸 = Slot (𝐸‘ndx) ∧ (𝐸‘ndx) ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝐸‘ndx) ≠ (Base‘ndx) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 = (𝐸‘𝑅)) | ||
Theorem | ressinbasd 12692 | Restriction only cares about the part of the second set which intersects the base of the first. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = (Base‘𝑊)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑊 ↾s 𝐴) = (𝑊 ↾s (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ressressg 12693 | Restriction composition law. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 2-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑌 ∧ 𝑊 ∈ 𝑍) → ((𝑊 ↾s 𝐴) ↾s 𝐵) = (𝑊 ↾s (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ressabsg 12694 | Restriction absorption law. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑊 ∈ 𝑌) → ((𝑊 ↾s 𝐴) ↾s 𝐵) = (𝑊 ↾s 𝐵)) | ||
Syntax | cplusg 12695 | Extend class notation with group (addition) operation. |
class +g | ||
Syntax | cmulr 12696 | Extend class notation with ring multiplication. |
class .r | ||
Syntax | cstv 12697 | Extend class notation with involution. |
class *𝑟 | ||
Syntax | csca 12698 | Extend class notation with scalar field. |
class Scalar | ||
Syntax | cvsca 12699 | Extend class notation with scalar product. |
class ·𝑠 | ||
Syntax | cip 12700 | Extend class notation with Hermitian form (inner product). |
class ·𝑖 |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |