![]() |
Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 149 of 149) | < Previous Wrap > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | iswomninn 14801* | Weak omniscience stated in terms of natural numbers. Similar to iswomnimap 7164 but it will sometimes be more convenient to use 0 and 1 rather than β and 1o. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jun-2024.) |
β’ (π΄ β π β (π΄ β WOmni β βπ β ({0, 1} βπ π΄)DECID βπ₯ β π΄ (πβπ₯) = 1)) | ||
Theorem | iswomni0 14802* | Weak omniscience stated in terms of equality with 0. Like iswomninn 14801 but with zero in place of one. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (π΄ β π β (π΄ β WOmni β βπ β ({0, 1} βπ π΄)DECID βπ₯ β π΄ (πβπ₯) = 0)) | ||
Theorem | ismkvnnlem 14803* | Lemma for ismkvnn 14804. The result, with a hypothesis to give a name to an expression for convenience. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2024.) |
β’ πΊ = frec((π₯ β β€ β¦ (π₯ + 1)), 0) β β’ (π΄ β π β (π΄ β Markov β βπ β ({0, 1} βπ π΄)(Β¬ βπ₯ β π΄ (πβπ₯) = 1 β βπ₯ β π΄ (πβπ₯) = 0))) | ||
Theorem | ismkvnn 14804* | The predicate of being Markov stated in terms of set exponentiation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2024.) |
β’ (π΄ β π β (π΄ β Markov β βπ β ({0, 1} βπ π΄)(Β¬ βπ₯ β π΄ (πβπ₯) = 1 β βπ₯ β π΄ (πβπ₯) = 0))) | ||
Theorem | redcwlpolemeq1 14805* | Lemma for redcwlpo 14806. A biconditionalized version of trilpolemeq1 14791. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Jun-2024.) |
β’ (π β πΉ:ββΆ{0, 1}) & β’ π΄ = Ξ£π β β ((1 / (2βπ)) Β· (πΉβπ)) β β’ (π β (π΄ = 1 β βπ₯ β β (πΉβπ₯) = 1)) | ||
Theorem | redcwlpo 14806* |
Decidability of real number equality implies the Weak Limited Principle
of Omniscience (WLPO). We expect that we'd need some form of countable
choice to prove the converse.
Here's the outline of the proof. Given an infinite sequence F of zeroes and ones, we need to show the sequence is all ones or it is not. Construct a real number A whose representation in base two consists of a zero, a decimal point, and then the numbers of the sequence. This real number will equal one if and only if the sequence is all ones (redcwlpolemeq1 14805). Therefore decidability of real number equality would imply decidability of whether the sequence is all ones. Because of this theorem, decidability of real number equality is sometimes called "analytic WLPO". WLPO is known to not be provable in IZF (and most constructive foundations), so this theorem establishes that we will be unable to prove an analogue to qdceq 10247 for real numbers. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Jun-2024.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β DECID π₯ = π¦ β Ο β WOmni) | ||
Theorem | tridceq 14807* | Real trichotomy implies decidability of real number equality. Or in other words, analytic LPO implies analytic WLPO (see trilpo 14794 and redcwlpo 14806). Thus, this is an analytic analogue to lpowlpo 7166. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β (π₯ < π¦ β¨ π₯ = π¦ β¨ π¦ < π₯) β βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β DECID π₯ = π¦) | ||
Theorem | redc0 14808* | Two ways to express decidability of real number equality. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β DECID π₯ = π¦ β βπ§ β β DECID π§ = 0) | ||
Theorem | reap0 14809* | Real number trichotomy is equivalent to decidability of apartness from zero. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β (π₯ < π¦ β¨ π₯ = π¦ β¨ π¦ < π₯) β βπ§ β β DECID π§ # 0) | ||
Theorem | dceqnconst 14810* | Decidability of real number equality implies the existence of a certain non-constant function from real numbers to integers. Variation of Exercise 11.6(i) of [HoTT], p. (varies). See redcwlpo 14806 for more discussion of decidability of real number equality. (Contributed by BJ and Jim Kingdon, 24-Jun-2024.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 23-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β DECID π₯ = 0 β βπ(π:ββΆβ€ β§ (πβ0) = 0 β§ βπ₯ β β+ (πβπ₯) β 0)) | ||
Theorem | dcapnconst 14811* |
Decidability of real number apartness implies the existence of a certain
non-constant function from real numbers to integers. Variation of
Exercise 11.6(i) of [HoTT], p. (varies).
See trilpo 14794 for more
discussion of decidability of real number apartness.
This is a weaker form of dceqnconst 14810 and in fact this theorem can be proved using dceqnconst 14810 as shown at dcapnconstALT 14812. (Contributed by BJ and Jim Kingdon, 24-Jun-2024.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β DECID π₯ # 0 β βπ(π:ββΆβ€ β§ (πβ0) = 0 β§ βπ₯ β β+ (πβπ₯) β 0)) | ||
Theorem | dcapnconstALT 14812* | Decidability of real number apartness implies the existence of a certain non-constant function from real numbers to integers. A proof of dcapnconst 14811 by means of dceqnconst 14810. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-Jul-2024.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β DECID π₯ # 0 β βπ(π:ββΆβ€ β§ (πβ0) = 0 β§ βπ₯ β β+ (πβπ₯) β 0)) | ||
Theorem | nconstwlpolem0 14813* | Lemma for nconstwlpo 14816. If all the terms of the series are zero, so is their sum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (π β πΊ:ββΆ{0, 1}) & β’ π΄ = Ξ£π β β ((1 / (2βπ)) Β· (πΊβπ)) & β’ (π β βπ₯ β β (πΊβπ₯) = 0) β β’ (π β π΄ = 0) | ||
Theorem | nconstwlpolemgt0 14814* | Lemma for nconstwlpo 14816. If one of the terms of series is positive, so is the sum. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 26-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (π β πΊ:ββΆ{0, 1}) & β’ π΄ = Ξ£π β β ((1 / (2βπ)) Β· (πΊβπ)) & β’ (π β βπ₯ β β (πΊβπ₯) = 1) β β’ (π β 0 < π΄) | ||
Theorem | nconstwlpolem 14815* | Lemma for nconstwlpo 14816. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (π β πΉ:ββΆβ€) & β’ (π β (πΉβ0) = 0) & β’ ((π β§ π₯ β β+) β (πΉβπ₯) β 0) & β’ (π β πΊ:ββΆ{0, 1}) & β’ π΄ = Ξ£π β β ((1 / (2βπ)) Β· (πΊβπ)) β β’ (π β (βπ¦ β β (πΊβπ¦) = 0 β¨ Β¬ βπ¦ β β (πΊβπ¦) = 0)) | ||
Theorem | nconstwlpo 14816* | Existence of a certain non-constant function from reals to integers implies Ο β WOmni (the Weak Limited Principle of Omniscience or WLPO). Based on Exercise 11.6(ii) of [HoTT], p. (varies). (Contributed by BJ and Jim Kingdon, 22-Jul-2024.) |
β’ (π β πΉ:ββΆβ€) & β’ (π β (πΉβ0) = 0) & β’ ((π β§ π₯ β β+) β (πΉβπ₯) β 0) β β’ (π β Ο β WOmni) | ||
Theorem | neapmkvlem 14817* | Lemma for neapmkv 14818. The result, with a few hypotheses broken out for convenience. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 25-Jun-2024.) |
β’ (π β πΉ:ββΆ{0, 1}) & β’ π΄ = Ξ£π β β ((1 / (2βπ)) Β· (πΉβπ)) & β’ ((π β§ π΄ β 1) β π΄ # 1) β β’ (π β (Β¬ βπ₯ β β (πΉβπ₯) = 1 β βπ₯ β β (πΉβπ₯) = 0)) | ||
Theorem | neapmkv 14818* | If negated equality for real numbers implies apartness, Markov's Principle follows. Exercise 11.10 of [HoTT], p. (varies). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jun-2024.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β (π₯ β π¦ β π₯ # π¦) β Ο β Markov) | ||
Theorem | neap0mkv 14819* | The analytic Markov principle can be expressed either with two arbitrary real numbers, or one arbitrary number and zero. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Feb-2025.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β (π₯ β π¦ β π₯ # π¦) β βπ₯ β β (π₯ β 0 β π₯ # 0)) | ||
Theorem | ltlenmkv 14820* | If < can be expressed as holding exactly when β€ holds and the values are not equal, then the analytic Markov's Principle applies. (To get the regular Markov's Principle, combine with neapmkv 14818). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 23-Feb-2025.) |
β’ (βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β (π₯ < π¦ β (π₯ β€ π¦ β§ π¦ β π₯)) β βπ₯ β β βπ¦ β β (π₯ β π¦ β π₯ # π¦)) | ||
Theorem | supfz 14821 | The supremum of a finite sequence of integers. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Oct-2022.) |
β’ (π β (β€β₯βπ) β sup((π...π), β€, < ) = π) | ||
Theorem | inffz 14822 | The infimum of a finite sequence of integers. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Oct-2022.) |
β’ (π β (β€β₯βπ) β inf((π...π), β€, < ) = π) | ||
Theorem | taupi 14823 | Relationship between Ο and Ο. This can be seen as connecting the ratio of a circle's circumference to its radius and the ratio of a circle's circumference to its diameter. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Feb-2019.) (Revised by AV, 1-Oct-2020.) |
β’ Ο = (2 Β· Ο) | ||
Theorem | ax1hfs 14824 | Heyting's formal system Axiom #1 from [Heyting] p. 127. (Contributed by MM, 11-Aug-2018.) |
β’ (π β (π β§ π)) | ||
Theorem | dftest 14825 |
A proposition is testable iff its negative or double-negative is true.
See Chapter 2 [Moschovakis] p. 2.
We do not formally define testability with a new token, but instead use DECID Β¬ before the formula in question. For example, DECID Β¬ π₯ = π¦ corresponds to "π₯ = π¦ is testable". (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 13-Aug-2018.) For statements about testable propositions, search for the keyword "testable" in the comments of statements, for instance using the Metamath command "MM> SEARCH * "testable" / COMMENTS". (New usage is discouraged.) |
β’ (DECID Β¬ π β (Β¬ π β¨ Β¬ Β¬ π)) | ||
These are definitions and proofs involving an experimental "allsome" quantifier (aka "all some"). In informal language, statements like "All Martians are green" imply that there is at least one Martian. But it's easy to mistranslate informal language into formal notations because similar statements like βπ₯π β π do not imply that π is ever true, leading to vacuous truths. Some systems include a mechanism to counter this, e.g., PVS allows types to be appended with "+" to declare that they are nonempty. This section presents a different solution to the same problem. The "allsome" quantifier expressly includes the notion of both "all" and "there exists at least one" (aka some), and is defined to make it easier to more directly express both notions. The hope is that if a quantifier more directly expresses this concept, it will be used instead and reduce the risk of creating formal expressions that look okay but in fact are mistranslations. The term "allsome" was chosen because it's short, easy to say, and clearly hints at the two concepts it combines. I do not expect this to be used much in metamath, because in metamath there's a general policy of avoiding the use of new definitions unless there are very strong reasons to do so. Instead, my goal is to rigorously define this quantifier and demonstrate a few basic properties of it. The syntax allows two forms that look like they would be problematic, but they are fine. When applied to a top-level implication we allow β!π₯(π β π), and when restricted (applied to a class) we allow β!π₯ β π΄π. The first symbol after the setvar variable must always be β if it is the form applied to a class, and since β cannot begin a wff, it is unambiguous. The β looks like it would be a problem because π or π might include implications, but any implication arrow β within any wff must be surrounded by parentheses, so only the implication arrow of β! can follow the wff. The implication syntax would work fine without the parentheses, but I added the parentheses because it makes things clearer inside larger complex expressions, and it's also more consistent with the rest of the syntax. For more, see "The Allsome Quantifier" by David A. Wheeler at https://dwheeler.com/essays/allsome.html I hope that others will eventually agree that allsome is awesome. | ||
Syntax | walsi 14826 | Extend wff definition to include "all some" applied to a top-level implication, which means π is true whenever π is true, and there is at least least one π₯ where π is true. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
wff β!π₯(π β π) | ||
Syntax | walsc 14827 | Extend wff definition to include "all some" applied to a class, which means π is true for all π₯ in π΄, and there is at least one π₯ in π΄. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
wff β!π₯ β π΄π | ||
Definition | df-alsi 14828 | Define "all some" applied to a top-level implication, which means π is true whenever π is true and there is at least one π₯ where π is true. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
β’ (β!π₯(π β π) β (βπ₯(π β π) β§ βπ₯π)) | ||
Definition | df-alsc 14829 | Define "all some" applied to a class, which means π is true for all π₯ in π΄ and there is at least one π₯ in π΄. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
β’ (β!π₯ β π΄π β (βπ₯ β π΄ π β§ βπ₯ π₯ β π΄)) | ||
Theorem | alsconv 14830 | There is an equivalence between the two "all some" forms. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 22-Oct-2018.) |
β’ (β!π₯(π₯ β π΄ β π) β β!π₯ β π΄π) | ||
Theorem | alsi1d 14831 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a top-level inference, you can extract the "for all" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
β’ (π β β!π₯(π β π)) β β’ (π β βπ₯(π β π)) | ||
Theorem | alsi2d 14832 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a top-level inference, you can extract the "exists" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
β’ (π β β!π₯(π β π)) β β’ (π β βπ₯π) | ||
Theorem | alsc1d 14833 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a class, you can extract the "for all" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
β’ (π β β!π₯ β π΄π) β β’ (π β βπ₯ β π΄ π) | ||
Theorem | alsc2d 14834 | Deduction rule: Given "all some" applied to a class, you can extract the "there exists" part. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 20-Oct-2018.) |
β’ (π β β!π₯ β π΄π) β β’ (π β βπ₯ π₯ β π΄) |
< Previous Wrap > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Wrap > |