Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 6701-6800 *Has distinct variable
group(s)
Type | Label | Description |
Statement |
|
Theorem | elixpsn 6701* |
Membership in a class of singleton functions. (Contributed by Stefan
O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ {𝐴}𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐹 = {〈𝐴, 𝑦〉})) |
|
Theorem | ixpsnf1o 6702* |
A bijection between a class and single-point functions to it.
(Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ({𝐼} × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→X𝑦 ∈ {𝐼}𝐴) |
|
Theorem | mapsnf1o 6703* |
A bijection between a set and single-point functions to it.
(Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ({𝐼} × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐼 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→(𝐴 ↑𝑚 {𝐼})) |
|
2.6.28 Equinumerosity
|
|
Syntax | cen 6704 |
Extend class definition to include the equinumerosity relation
("approximately equals" symbol)
|
class ≈ |
|
Syntax | cdom 6705 |
Extend class definition to include the dominance relation (curly
less-than-or-equal)
|
class ≼ |
|
Syntax | cfn 6706 |
Extend class definition to include the class of all finite sets.
|
class Fin |
|
Definition | df-en 6707* |
Define the equinumerosity relation. Definition of [Enderton] p. 129.
We define ≈ to be a binary relation rather
than a connective, so
its arguments must be sets to be meaningful. This is acceptable because
we do not consider equinumerosity for proper classes. We derive the
usual definition as bren 6713. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.)
|
⊢ ≈ = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝑥–1-1-onto→𝑦} |
|
Definition | df-dom 6708* |
Define the dominance relation. Compare Definition of [Enderton] p. 145.
Typical textbook definitions are derived as brdom 6716 and domen 6717.
(Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.)
|
⊢ ≼ = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝑥–1-1→𝑦} |
|
Definition | df-fin 6709* |
Define the (proper) class of all finite sets. Similar to Definition
10.29 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91,
whose "Fin(a)" corresponds to
our "𝑎 ∈ Fin". This definition is
meaningful whether or not we
accept the Axiom of Infinity ax-inf2 13858. (Contributed by NM,
22-Aug-2008.)
|
⊢ Fin = {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ ω 𝑥 ≈ 𝑦} |
|
Theorem | relen 6710 |
Equinumerosity is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.)
|
⊢ Rel ≈ |
|
Theorem | reldom 6711 |
Dominance is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1998.)
|
⊢ Rel ≼ |
|
Theorem | encv 6712 |
If two classes are equinumerous, both classes are sets. (Contributed by
AV, 21-Mar-2019.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝐵 ∈ V)) |
|
Theorem | bren 6713* |
Equinumerosity relation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) |
|
Theorem | brdomg 6714* |
Dominance relation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | brdomi 6715* |
Dominance relation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 → ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) |
|
Theorem | brdom 6716* |
Dominance relation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) |
|
Theorem | domen 6717* |
Dominance in terms of equinumerosity. Example 1 of [Enderton] p. 146.
(Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝐴 ≈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ⊆ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | domeng 6718* |
Dominance in terms of equinumerosity, with the sethood requirement
expressed as an antecedent. Example 1 of [Enderton] p. 146.
(Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝐴 ≈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ⊆ 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | ctex 6719 |
A class dominated by ω is a set. See also ctfoex 7083 which says that
a countable class is a set. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 29-Dec-2016.)
(Proof shortened by Jim Kingdon, 13-Mar-2023.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ ω → 𝐴 ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | f1oen3g 6720 |
The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto function are equinumerous.
This variation of f1oeng 6723 does not require the Axiom of Replacement.
(Contributed by NM, 13-Jan-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
10-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | f1oen2g 6721 |
The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto function are equinumerous.
This variation of f1oeng 6723 does not require the Axiom of Replacement.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | f1dom2g 6722 |
The domain of a one-to-one function is dominated by its codomain. This
variation of f1domg 6724 does not require the Axiom of Replacement.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | f1oeng 6723 |
The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto function are equinumerous.
(Contributed by NM, 19-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | f1domg 6724 |
The domain of a one-to-one function is dominated by its codomain.
(Contributed by NM, 4-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 → (𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | f1oen 6725 |
The domain and range of a one-to-one, onto function are equinumerous.
(Contributed by NM, 19-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | f1dom 6726 |
The domain of a one-to-one function is dominated by its codomain.
(Contributed by NM, 19-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | isfi 6727* |
Express "𝐴 is finite". Definition 10.29
of [TakeutiZaring] p. 91
(whose "Fin " is a predicate instead
of a class). (Contributed by
NM, 22-Aug-2008.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ ω 𝐴 ≈ 𝑥) |
|
Theorem | enssdom 6728 |
Equinumerosity implies dominance. (Contributed by NM, 31-Mar-1998.)
|
⊢ ≈ ⊆ ≼ |
|
Theorem | endom 6729 |
Equinumerosity implies dominance. Theorem 15 of [Suppes] p. 94.
(Contributed by NM, 28-May-1998.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | enrefg 6730 |
Equinumerosity is reflexive. Theorem 1 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed
by NM, 18-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | enref 6731 |
Equinumerosity is reflexive. Theorem 1 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed
by NM, 25-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | eqeng 6732 |
Equality implies equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 = 𝐵 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | domrefg 6733 |
Dominance is reflexive. (Contributed by NM, 18-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | en2d 6734* |
Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function.
(Contributed by NM, 27-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
12-May-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ V)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ V)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐶) ↔ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐷))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | en3d 6735* |
Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function.
(Contributed by NM, 27-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
12-May-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑥 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑦 = 𝐶))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | en2i 6736* |
Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function.
(Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ V) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐶) ↔ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐷)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 |
|
Theorem | en3i 6737* |
Equinumerosity inference from an implicit one-to-one onto function.
(Contributed by NM, 19-Jul-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)
& ⊢ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑥 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑦 = 𝐶)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 |
|
Theorem | dom2lem 6738* |
A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis)
implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by NM,
24-Jul-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶):𝐴–1-1→𝐵) |
|
Theorem | dom2d 6739* |
A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis)
implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by NM,
24-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐵 ∈ 𝑅 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | dom3d 6740* |
A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis)
implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 20-May-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | dom2 6741* |
A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis)
implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. 𝐶 and 𝐷 can be
read 𝐶(𝑥) and 𝐷(𝑦), as can be inferred from their
distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2003.)
|
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | dom3 6742* |
A mapping (first hypothesis) that is one-to-one (second hypothesis)
implies its domain is dominated by its codomain. 𝐶 and 𝐷 can be
read 𝐶(𝑥) and 𝐷(𝑦), as can be inferred from their
distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
20-May-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐶 = 𝐷 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | idssen 6743 |
Equality implies equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1998.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ I ⊆ ≈ |
|
Theorem | ssdomg 6744 |
A set dominates its subsets. Theorem 16 of [Suppes] p. 94. (Contributed
by NM, 19-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | ener 6745 |
Equinumerosity is an equivalence relation. (Contributed by NM,
19-Mar-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ≈ Er V |
|
Theorem | ensymb 6746 |
Symmetry of equinumerosity. Theorem 2 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | ensym 6747 |
Symmetry of equinumerosity. Theorem 2 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed by
NM, 26-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | ensymi 6748 |
Symmetry of equinumerosity. Theorem 2 of [Suppes] p. 92. (Contributed
by NM, 25-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | ensymd 6749 |
Symmetry of equinumerosity. Deduction form of ensym 6747. (Contributed
by David Moews, 1-May-2017.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ≈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | entr 6750 |
Transitivity of equinumerosity. Theorem 3 of [Suppes] p. 92.
(Contributed by NM, 9-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | domtr 6751 |
Transitivity of dominance relation. Theorem 17 of [Suppes] p. 94.
(Contributed by NM, 4-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | entri 6752 |
A chained equinumerosity inference. (Contributed by NM,
25-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵
& ⊢ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐶 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐶 |
|
Theorem | entr2i 6753 |
A chained equinumerosity inference. (Contributed by NM,
25-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵
& ⊢ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐶 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐶 ≈ 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | entr3i 6754 |
A chained equinumerosity inference. (Contributed by NM,
25-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵
& ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐶 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐶 |
|
Theorem | entr4i 6755 |
A chained equinumerosity inference. (Contributed by NM,
25-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵
& ⊢ 𝐶 ≈ 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐶 |
|
Theorem | endomtr 6756 |
Transitivity of equinumerosity and dominance. (Contributed by NM,
7-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | domentr 6757 |
Transitivity of dominance and equinumerosity. (Contributed by NM,
7-Jun-1998.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ≼ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | f1imaeng 6758 |
A one-to-one function's image under a subset of its domain is equinumerous
to the subset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝐹 “ 𝐶) ≈ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | f1imaen2g 6759 |
A one-to-one function's image under a subset of its domain is equinumerous
to the subset. (This version of f1imaen 6760 does not need ax-setind 4514.)
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
25-Jun-2015.)
|
⊢ (((𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) ∧ (𝐶 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉)) → (𝐹 “ 𝐶) ≈ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | f1imaen 6760 |
A one-to-one function's image under a subset of its domain is
equinumerous to the subset. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐹 “ 𝐶) ≈ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | en0 6761 |
The empty set is equinumerous only to itself. Exercise 1 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 88.
(Contributed by NM, 27-May-1998.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ ∅ ↔ 𝐴 = ∅) |
|
Theorem | ensn1 6762 |
A singleton is equinumerous to ordinal one. (Contributed by NM,
4-Nov-2002.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ {𝐴} ≈ 1o |
|
Theorem | ensn1g 6763 |
A singleton is equinumerous to ordinal one. (Contributed by NM,
23-Apr-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝐴} ≈ 1o) |
|
Theorem | enpr1g 6764 |
{𝐴, 𝐴} has only one element.
(Contributed by FL, 15-Feb-2010.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝐴, 𝐴} ≈ 1o) |
|
Theorem | en1 6765* |
A set is equinumerous to ordinal one iff it is a singleton.
(Contributed by NM, 25-Jul-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 1o ↔ ∃𝑥 𝐴 = {𝑥}) |
|
Theorem | en1bg 6766 |
A set is equinumerous to ordinal one iff it is a singleton.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Apr-2020.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ≈ 1o ↔ 𝐴 = {∪ 𝐴})) |
|
Theorem | reuen1 6767* |
Two ways to express "exactly one". (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear,
28-Oct-2014.)
|
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} ≈ 1o) |
|
Theorem | euen1 6768 |
Two ways to express "exactly one". (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear,
28-Oct-2014.)
|
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 ↔ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ≈ 1o) |
|
Theorem | euen1b 6769* |
Two ways to express "𝐴 has a unique element".
(Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 9-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 1o ↔ ∃!𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | en1uniel 6770 |
A singleton contains its sole element. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear,
16-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝑆 ≈ 1o → ∪ 𝑆
∈ 𝑆) |
|
Theorem | 2dom 6771* |
A set that dominates ordinal 2 has at least 2 different members.
(Contributed by NM, 25-Jul-2004.)
|
⊢ (2o ≼ 𝐴 → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦) |
|
Theorem | fundmen 6772 |
A function is equinumerous to its domain. Exercise 4 of [Suppes] p. 98.
(Contributed by NM, 28-Jul-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → dom 𝐹 ≈ 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | fundmeng 6773 |
A function is equinumerous to its domain. Exercise 4 of [Suppes] p. 98.
(Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ Fun 𝐹) → dom 𝐹 ≈ 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | cnven 6774 |
A relational set is equinumerous to its converse. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 28-Dec-2014.)
|
⊢ ((Rel 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) → 𝐴 ≈ ◡𝐴) |
|
Theorem | cnvct 6775 |
If a set is dominated by ω, so is its converse.
(Contributed by
Thierry Arnoux, 29-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ ω → ◡𝐴 ≼ ω) |
|
Theorem | fndmeng 6776 |
A function is equinumerate to its domain. (Contributed by Paul Chapman,
22-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | mapsnen 6777 |
Set exponentiation to a singleton exponent is equinumerous to its base.
Exercise 4.43 of [Mendelson] p. 255.
(Contributed by NM, 17-Dec-2003.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑𝑚 {𝐵}) ≈ 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | map1 6778 |
Set exponentiation: ordinal 1 to any set is equinumerous to ordinal 1.
Exercise 4.42(b) of [Mendelson] p.
255. (Contributed by NM,
17-Dec-2003.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (1o
↑𝑚 𝐴) ≈ 1o) |
|
Theorem | en2sn 6779 |
Two singletons are equinumerous. (Contributed by NM, 9-Nov-2003.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → {𝐴} ≈ {𝐵}) |
|
Theorem | snfig 6780 |
A singleton is finite. For the proper class case, see snprc 3641.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 13-Apr-2020.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝐴} ∈ Fin) |
|
Theorem | fiprc 6781 |
The class of finite sets is a proper class. (Contributed by Jeff
Hankins, 3-Oct-2008.)
|
⊢ Fin ∉ V |
|
Theorem | unen 6782 |
Equinumerosity of union of disjoint sets. Theorem 4 of [Suppes] p. 92.
(Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1998.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ≈ 𝐷) ∧ ((𝐴 ∩ 𝐶) = ∅ ∧ (𝐵 ∩ 𝐷) = ∅)) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐶) ≈ (𝐵 ∪ 𝐷)) |
|
Theorem | enpr2d 6783 |
A pair with distinct elements is equinumerous to ordinal two.
(Contributed by Rohan Ridenour, 3-Aug-2023.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {𝐴, 𝐵} ≈ 2o) |
|
Theorem | ssct 6784 |
A subset of a set dominated by ω is dominated by
ω.
(Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 31-Jan-2017.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ ω) → 𝐴 ≼ ω) |
|
Theorem | 1domsn 6785 |
A singleton (whether of a set or a proper class) is dominated by one.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 1-Mar-2022.)
|
⊢ {𝐴} ≼ 1o |
|
Theorem | enm 6786* |
A set equinumerous to an inhabited set is inhabited. (Contributed by
Jim Kingdon, 19-May-2020.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ ∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → ∃𝑦 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | xpsnen 6787 |
A set is equinumerous to its Cartesian product with a singleton.
Proposition 4.22(c) of [Mendelson] p.
254. (Contributed by NM,
4-Jan-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 × {𝐵}) ≈ 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | xpsneng 6788 |
A set is equinumerous to its Cartesian product with a singleton.
Proposition 4.22(c) of [Mendelson] p.
254. (Contributed by NM,
22-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 × {𝐵}) ≈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | xp1en 6789 |
One times a cardinal number. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised
by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 × 1o) ≈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | endisj 6790* |
Any two sets are equinumerous to disjoint sets. Exercise 4.39 of
[Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed by
NM, 16-Apr-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑥∃𝑦((𝑥 ≈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ≈ 𝐵) ∧ (𝑥 ∩ 𝑦) = ∅) |
|
Theorem | xpcomf1o 6791* |
The canonical bijection from (𝐴 × 𝐵) to (𝐵 × 𝐴).
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Apr-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ↦ ∪
◡{𝑥}) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:(𝐴 × 𝐵)–1-1-onto→(𝐵 × 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | xpcomco 6792* |
Composition with the bijection of xpcomf1o 6791 swaps the arguments to a
mapping. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-May-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ↦ ∪
◡{𝑥})
& ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵, 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∘ 𝐹) = (𝑧 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | xpcomen 6793 |
Commutative law for equinumerosity of Cartesian product. Proposition
4.22(d) of [Mendelson] p. 254.
(Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-2004.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≈ (𝐵 × 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | xpcomeng 6794 |
Commutative law for equinumerosity of Cartesian product. Proposition
4.22(d) of [Mendelson] p. 254.
(Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-2006.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≈ (𝐵 × 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | xpsnen2g 6795 |
A set is equinumerous to its Cartesian product with a singleton on the
left. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → ({𝐴} × 𝐵) ≈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | xpassen 6796 |
Associative law for equinumerosity of Cartesian product. Proposition
4.22(e) of [Mendelson] p. 254.
(Contributed by NM, 22-Jan-2004.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ≈ (𝐴 × (𝐵 × 𝐶)) |
|
Theorem | xpdom2 6797 |
Dominance law for Cartesian product. Proposition 10.33(2) of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 92.
(Contributed by NM, 24-Jul-2004.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 → (𝐶 × 𝐴) ≼ (𝐶 × 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | xpdom2g 6798 |
Dominance law for Cartesian product. Theorem 6L(c) of [Enderton]
p. 149. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) → (𝐶 × 𝐴) ≼ (𝐶 × 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | xpdom1g 6799 |
Dominance law for Cartesian product. Theorem 6L(c) of [Enderton]
p. 149. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵) → (𝐴 × 𝐶) ≼ (𝐵 × 𝐶)) |
|
Theorem | xpdom3m 6800* |
A set is dominated by its Cartesian product with an inhabited set.
Exercise 6 of [Suppes] p. 98.
(Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
15-Apr-2020.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ ∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐴 ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) |