Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 6101-6200 *Has distinct variable
group(s)
Type | Label | Description |
Statement |
|
Theorem | abrexex2 6101* |
Existence of an existentially restricted class abstraction. 𝜑 is
normally has free-variable parameters 𝑥 and 𝑦. See
also
abrexex 6094. (Contributed by NM, 12-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑} ∈ V |
|
Theorem | abexssex 6102* |
Existence of a class abstraction with an existentially quantified
expression. Both 𝑥 and 𝑦 can be free in 𝜑.
(Contributed
by NM, 29-Jul-2006.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑)} ∈ V |
|
Theorem | abexex 6103* |
A condition where a class builder continues to exist after its wff is
existentially quantified. (Contributed by NM, 4-Mar-2007.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴)
& ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑} ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑥𝜑} ∈ V |
|
Theorem | oprabexd 6104* |
Existence of an operator abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen,
2-Sep-2009.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵)) → ∃*𝑧𝜓)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 = {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) ∧ 𝜓)}) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | oprabex 6105* |
Existence of an operation class abstraction. (Contributed by NM,
19-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → ∃*𝑧𝜑)
& ⊢ 𝐹 = {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) ∧ 𝜑)} ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V |
|
Theorem | oprabex3 6106* |
Existence of an operation class abstraction (special case).
(Contributed by NM, 19-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐻 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 = {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝐻 × 𝐻) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐻 × 𝐻)) ∧ ∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢∃𝑓((𝑥 = 〈𝑤, 𝑣〉 ∧ 𝑦 = 〈𝑢, 𝑓〉) ∧ 𝑧 = 𝑅))} ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V |
|
Theorem | oprabrexex2 6107* |
Existence of an existentially restricted operation abstraction.
(Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 11-Jun-2010.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢
{〈〈𝑥,
𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝜑} ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑} ∈ V |
|
Theorem | ab2rexex 6108* |
Existence of a class abstraction of existentially restricted sets.
Variables 𝑥 and 𝑦 are normally
free-variable parameters in the
class expression substituted for 𝐶, which can be thought of as
𝐶(𝑥, 𝑦). See comments for abrexex 6094. (Contributed by NM,
20-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ {𝑧 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝑧 = 𝐶} ∈ V |
|
Theorem | ab2rexex2 6109* |
Existence of an existentially restricted class abstraction. 𝜑
normally has free-variable parameters 𝑥, 𝑦, and 𝑧.
Compare abrexex2 6101. (Contributed by NM, 20-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ {𝑧 ∣ 𝜑} ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ {𝑧 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑} ∈ V |
|
Theorem | xpexgALT 6110 |
The cross product of two sets is a set. Proposition 6.2 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 23. This
version is proven using Replacement; see
xpexg 4723 for a version that uses the Power Set axiom
instead.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-May-2013.)
(Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | offval3 6111* |
General value of (𝐹 ∘𝑓 𝑅𝐺) with no assumptions on
functionality
of 𝐹 and 𝐺. (Contributed by Stefan
O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐹 ∘𝑓 𝑅𝐺) = (𝑥 ∈ (dom 𝐹 ∩ dom 𝐺) ↦ ((𝐹‘𝑥)𝑅(𝐺‘𝑥)))) |
|
Theorem | offres 6112 |
Pointwise combination commutes with restriction. (Contributed by Stefan
O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ 𝑊) → ((𝐹 ∘𝑓 𝑅𝐺) ↾ 𝐷) = ((𝐹 ↾ 𝐷) ∘𝑓 𝑅(𝐺 ↾ 𝐷))) |
|
Theorem | ofmres 6113* |
Equivalent expressions for a restriction of the function operation map.
Unlike ∘𝑓 𝑅 which is a proper class, ( ∘𝑓 𝑅 ↾ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) can
be a set by ofmresex 6114, allowing it to be used as a function or
structure argument. By ofmresval 6070, the restricted operation map
values are the same as the original values, allowing theorems for
∘𝑓 𝑅 to be reused. (Contributed by NM,
20-Oct-2014.)
|
⊢ ( ∘𝑓 𝑅 ↾ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) = (𝑓 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑔 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝑓 ∘𝑓 𝑅𝑔)) |
|
Theorem | ofmresex 6114 |
Existence of a restriction of the function operation map. (Contributed
by NM, 20-Oct-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ( ∘𝑓 𝑅 ↾ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) ∈ V) |
|
2.6.15 First and second members of an ordered
pair
|
|
Syntax | c1st 6115 |
Extend the definition of a class to include the first member an ordered
pair function.
|
class 1st |
|
Syntax | c2nd 6116 |
Extend the definition of a class to include the second member an ordered
pair function.
|
class 2nd |
|
Definition | df-1st 6117 |
Define a function that extracts the first member, or abscissa, of an
ordered pair. Theorem op1st 6123 proves that it does this. For example,
(1st ‘〈 3 , 4 〉) = 3 . Equivalent to Definition 5.13 (i) of
[Monk1] p. 52 (compare op1sta 5090 and op1stb 4461). The notation is the same
as Monk's. (Contributed by NM, 9-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ 1st = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ ∪ dom {𝑥}) |
|
Definition | df-2nd 6118 |
Define a function that extracts the second member, or ordinate, of an
ordered pair. Theorem op2nd 6124 proves that it does this. For example,
(2nd ‘〈 3 , 4 〉) = 4 . Equivalent to Definition 5.13 (ii)
of [Monk1] p. 52 (compare op2nda 5093 and op2ndb 5092). The notation is the
same as Monk's. (Contributed by NM, 9-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ 2nd = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ ∪ ran {𝑥}) |
|
Theorem | 1stvalg 6119 |
The value of the function that extracts the first member of an ordered
pair. (Contributed by NM, 9-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ V → (1st
‘𝐴) = ∪ dom {𝐴}) |
|
Theorem | 2ndvalg 6120 |
The value of the function that extracts the second member of an ordered
pair. (Contributed by NM, 9-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ V → (2nd
‘𝐴) = ∪ ran {𝐴}) |
|
Theorem | 1st0 6121 |
The value of the first-member function at the empty set. (Contributed by
NM, 23-Apr-2007.)
|
⊢ (1st ‘∅) =
∅ |
|
Theorem | 2nd0 6122 |
The value of the second-member function at the empty set. (Contributed by
NM, 23-Apr-2007.)
|
⊢ (2nd ‘∅) =
∅ |
|
Theorem | op1st 6123 |
Extract the first member of an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM,
5-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (1st
‘〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) = 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | op2nd 6124 |
Extract the second member of an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM,
5-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (2nd
‘〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) = 𝐵 |
|
Theorem | op1std 6125 |
Extract the first member of an ordered pair. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 = 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 → (1st ‘𝐶) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | op2ndd 6126 |
Extract the second member of an ordered pair. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 = 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 → (2nd ‘𝐶) = 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | op1stg 6127 |
Extract the first member of an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM,
19-Jul-2005.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (1st ‘〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | op2ndg 6128 |
Extract the second member of an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM,
19-Jul-2005.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (2nd ‘〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) = 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | ot1stg 6129 |
Extract the first member of an ordered triple. (Due to infrequent
usage, it isn't worthwhile at this point to define special extractors
for triples, so we reuse the ordered pair extractors for ot1stg 6129,
ot2ndg 6130, ot3rdgg 6131.) (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-2015.) (Revised
by
Mario Carneiro, 2-May-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (1st
‘(1st ‘〈𝐴, 𝐵, 𝐶〉)) = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | ot2ndg 6130 |
Extract the second member of an ordered triple. (See ot1stg 6129 comment.)
(Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
2-May-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (2nd
‘(1st ‘〈𝐴, 𝐵, 𝐶〉)) = 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | ot3rdgg 6131 |
Extract the third member of an ordered triple. (See ot1stg 6129 comment.)
(Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (2nd ‘〈𝐴, 𝐵, 𝐶〉) = 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | 1stval2 6132 |
Alternate value of the function that extracts the first member of an
ordered pair. Definition 5.13 (i) of [Monk1] p. 52. (Contributed by
NM, 18-Aug-2006.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (V × V) →
(1st ‘𝐴)
= ∩ ∩ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | 2ndval2 6133 |
Alternate value of the function that extracts the second member of an
ordered pair. Definition 5.13 (ii) of [Monk1] p. 52. (Contributed by
NM, 18-Aug-2006.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (V × V) →
(2nd ‘𝐴)
= ∩ ∩ ∩ ◡{𝐴}) |
|
Theorem | fo1st 6134 |
The 1st function maps the universe onto the
universe. (Contributed
by NM, 14-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ 1st :V–onto→V |
|
Theorem | fo2nd 6135 |
The 2nd function maps the universe onto the
universe. (Contributed
by NM, 14-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ 2nd :V–onto→V |
|
Theorem | f1stres 6136 |
Mapping of a restriction of the 1st (first
member of an ordered
pair) function. (Contributed by NM, 11-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario
Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (1st ↾ (𝐴 × 𝐵)):(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐴 |
|
Theorem | f2ndres 6137 |
Mapping of a restriction of the 2nd (second
member of an ordered
pair) function. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-2006.) (Revised by Mario
Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (2nd ↾ (𝐴 × 𝐵)):(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐵 |
|
Theorem | fo1stresm 6138* |
Onto mapping of a restriction of the 1st
(first member of an ordered
pair) function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jan-2019.)
|
⊢ (∃𝑦 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 → (1st ↾ (𝐴 × 𝐵)):(𝐴 × 𝐵)–onto→𝐴) |
|
Theorem | fo2ndresm 6139* |
Onto mapping of a restriction of the 2nd
(second member of an
ordered pair) function. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Jan-2019.)
|
⊢ (∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → (2nd ↾ (𝐴 × 𝐵)):(𝐴 × 𝐵)–onto→𝐵) |
|
Theorem | 1stcof 6140 |
Composition of the first member function with another function.
(Contributed by NM, 12-Oct-2007.)
|
⊢ (𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝐵 × 𝐶) → (1st ∘ 𝐹):𝐴⟶𝐵) |
|
Theorem | 2ndcof 6141 |
Composition of the second member function with another function.
(Contributed by FL, 15-Oct-2012.)
|
⊢ (𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝐵 × 𝐶) → (2nd ∘ 𝐹):𝐴⟶𝐶) |
|
Theorem | xp1st 6142 |
Location of the first element of a Cartesian product. (Contributed by
Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) → (1st ‘𝐴) ∈ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | xp2nd 6143 |
Location of the second element of a Cartesian product. (Contributed by
Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) → (2nd ‘𝐴) ∈ 𝐶) |
|
Theorem | 1stexg 6144 |
Existence of the first member of a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
26-Jan-2019.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (1st ‘𝐴) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | 2ndexg 6145 |
Existence of the first member of a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
26-Jan-2019.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (2nd ‘𝐴) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | elxp6 6146 |
Membership in a cross product. This version requires no quantifiers or
dummy variables. See also elxp4 5096. (Contributed by NM, 9-Oct-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) ↔ (𝐴 = 〈(1st ‘𝐴), (2nd ‘𝐴)〉 ∧ ((1st
‘𝐴) ∈ 𝐵 ∧ (2nd
‘𝐴) ∈ 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | elxp7 6147 |
Membership in a cross product. This version requires no quantifiers or
dummy variables. See also elxp4 5096. (Contributed by NM, 19-Aug-2006.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) ↔ (𝐴 ∈ (V × V) ∧
((1st ‘𝐴)
∈ 𝐵 ∧
(2nd ‘𝐴)
∈ 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | oprssdmm 6148* |
Domain of closure of an operation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
23-Oct-2023.)
|
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆) → ∃𝑣 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑥𝐹𝑦) ∈ 𝑆)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → Rel 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑆 × 𝑆) ⊆ dom 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | eqopi 6149 |
Equality with an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM, 15-Dec-2008.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 23-Feb-2014.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝑉 × 𝑊) ∧ ((1st ‘𝐴) = 𝐵 ∧ (2nd ‘𝐴) = 𝐶)) → 𝐴 = 〈𝐵, 𝐶〉) |
|
Theorem | xp2 6150* |
Representation of cross product based on ordered pair component
functions. (Contributed by NM, 16-Sep-2006.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 × 𝐵) = {𝑥 ∈ (V × V) ∣
((1st ‘𝑥)
∈ 𝐴 ∧
(2nd ‘𝑥)
∈ 𝐵)} |
|
Theorem | unielxp 6151 |
The membership relation for a cross product is inherited by union.
(Contributed by NM, 16-Sep-2006.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) → ∪ 𝐴 ∈ ∪ (𝐵
× 𝐶)) |
|
Theorem | 1st2nd2 6152 |
Reconstruction of a member of a cross product in terms of its ordered pair
components. (Contributed by NM, 20-Oct-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) → 𝐴 = 〈(1st ‘𝐴), (2nd ‘𝐴)〉) |
|
Theorem | xpopth 6153 |
An ordered pair theorem for members of cross products. (Contributed by
NM, 20-Jun-2007.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝐶 × 𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝑅 × 𝑆)) → (((1st ‘𝐴) = (1st
‘𝐵) ∧
(2nd ‘𝐴)
= (2nd ‘𝐵)) ↔ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | eqop 6154 |
Two ways to express equality with an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM,
3-Sep-2007.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝑉 × 𝑊) → (𝐴 = 〈𝐵, 𝐶〉 ↔ ((1st ‘𝐴) = 𝐵 ∧ (2nd ‘𝐴) = 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | eqop2 6155 |
Two ways to express equality with an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM,
25-Feb-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 = 〈𝐵, 𝐶〉 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ (V × V) ∧
((1st ‘𝐴)
= 𝐵 ∧ (2nd
‘𝐴) = 𝐶))) |
|
Theorem | op1steq 6156* |
Two ways of expressing that an element is the first member of an ordered
pair. (Contributed by NM, 22-Sep-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
23-Feb-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝑉 × 𝑊) → ((1st ‘𝐴) = 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥 𝐴 = 〈𝐵, 𝑥〉)) |
|
Theorem | 2nd1st 6157 |
Swap the members of an ordered pair. (Contributed by NM, 31-Dec-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 × 𝐶) → ∪ ◡{𝐴} = 〈(2nd ‘𝐴), (1st ‘𝐴)〉) |
|
Theorem | 1st2nd 6158 |
Reconstruction of a member of a relation in terms of its ordered pair
components. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-2006.)
|
⊢ ((Rel 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐴 = 〈(1st ‘𝐴), (2nd ‘𝐴)〉) |
|
Theorem | 1stdm 6159 |
The first ordered pair component of a member of a relation belongs to the
domain of the relation. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-2006.)
|
⊢ ((Rel 𝑅 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑅) → (1st ‘𝐴) ∈ dom 𝑅) |
|
Theorem | 2ndrn 6160 |
The second ordered pair component of a member of a relation belongs to the
range of the relation. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-2006.)
|
⊢ ((Rel 𝑅 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑅) → (2nd ‘𝐴) ∈ ran 𝑅) |
|
Theorem | 1st2ndbr 6161 |
Express an element of a relation as a relationship between first and
second components. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2016.)
|
⊢ ((Rel 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) → (1st ‘𝐴)𝐵(2nd ‘𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | releldm2 6162* |
Two ways of expressing membership in the domain of a relation.
(Contributed by NM, 22-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (Rel 𝐴 → (𝐵 ∈ dom 𝐴 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (1st ‘𝑥) = 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | reldm 6163* |
An expression for the domain of a relation. (Contributed by NM,
22-Sep-2013.)
|
⊢ (Rel 𝐴 → dom 𝐴 = ran (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (1st ‘𝑥))) |
|
Theorem | sbcopeq1a 6164 |
Equality theorem for substitution of a class for an ordered pair (analog
of sbceq1a 2964 that avoids the existential quantifiers of copsexg 4227).
(Contributed by NM, 19-Aug-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 = 〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 → ([(1st
‘𝐴) / 𝑥][(2nd
‘𝐴) / 𝑦]𝜑 ↔ 𝜑)) |
|
Theorem | csbopeq1a 6165 |
Equality theorem for substitution of a class 𝐴 for an ordered pair
〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 in 𝐵 (analog of csbeq1a 3058). (Contributed by NM,
19-Aug-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 = 〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 → ⦋(1st
‘𝐴) / 𝑥⦌⦋(2nd
‘𝐴) / 𝑦⦌𝐵 = 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | dfopab2 6166* |
A way to define an ordered-pair class abstraction without using
existential quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-2006.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑧 ∈ (V × V) ∣
[(1st ‘𝑧) / 𝑥][(2nd ‘𝑧) / 𝑦]𝜑} |
|
Theorem | dfoprab3s 6167* |
A way to define an operation class abstraction without using existential
quantifiers. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-2006.) (Revised by Mario
Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑤, 𝑧〉 ∣ (𝑤 ∈ (V × V) ∧
[(1st ‘𝑤) / 𝑥][(2nd ‘𝑤) / 𝑦]𝜑)} |
|
Theorem | dfoprab3 6168* |
Operation class abstraction expressed without existential quantifiers.
(Contributed by NM, 16-Dec-2008.)
|
⊢ (𝑤 = 〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑤, 𝑧〉 ∣ (𝑤 ∈ (V × V) ∧ 𝜑)} = {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝜓} |
|
Theorem | dfoprab4 6169* |
Operation class abstraction expressed without existential quantifiers.
(Contributed by NM, 3-Sep-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝑤 = 〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑤, 𝑧〉 ∣ (𝑤 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝜑)} = {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) ∧ 𝜓)} |
|
Theorem | dfoprab4f 6170* |
Operation class abstraction expressed without existential quantifiers.
(Unnecessary distinct variable restrictions were removed by David
Abernethy, 19-Jun-2012.) (Contributed by NM, 20-Dec-2008.) (Revised by
Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑
& ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑
& ⊢ (𝑤 = 〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑤, 𝑧〉 ∣ (𝑤 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝜑)} = {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) ∧ 𝜓)} |
|
Theorem | dfxp3 6171* |
Define the cross product of three classes. Compare df-xp 4615.
(Contributed by FL, 6-Nov-2013.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro,
3-Nov-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) = {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐶)} |
|
Theorem | elopabi 6172* |
A consequence of membership in an ordered-pair class abstraction, using
ordered pair extractors. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-2006.)
|
⊢ (𝑥 = (1st ‘𝐴) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = (2nd ‘𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} → 𝜒) |
|
Theorem | eloprabi 6173* |
A consequence of membership in an operation class abstraction, using
ordered pair extractors. (Contributed by NM, 6-Nov-2006.) (Revised by
David Abernethy, 19-Jun-2012.)
|
⊢ (𝑥 = (1st ‘(1st
‘𝐴)) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = (2nd
‘(1st ‘𝐴)) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = (2nd ‘𝐴) → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝜑} → 𝜃) |
|
Theorem | mpomptsx 6174* |
Express a two-argument function as a one-argument function, or
vice-versa. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) = (𝑧 ∈ ∪
𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵) ↦ ⦋(1st
‘𝑧) / 𝑥⦌⦋(2nd
‘𝑧) / 𝑦⦌𝐶) |
|
Theorem | mpompts 6175* |
Express a two-argument function as a one-argument function, or
vice-versa. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) = (𝑧 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ↦ ⦋(1st
‘𝑧) / 𝑥⦌⦋(2nd
‘𝑧) / 𝑦⦌𝐶) |
|
Theorem | dmmpossx 6176* |
The domain of a mapping is a subset of its base class. (Contributed by
Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ dom 𝐹 ⊆ ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | fmpox 6177* |
Functionality, domain and codomain of a class given by the maps-to
notation, where 𝐵(𝑥) is not constant but depends on 𝑥.
(Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷 ↔ 𝐹:∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵)⟶𝐷) |
|
Theorem | fmpo 6178* |
Functionality, domain and range of a class given by the maps-to
notation. (Contributed by FL, 17-May-2010.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷 ↔ 𝐹:(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐷) |
|
Theorem | fnmpo 6179* |
Functionality and domain of a class given by the maps-to notation.
(Contributed by FL, 17-May-2010.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐹 Fn (𝐴 × 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | mpofvex 6180* |
Sufficient condition for an operation maps-to notation to be set-like.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑥∀𝑦 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑅 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝑆 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝑅𝐹𝑆) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | fnmpoi 6181* |
Functionality and domain of a class given by the maps-to notation.
(Contributed by FL, 17-May-2010.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶)
& ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹 Fn (𝐴 × 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | dmmpo 6182* |
Domain of a class given by the maps-to notation. (Contributed by FL,
17-May-2010.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶)
& ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ dom 𝐹 = (𝐴 × 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | mpofvexi 6183* |
Sufficient condition for an operation maps-to notation to be set-like.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jul-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶)
& ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑅 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅𝐹𝑆) ∈ V |
|
Theorem | ovmpoelrn 6184* |
An operation's value belongs to its range. (Contributed by AV,
27-Jan-2020.)
|
⊢ 𝑂 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∈ 𝑀 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑋𝑂𝑌) ∈ 𝑀) |
|
Theorem | dmmpoga 6185* |
Domain of an operation given by the maps-to notation, closed form of
dmmpo 6182. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens,
10-Feb-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 → dom 𝐹 = (𝐴 × 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | dmmpog 6186* |
Domain of an operation given by the maps-to notation, closed form of
dmmpo 6182. Caution: This theorem is only valid in the
very special case
where the value of the mapping is a constant! (Contributed by Alexander
van der Vekens, 1-Jun-2017.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Feb-2019.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 → dom 𝐹 = (𝐴 × 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | mpoexxg 6187* |
Existence of an operation class abstraction (version for dependent
domains). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) → 𝐹 ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | mpoexg 6188* |
Existence of an operation class abstraction (special case).
(Contributed by FL, 17-May-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
1-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑅 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) → 𝐹 ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | mpoexga 6189* |
If the domain of an operation given by maps-to notation is a set, the
operation is a set. (Contributed by NM, 12-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | mpoexw 6190* |
Weak version of mpoex 6191 that holds without ax-coll 4102. If the domain
and codomain of an operation given by maps-to notation are sets, the
operation is a set. (Contributed by Rohan Ridenour, 14-Aug-2023.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ V |
|
Theorem | mpoex 6191* |
If the domain of an operation given by maps-to notation is a set, the
operation is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Dec-2013.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ∈ V |
|
Theorem | fnmpoovd 6192* |
A function with a Cartesian product as domain is a mapping with two
arguments defined by its operation values. (Contributed by AV,
20-Feb-2019.) (Revised by AV, 3-Jul-2022.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑀 Fn (𝐴 × 𝐵)) & ⊢ ((𝑖 = 𝑎 ∧ 𝑗 = 𝑏) → 𝐷 = 𝐶)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑗 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐷 ∈ 𝑈)
& ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑀 = (𝑎 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) ↔ ∀𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑗 ∈ 𝐵 (𝑖𝑀𝑗) = 𝐷)) |
|
Theorem | fmpoco 6193* |
Composition of two functions. Variation of fmptco 5660 when the second
function has two arguments. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro,
8-Feb-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵)) → 𝑅 ∈ 𝐶)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝑅)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺 = (𝑧 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝑅 → 𝑆 = 𝑇) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐺 ∘ 𝐹) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝑇)) |
|
Theorem | oprabco 6194* |
Composition of a function with an operator abstraction. (Contributed by
Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro,
26-Sep-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷)
& ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶)
& ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝐻‘𝐶)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐻 Fn 𝐷 → 𝐺 = (𝐻 ∘ 𝐹)) |
|
Theorem | oprab2co 6195* |
Composition of operator abstractions. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen,
2-Sep-2009.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 23-Apr-2013.)
|
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝑅)
& ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)
& ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 〈𝐶, 𝐷〉) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝐶𝑀𝐷)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑀 Fn (𝑅 × 𝑆) → 𝐺 = (𝑀 ∘ 𝐹)) |
|
Theorem | df1st2 6196* |
An alternate possible definition of the 1st
function. (Contributed
by NM, 14-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝑧 = 𝑥} = (1st ↾ (V ×
V)) |
|
Theorem | df2nd2 6197* |
An alternate possible definition of the 2nd
function. (Contributed
by NM, 10-Aug-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝑧 = 𝑦} = (2nd ↾ (V ×
V)) |
|
Theorem | 1stconst 6198 |
The mapping of a restriction of the 1st
function to a constant
function. (Contributed by NM, 14-Dec-2008.)
|
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → (1st ↾ (𝐴 × {𝐵})):(𝐴 × {𝐵})–1-1-onto→𝐴) |
|
Theorem | 2ndconst 6199 |
The mapping of a restriction of the 2nd
function to a converse
constant function. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-2008.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (2nd ↾ ({𝐴} × 𝐵)):({𝐴} × 𝐵)–1-1-onto→𝐵) |
|
Theorem | dfmpo 6200* |
Alternate definition for the maps-to notation df-mpo 5856 (although it
requires that 𝐶 be a set). (Contributed by NM,
19-Dec-2008.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) = ∪
𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∪ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 {〈〈𝑥, 𝑦〉, 𝐶〉} |