![]() |
Intuitionistic Logic Explorer Theorem List (p. 53 of 157) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > ILE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | dfdm2 5201 | Alternate definition of domain df-dm 4670 that doesn't require dummy variables. (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-2010.) |
⊢ dom 𝐴 = ∪ ∪ (◡𝐴 ∘ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | unixpm 5202* | The double class union of an inhabited cross product is the union of its members. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) → ∪ ∪ (𝐴 × 𝐵) = (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | unixp0im 5203 | The union of an empty cross product is empty. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) = ∅ → ∪ (𝐴 × 𝐵) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | cnvexg 5204 | The converse of a set is a set. Corollary 6.8(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 26. (Contributed by NM, 17-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ◡𝐴 ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | cnvex 5205 | The converse of a set is a set. Corollary 6.8(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 26. (Contributed by NM, 19-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ◡𝐴 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | relcnvexb 5206 | A relation is a set iff its converse is a set. (Contributed by FL, 3-Mar-2007.) |
⊢ (Rel 𝑅 → (𝑅 ∈ V ↔ ◡𝑅 ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | ressn 5207 | Restriction of a class to a singleton. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↾ {𝐵}) = ({𝐵} × (𝐴 “ {𝐵})) | ||
Theorem | cnviinm 5208* | The converse of an intersection is the intersection of the converse. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 → ◡∩ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = ∩ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ◡𝐵) | ||
Theorem | cnvpom 5209* | The converse of a partial order relation is a partial order relation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Jun-2005.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝑅 Po 𝐴 ↔ ◡𝑅 Po 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | cnvsom 5210* | The converse of a strict order relation is a strict order relation. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 19-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝑅 Or 𝐴 ↔ ◡𝑅 Or 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | coexg 5211 | The composition of two sets is a set. (Contributed by NM, 19-Mar-1998.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ∘ 𝐵) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | coex 5212 | The composition of two sets is a set. (Contributed by NM, 15-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∘ 𝐵) ∈ V | ||
Theorem | xpcom 5213* | Composition of two cross products. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 20-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 → ((𝐵 × 𝐶) ∘ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) = (𝐴 × 𝐶)) | ||
Syntax | cio 5214 | Extend class notation with Russell's definition description binder (inverted iota). |
class (℩𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | iotajust 5215* | Soundness justification theorem for df-iota 5216. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 29-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ ∪ {𝑦 ∣ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑦}} = ∪ {𝑧 ∣ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑧}} | ||
Definition | df-iota 5216* |
Define Russell's definition description binder, which can be read as
"the unique 𝑥 such that 𝜑," where 𝜑
ordinarily contains
𝑥 as a free variable. Our definition
is meaningful only when there
is exactly one 𝑥 such that 𝜑 is true (see iotaval 5227);
otherwise, it evaluates to the empty set (see iotanul 5231). Russell used
the inverted iota symbol ℩ to represent
the binder.
Sometimes proofs need to expand an iota-based definition. That is, given "X = the x for which ... x ... x ..." holds, the proof needs to get to "... X ... X ...". A general strategy to do this is to use iotacl 5240 (for unbounded iota). This can be easier than applying a version that applies an explicit substitution, because substituting an iota into its own property always has a bound variable clash which must be first renamed or else guarded with NF. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 30-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = ∪ {𝑦 ∣ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑦}} | ||
Theorem | dfiota2 5217* | Alternate definition for descriptions. Definition 8.18 in [Quine] p. 56. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 30-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = ∪ {𝑦 ∣ ∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦)} | ||
Theorem | nfiota1 5218 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the ℩ class. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(℩𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfiotadw 5219* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the ℩ class. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(℩𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfiotaw 5220* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the ℩ class. (Contributed by NM, 23-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(℩𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | cbviota 5221 | Change bound variables in a description binder. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 1-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = (℩𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | cbviotav 5222* | Change bound variables in a description binder. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 1-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = (℩𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | sb8iota 5223 | Variable substitution in description binder. Compare sb8eu 2055. (Contributed by NM, 18-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = (℩𝑦[𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | iotaeq 5224 | Equality theorem for descriptions. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 30-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (℩𝑥𝜑) = (℩𝑦𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | iotabi 5225 | Equivalence theorem for descriptions. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 30-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (℩𝑥𝜑) = (℩𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | uniabio 5226* | Part of Theorem 8.17 in [Quine] p. 56. This theorem serves as a lemma for the fundamental property of iota. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦) → ∪ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | iotaval 5227* | Theorem 8.19 in [Quine] p. 57. This theorem is the fundamental property of iota. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦) → (℩𝑥𝜑) = 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | iotauni 5228 | Equivalence between two different forms of ℩. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 12-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 → (℩𝑥𝜑) = ∪ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑}) | ||
Theorem | iotaint 5229 | Equivalence between two different forms of ℩. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 → (℩𝑥𝜑) = ∩ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑}) | ||
Theorem | iota1 5230 | Property of iota. (Contributed by NM, 23-Aug-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 → (𝜑 ↔ (℩𝑥𝜑) = 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | iotanul 5231 | Theorem 8.22 in [Quine] p. 57. This theorem is the result if there isn't exactly one 𝑥 that satisfies 𝜑. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (¬ ∃!𝑥𝜑 → (℩𝑥𝜑) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | euiotaex 5232 | Theorem 8.23 in [Quine] p. 58, with existential uniqueness condition added. This theorem proves the existence of the ℩ class under our definition. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 21-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 → (℩𝑥𝜑) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | iotass 5233* | Value of iota based on a proposition which holds only for values which are subsets of a given class. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro and Jim Kingdon, 21-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴) → (℩𝑥𝜑) ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | iotaexab 5234 | Existence of the ℩ class when all the possible values are contained in a set. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-May-2025.) |
⊢ ({𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ∈ 𝑉 → (℩𝑥𝜑) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | iota4 5235 | Theorem *14.22 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 190. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 12-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 → [(℩𝑥𝜑) / 𝑥]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | iota4an 5236 | Theorem *14.23 in [WhiteheadRussell] p. 191. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 12-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → [(℩𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) / 𝑥]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | iota5 5237* | A method for computing iota. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝐴)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) → (℩𝑥𝜓) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | iotabidv 5238* | Formula-building deduction for iota. (Contributed by NM, 20-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (℩𝑥𝜓) = (℩𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | iotabii 5239 | Formula-building deduction for iota. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Oct-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = (℩𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | iotacl 5240 |
Membership law for descriptions.
This can useful for expanding an unbounded iota-based definition (see df-iota 5216). (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 1-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 → (℩𝑥𝜑) ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑}) | ||
Theorem | iota2df 5241 | A condition that allows us to represent "the unique element such that 𝜑 " with a class expression 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 30-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃!𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ (℩𝑥𝜓) = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | iota2d 5242* | A condition that allows us to represent "the unique element such that 𝜑 " with a class expression 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 30-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃!𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ (℩𝑥𝜓) = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | eliota 5243* | An element of an iota expression. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (℩𝑥𝜑) ↔ ∃𝑦(𝐴 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | eliotaeu 5244 | An inhabited iota expression has a unique value. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 22-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (℩𝑥𝜑) → ∃!𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | iota2 5245* | The unique element such that 𝜑. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 1-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ∃!𝑥𝜑) → (𝜓 ↔ (℩𝑥𝜑) = 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | sniota 5246 | A class abstraction with a unique member can be expressed as a singleton. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 → {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = {(℩𝑥𝜑)}) | ||
Theorem | iotam 5247* | Representation of "the unique element such that 𝜑 " with a class expression 𝐴 which is inhabited (that means that "the unique element such that 𝜑 " exists). (Contributed by AV, 30-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∃𝑤 𝑤 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 = (℩𝑥𝜑)) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | csbiotag 5248* | Class substitution within a description binder. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 6-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌(℩𝑦𝜑) = (℩𝑦[𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑)) | ||
Syntax | wfun 5249 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the function predicate. (Read: 𝐴 is a function.) |
wff Fun 𝐴 | ||
Syntax | wfn 5250 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the function predicate with a domain. (Read: 𝐴 is a function on 𝐵.) |
wff 𝐴 Fn 𝐵 | ||
Syntax | wf 5251 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the function predicate with domain and codomain. (Read: 𝐹 maps 𝐴 into 𝐵.) |
wff 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵 | ||
Syntax | wf1 5252 | Extend the definition of a wff to include one-to-one functions. (Read: 𝐹 maps 𝐴 one-to-one into 𝐵.) The notation ("1-1" above the arrow) is from Definition 6.15(5) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. |
wff 𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 | ||
Syntax | wfo 5253 | Extend the definition of a wff to include onto functions. (Read: 𝐹 maps 𝐴 onto 𝐵.) The notation ("onto" below the arrow) is from Definition 6.15(4) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. |
wff 𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵 | ||
Syntax | wf1o 5254 | Extend the definition of a wff to include one-to-one onto functions. (Read: 𝐹 maps 𝐴 one-to-one onto 𝐵.) The notation ("1-1" above the arrow and "onto" below the arrow) is from Definition 6.15(6) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. |
wff 𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵 | ||
Syntax | cfv 5255 | Extend the definition of a class to include the value of a function. (Read: The value of 𝐹 at 𝐴, or "𝐹 of 𝐴.") |
class (𝐹‘𝐴) | ||
Syntax | wiso 5256 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the isomorphism property. (Read: 𝐻 is an 𝑅, 𝑆 isomorphism of 𝐴 onto 𝐵.) |
wff 𝐻 Isom 𝑅, 𝑆 (𝐴, 𝐵) | ||
Definition | df-fun 5257 | Define predicate that determines if some class 𝐴 is a function. Definition 10.1 of [Quine] p. 65. For example, the expression Fun I is true (funi 5287). This is not the same as defining a specific function's mapping, which is typically done using the format of cmpt 4091 with the maps-to notation (see df-mpt 4093). Contrast this predicate with the predicates to determine if some class is a function with a given domain (df-fn 5258), a function with a given domain and codomain (df-f 5259), a one-to-one function (df-f1 5260), an onto function (df-fo 5261), or a one-to-one onto function (df-f1o 5262). For alternate definitions, see dffun2 5265, dffun4 5266, dffun6 5269, dffun7 5282, dffun8 5283, and dffun9 5284. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ (𝐴 ∘ ◡𝐴) ⊆ I )) | ||
Definition | df-fn 5258 | Define a function with domain. Definition 6.15(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 Fn 𝐵 ↔ (Fun 𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Definition | df-f 5259 | Define a function (mapping) with domain and codomain. Definition 6.15(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵 ↔ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ran 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵)) | ||
Definition | df-f1 5260 | Define a one-to-one function. Compare Definition 6.15(5) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. We use their notation ("1-1" above the arrow). (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 ↔ (𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵 ∧ Fun ◡𝐹)) | ||
Definition | df-fo 5261 | Define an onto function. Definition 6.15(4) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. We use their notation ("onto" under the arrow). (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵 ↔ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ran 𝐹 = 𝐵)) | ||
Definition | df-f1o 5262 | Define a one-to-one onto function. Compare Definition 6.15(6) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 27. We use their notation ("1-1" above the arrow and "onto" below the arrow). (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐹:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵 ↔ (𝐹:𝐴–1-1→𝐵 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴–onto→𝐵)) | ||
Definition | df-fv 5263* | Define the value of a function, (𝐹‘𝐴), also known as function application. For example, ( I ‘∅) = ∅. Typically, function 𝐹 is defined using maps-to notation (see df-mpt 4093), but this is not required. For example, 𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} → (𝐹‘3) = 9. We will later define two-argument functions using ordered pairs as (𝐴𝐹𝐵) = (𝐹‘〈𝐴, 𝐵〉). This particular definition is quite convenient: it can be applied to any class and evaluates to the empty set when it is not meaningful. The left apostrophe notation originated with Peano and was adopted in Definition *30.01 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 235, Definition 10.11 of [Quine] p. 68, and Definition 6.11 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 26. It means the same thing as the more familiar 𝐹(𝐴) notation for a function's value at 𝐴, i.e., "𝐹 of 𝐴," but without context-dependent notational ambiguity. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) Revised to use ℩. (Revised by Scott Fenton, 6-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐹‘𝐴) = (℩𝑥𝐴𝐹𝑥) | ||
Definition | df-isom 5264* | Define the isomorphism predicate. We read this as "𝐻 is an 𝑅, 𝑆 isomorphism of 𝐴 onto 𝐵". Normally, 𝑅 and 𝑆 are ordering relations on 𝐴 and 𝐵 respectively. Definition 6.28 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 32, whose notation is the same as ours except that 𝑅 and 𝑆 are subscripts. (Contributed by NM, 4-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝐻 Isom 𝑅, 𝑆 (𝐴, 𝐵) ↔ (𝐻:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑥𝑅𝑦 ↔ (𝐻‘𝑥)𝑆(𝐻‘𝑦)))) | ||
Theorem | dffun2 5265* | Alternate definition of a function. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1996.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧((𝑥𝐴𝑦 ∧ 𝑥𝐴𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | dffun4 5266* | Alternate definition of a function. Definition 6.4(4) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. (Contributed by NM, 29-Dec-1996.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧((〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 〈𝑥, 𝑧〉 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑦 = 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | dffun5r 5267* | A way of proving a relation is a function, analogous to mo2r 2094. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 27-May-2020.) |
⊢ ((Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∃𝑧∀𝑦(〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) → Fun 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dffun6f 5268* | Definition of function, using bound-variable hypotheses instead of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dffun6 5269* | Alternate definition of a function using "at most one" notation. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 ↔ (Rel 𝐹 ∧ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦 𝑥𝐹𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | funmo 5270* | A function has at most one value for each argument. (Contributed by NM, 24-May-1998.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → ∃*𝑦 𝐴𝐹𝑦) | ||
Theorem | dffun4f 5271* | Definition of function like dffun4 5266 but using bound-variable hypotheses instead of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 17-Mar-2019.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧((〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 〈𝑥, 𝑧〉 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑦 = 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | funrel 5272 | A function is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 → Rel 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | 0nelfun 5273 | A function does not contain the empty set. (Contributed by BJ, 26-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝑅 → ∅ ∉ 𝑅) | ||
Theorem | funss 5274 | Subclass theorem for function predicate. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (Fun 𝐵 → Fun 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | funeq 5275 | Equality theorem for function predicate. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (Fun 𝐴 ↔ Fun 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | funeqi 5276 | Equality inference for the function predicate. (Contributed by Jonathan Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ Fun 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | funeqd 5277 | Equality deduction for the function predicate. (Contributed by NM, 23-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Fun 𝐴 ↔ Fun 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | nffun 5278 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for a function. (Contributed by NM, 30-Jan-2004.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐹 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥Fun 𝐹 | ||
Theorem | sbcfung 5279 | Distribute proper substitution through the function predicate. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 23-Jul-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]Fun 𝐹 ↔ Fun ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐹)) | ||
Theorem | funeu 5280* | There is exactly one value of a function. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴𝐹𝐵) → ∃!𝑦 𝐴𝐹𝑦) | ||
Theorem | funeu2 5281* | There is exactly one value of a function. (Contributed by NM, 3-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 ∈ 𝐹) → ∃!𝑦〈𝐴, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐹) | ||
Theorem | dffun7 5282* | Alternate definition of a function. One possibility for the definition of a function in [Enderton] p. 42. (Enderton's definition is ambiguous because "there is only one" could mean either "there is at most one" or "there is exactly one". However, dffun8 5283 shows that it does not matter which meaning we pick.) (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2002.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ dom 𝐴∃*𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dffun8 5283* | Alternate definition of a function. One possibility for the definition of a function in [Enderton] p. 42. Compare dffun7 5282. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2002.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ dom 𝐴∃!𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dffun9 5284* | Alternate definition of a function. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-2007.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ dom 𝐴∃*𝑦 ∈ ran 𝐴 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | funfn 5285 | An equivalence for the function predicate. (Contributed by NM, 13-Aug-2004.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 Fn dom 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | funfnd 5286 | A function is a function over its domain. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 23-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 Fn dom 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | funi 5287 | The identity relation is a function. Part of Theorem 10.4 of [Quine] p. 65. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1998.) |
⊢ Fun I | ||
Theorem | nfunv 5288 | The universe is not a function. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 27-Jan-2004.) |
⊢ ¬ Fun V | ||
Theorem | funopg 5289 | A Kuratowski ordered pair is a function only if its components are equal. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ Fun 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | funopab 5290* | A class of ordered pairs is a function when there is at most one second member for each pair. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-1995.) |
⊢ (Fun {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | funopabeq 5291* | A class of ordered pairs of values is a function. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ Fun {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝑦 = 𝐴} | ||
Theorem | funopab4 5292* | A class of ordered pairs of values in the form used by df-mpt 4093 is a function. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ Fun {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐴)} | ||
Theorem | funmpt 5293 | A function in maps-to notation is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ Fun (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | funmpt2 5294 | Functionality of a class given by a maps-to notation. (Contributed by FL, 17-Feb-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-May-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ Fun 𝐹 | ||
Theorem | funco 5295 | The composition of two functions is a function. Exercise 29 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 25. (Contributed by NM, 26-Jan-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ Fun 𝐺) → Fun (𝐹 ∘ 𝐺)) | ||
Theorem | funres 5296 | A restriction of a function is a function. Compare Exercise 18 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 25. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → Fun (𝐹 ↾ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | funssres 5297 | The restriction of a function to the domain of a subclass equals the subclass. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐺 ⊆ 𝐹) → (𝐹 ↾ dom 𝐺) = 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | fun2ssres 5298 | Equality of restrictions of a function and a subclass. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐺 ⊆ 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ dom 𝐺) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐴) = (𝐺 ↾ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | funun 5299 | The union of functions with disjoint domains is a function. Theorem 4.6 of [Monk1] p. 43. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (((Fun 𝐹 ∧ Fun 𝐺) ∧ (dom 𝐹 ∩ dom 𝐺) = ∅) → Fun (𝐹 ∪ 𝐺)) | ||
Theorem | funcnvsn 5300 | The converse singleton of an ordered pair is a function. This is equivalent to funsn 5303 via cnvsn 5149, but stating it this way allows us to skip the sethood assumptions on 𝐴 and 𝐵. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ Fun ◡{〈𝐴, 𝐵〉} |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |