Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 5201-5300 *Has distinct variable
group(s)
Type | Label | Description |
Statement |
|
Theorem | dffun6f 5201* |
Definition of function, using bound-variable hypotheses instead of
distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.)
(Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.)
|
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴
& ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) |
|
Theorem | dffun6 5202* |
Alternate definition of a function using "at most one" notation.
(Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 ↔ (Rel 𝐹 ∧ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦 𝑥𝐹𝑦)) |
|
Theorem | funmo 5203* |
A function has at most one value for each argument. (Contributed by NM,
24-May-1998.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → ∃*𝑦 𝐴𝐹𝑦) |
|
Theorem | dffun4f 5204* |
Definition of function like dffun4 5199 but using bound-variable hypotheses
instead of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
17-Mar-2019.)
|
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴
& ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴
& ⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧((〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 〈𝑥, 𝑧〉 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑦 = 𝑧))) |
|
Theorem | funrel 5205 |
A function is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 → Rel 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | 0nelfun 5206 |
A function does not contain the empty set. (Contributed by BJ,
26-Nov-2021.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝑅 → ∅ ∉ 𝑅) |
|
Theorem | funss 5207 |
Subclass theorem for function predicate. (Contributed by NM,
16-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2014.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (Fun 𝐵 → Fun 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | funeq 5208 |
Equality theorem for function predicate. (Contributed by NM,
16-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (Fun 𝐴 ↔ Fun 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | funeqi 5209 |
Equality inference for the function predicate. (Contributed by Jonathan
Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ Fun 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | funeqd 5210 |
Equality deduction for the function predicate. (Contributed by NM,
23-Feb-2013.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (Fun 𝐴 ↔ Fun 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | nffun 5211 |
Bound-variable hypothesis builder for a function. (Contributed by NM,
30-Jan-2004.)
|
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐹 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥Fun 𝐹 |
|
Theorem | sbcfung 5212 |
Distribute proper substitution through the function predicate.
(Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 23-Jul-2017.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]Fun 𝐹 ↔ Fun ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐹)) |
|
Theorem | funeu 5213* |
There is exactly one value of a function. (Contributed by NM,
22-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴𝐹𝐵) → ∃!𝑦 𝐴𝐹𝑦) |
|
Theorem | funeu2 5214* |
There is exactly one value of a function. (Contributed by NM,
3-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉 ∈ 𝐹) → ∃!𝑦〈𝐴, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | dffun7 5215* |
Alternate definition of a function. One possibility for the definition
of a function in [Enderton] p. 42.
(Enderton's definition is ambiguous
because "there is only one" could mean either "there is
at most one" or
"there is exactly one". However, dffun8 5216 shows that it does not matter
which meaning we pick.) (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2002.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ dom 𝐴∃*𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) |
|
Theorem | dffun8 5216* |
Alternate definition of a function. One possibility for the definition
of a function in [Enderton] p. 42.
Compare dffun7 5215. (Contributed by
NM, 4-Nov-2002.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ dom 𝐴∃!𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) |
|
Theorem | dffun9 5217* |
Alternate definition of a function. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-2007.)
(Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ dom 𝐴∃*𝑦 ∈ ran 𝐴 𝑥𝐴𝑦)) |
|
Theorem | funfn 5218 |
An equivalence for the function predicate. (Contributed by NM,
13-Aug-2004.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 Fn dom 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | funfnd 5219 |
A function is a function over its domain. (Contributed by Glauco
Siliprandi, 23-Oct-2021.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 Fn dom 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | funi 5220 |
The identity relation is a function. Part of Theorem 10.4 of [Quine]
p. 65. (Contributed by NM, 30-Apr-1998.)
|
⊢ Fun I |
|
Theorem | nfunv 5221 |
The universe is not a function. (Contributed by Raph Levien,
27-Jan-2004.)
|
⊢ ¬ Fun V |
|
Theorem | funopg 5222 |
A Kuratowski ordered pair is a function only if its components are
equal. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro,
26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ Fun 〈𝐴, 𝐵〉) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | funopab 5223* |
A class of ordered pairs is a function when there is at most one second
member for each pair. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-1995.)
|
⊢ (Fun {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦𝜑) |
|
Theorem | funopabeq 5224* |
A class of ordered pairs of values is a function. (Contributed by NM,
14-Nov-1995.)
|
⊢ Fun {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝑦 = 𝐴} |
|
Theorem | funopab4 5225* |
A class of ordered pairs of values in the form used by df-mpt 4045 is a
function. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2013.)
|
⊢ Fun {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐴)} |
|
Theorem | funmpt 5226 |
A function in maps-to notation is a function. (Contributed by Mario
Carneiro, 13-Jan-2013.)
|
⊢ Fun (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | funmpt2 5227 |
Functionality of a class given by a maps-to notation. (Contributed by
FL, 17-Feb-2008.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-May-2014.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ Fun 𝐹 |
|
Theorem | funco 5228 |
The composition of two functions is a function. Exercise 29 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 25.
(Contributed by NM, 26-Jan-1997.) (Proof
shortened by Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ Fun 𝐺) → Fun (𝐹 ∘ 𝐺)) |
|
Theorem | funres 5229 |
A restriction of a function is a function. Compare Exercise 18 of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 25. (Contributed
by NM, 16-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → Fun (𝐹 ↾ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | funssres 5230 |
The restriction of a function to the domain of a subclass equals the
subclass. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐺 ⊆ 𝐹) → (𝐹 ↾ dom 𝐺) = 𝐺) |
|
Theorem | fun2ssres 5231 |
Equality of restrictions of a function and a subclass. (Contributed by
NM, 16-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐺 ⊆ 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ dom 𝐺) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐴) = (𝐺 ↾ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | funun 5232 |
The union of functions with disjoint domains is a function. Theorem 4.6
of [Monk1] p. 43. (Contributed by NM,
12-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (((Fun 𝐹 ∧ Fun 𝐺) ∧ (dom 𝐹 ∩ dom 𝐺) = ∅) → Fun (𝐹 ∪ 𝐺)) |
|
Theorem | funcnvsn 5233 |
The converse singleton of an ordered pair is a function. This is
equivalent to funsn 5236 via cnvsn 5086, but stating it this way allows us to
skip the sethood assumptions on 𝐴 and 𝐵. (Contributed by NM,
30-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ Fun ◡{〈𝐴, 𝐵〉} |
|
Theorem | funsng 5234 |
A singleton of an ordered pair is a function. Theorem 10.5 of [Quine]
p. 65. (Contributed by NM, 28-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → Fun {〈𝐴, 𝐵〉}) |
|
Theorem | fnsng 5235 |
Functionality and domain of the singleton of an ordered pair.
(Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → {〈𝐴, 𝐵〉} Fn {𝐴}) |
|
Theorem | funsn 5236 |
A singleton of an ordered pair is a function. Theorem 10.5 of [Quine]
p. 65. (Contributed by NM, 12-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ Fun {〈𝐴, 𝐵〉} |
|
Theorem | funinsn 5237 |
A function based on the singleton of an ordered pair. Unlike funsng 5234,
this holds even if 𝐴 or 𝐵 is a proper class.
(Contributed by
Jim Kingdon, 17-Apr-2022.)
|
⊢ Fun ({〈𝐴, 𝐵〉} ∩ (𝑉 × 𝑊)) |
|
Theorem | funprg 5238 |
A set of two pairs is a function if their first members are different.
(Contributed by FL, 26-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑌) ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) → Fun {〈𝐴, 𝐶〉, 〈𝐵, 𝐷〉}) |
|
Theorem | funtpg 5239 |
A set of three pairs is a function if their first members are different.
(Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 5-Dec-2017.)
|
⊢ (((𝑋 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑊) ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐹 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐻) ∧ (𝑋 ≠ 𝑌 ∧ 𝑋 ≠ 𝑍 ∧ 𝑌 ≠ 𝑍)) → Fun {〈𝑋, 𝐴〉, 〈𝑌, 𝐵〉, 〈𝑍, 𝐶〉}) |
|
Theorem | funpr 5240 |
A function with a domain of two elements. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen,
20-Jun-2010.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ≠ 𝐵 → Fun {〈𝐴, 𝐶〉, 〈𝐵, 𝐷〉}) |
|
Theorem | funtp 5241 |
A function with a domain of three elements. (Contributed by NM,
14-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐸 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ 𝐶) → Fun {〈𝐴, 𝐷〉, 〈𝐵, 𝐸〉, 〈𝐶, 𝐹〉}) |
|
Theorem | fnsn 5242 |
Functionality and domain of the singleton of an ordered pair.
(Contributed by Jonathan Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝐴, 𝐵〉} Fn {𝐴} |
|
Theorem | fnprg 5243 |
Function with a domain of two different values. (Contributed by FL,
26-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑌) ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) → {〈𝐴, 𝐶〉, 〈𝐵, 𝐷〉} Fn {𝐴, 𝐵}) |
|
Theorem | fntpg 5244 |
Function with a domain of three different values. (Contributed by
Alexander van der Vekens, 5-Dec-2017.)
|
⊢ (((𝑋 ∈ 𝑈 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑊) ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐹 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐻) ∧ (𝑋 ≠ 𝑌 ∧ 𝑋 ≠ 𝑍 ∧ 𝑌 ≠ 𝑍)) → {〈𝑋, 𝐴〉, 〈𝑌, 𝐵〉, 〈𝑍, 𝐶〉} Fn {𝑋, 𝑌, 𝑍}) |
|
Theorem | fntp 5245 |
A function with a domain of three elements. (Contributed by NM,
14-Sep-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐸 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 ∈
V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ 𝐶) → {〈𝐴, 𝐷〉, 〈𝐵, 𝐸〉, 〈𝐶, 𝐹〉} Fn {𝐴, 𝐵, 𝐶}) |
|
Theorem | fun0 5246 |
The empty set is a function. Theorem 10.3 of [Quine] p. 65. (Contributed
by NM, 7-Apr-1998.)
|
⊢ Fun ∅ |
|
Theorem | funcnvcnv 5247 |
The double converse of a function is a function. (Contributed by NM,
21-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 → Fun ◡◡𝐴) |
|
Theorem | funcnv2 5248* |
A simpler equivalence for single-rooted (see funcnv 5249). (Contributed
by NM, 9-Aug-2004.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑦∃*𝑥 𝑥𝐴𝑦) |
|
Theorem | funcnv 5249* |
The converse of a class is a function iff the class is single-rooted,
which means that for any 𝑦 in the range of 𝐴 there
is at most
one 𝑥 such that 𝑥𝐴𝑦. Definition of single-rooted in
[Enderton] p. 43. See funcnv2 5248 for a simpler version. (Contributed by
NM, 13-Aug-2004.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ ran 𝐴∃*𝑥 𝑥𝐴𝑦) |
|
Theorem | funcnv3 5250* |
A condition showing a class is single-rooted. (See funcnv 5249).
(Contributed by NM, 26-May-2006.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ ran 𝐴∃!𝑥 ∈ dom 𝐴 𝑥𝐴𝑦) |
|
Theorem | funcnveq 5251* |
Another way of expressing that a class is single-rooted. Counterpart to
dffun2 5198. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 24-Dec-2018.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧((𝑥𝐴𝑦 ∧ 𝑧𝐴𝑦) → 𝑥 = 𝑧)) |
|
Theorem | fun2cnv 5252* |
The double converse of a class is a function iff the class is
single-valued. Each side is equivalent to Definition 6.4(2) of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 23, who use the
notation "Un(A)" for single-valued.
Note that 𝐴 is not necessarily a function.
(Contributed by NM,
13-Aug-2004.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡◡𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦) |
|
Theorem | svrelfun 5253 |
A single-valued relation is a function. (See fun2cnv 5252 for
"single-valued.") Definition 6.4(4) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24.
(Contributed by NM, 17-Jan-2006.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐴 ↔ (Rel 𝐴 ∧ Fun ◡◡𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | fncnv 5254* |
Single-rootedness (see funcnv 5249) of a class cut down by a cross
product. (Contributed by NM, 5-Mar-2007.)
|
⊢ (◡(𝑅 ∩ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) Fn 𝐵 ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥𝑅𝑦) |
|
Theorem | fun11 5255* |
Two ways of stating that 𝐴 is one-to-one (but not necessarily a
function). Each side is equivalent to Definition 6.4(3) of
[TakeutiZaring] p. 24, who use the
notation "Un2 (A)" for one-to-one
(but not necessarily a function). (Contributed by NM, 17-Jan-2006.)
|
⊢ ((Fun ◡◡𝐴 ∧ Fun ◡𝐴) ↔ ∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑥𝐴𝑦 ∧ 𝑧𝐴𝑤) → (𝑥 = 𝑧 ↔ 𝑦 = 𝑤))) |
|
Theorem | fununi 5256* |
The union of a chain (with respect to inclusion) of functions is a
function. (Contributed by NM, 10-Aug-2004.)
|
⊢ (∀𝑓 ∈ 𝐴 (Fun 𝑓 ∧ ∀𝑔 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓 ⊆ 𝑔 ∨ 𝑔 ⊆ 𝑓)) → Fun ∪
𝐴) |
|
Theorem | funcnvuni 5257* |
The union of a chain (with respect to inclusion) of single-rooted sets
is single-rooted. (See funcnv 5249 for "single-rooted"
definition.)
(Contributed by NM, 11-Aug-2004.)
|
⊢ (∀𝑓 ∈ 𝐴 (Fun ◡𝑓 ∧ ∀𝑔 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓 ⊆ 𝑔 ∨ 𝑔 ⊆ 𝑓)) → Fun ◡∪ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | fun11uni 5258* |
The union of a chain (with respect to inclusion) of one-to-one functions
is a one-to-one function. (Contributed by NM, 11-Aug-2004.)
|
⊢ (∀𝑓 ∈ 𝐴 ((Fun 𝑓 ∧ Fun ◡𝑓) ∧ ∀𝑔 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓 ⊆ 𝑔 ∨ 𝑔 ⊆ 𝑓)) → (Fun ∪
𝐴 ∧ Fun ◡∪ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | funin 5259 |
The intersection with a function is a function. Exercise 14(a) of
[Enderton] p. 53. (Contributed by NM,
19-Mar-2004.) (Proof shortened by
Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → Fun (𝐹 ∩ 𝐺)) |
|
Theorem | funres11 5260 |
The restriction of a one-to-one function is one-to-one. (Contributed by
NM, 25-Mar-1998.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐹 → Fun ◡(𝐹 ↾ 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | funcnvres 5261 |
The converse of a restricted function. (Contributed by NM,
27-Mar-1998.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐹 → ◡(𝐹 ↾ 𝐴) = (◡𝐹 ↾ (𝐹 “ 𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | cnvresid 5262 |
Converse of a restricted identity function. (Contributed by FL,
4-Mar-2007.)
|
⊢ ◡( I
↾ 𝐴) = ( I ↾
𝐴) |
|
Theorem | funcnvres2 5263 |
The converse of a restriction of the converse of a function equals the
function restricted to the image of its converse. (Contributed by NM,
4-May-2005.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → ◡(◡𝐹 ↾ 𝐴) = (𝐹 ↾ (◡𝐹 “ 𝐴))) |
|
Theorem | funimacnv 5264 |
The image of the preimage of a function. (Contributed by NM,
25-May-2004.)
|
⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → (𝐹 “ (◡𝐹 “ 𝐴)) = (𝐴 ∩ ran 𝐹)) |
|
Theorem | funimass1 5265 |
A kind of contraposition law that infers a subclass of an image from a
preimage subclass. (Contributed by NM, 25-May-2004.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ ran 𝐹) → ((◡𝐹 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ⊆ (𝐹 “ 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | funimass2 5266 |
A kind of contraposition law that infers an image subclass from a subclass
of a preimage. (Contributed by NM, 25-May-2004.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ (◡𝐹 “ 𝐵)) → (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | imadiflem 5267 |
One direction of imadif 5268. This direction does not require
Fun ◡𝐹. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 25-Dec-2018.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 “ 𝐴) ∖ (𝐹 “ 𝐵)) ⊆ (𝐹 “ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | imadif 5268 |
The image of a difference is the difference of images. (Contributed by
NM, 24-May-1998.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐹 → (𝐹 “ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵)) = ((𝐹 “ 𝐴) ∖ (𝐹 “ 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | imainlem 5269 |
One direction of imain 5270. This direction does not require
Fun ◡𝐹. (Contributed by Jim
Kingdon, 25-Dec-2018.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 “ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵)) ⊆ ((𝐹 “ 𝐴) ∩ (𝐹 “ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | imain 5270 |
The image of an intersection is the intersection of images.
(Contributed by Paul Chapman, 11-Apr-2009.)
|
⊢ (Fun ◡𝐹 → (𝐹 “ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵)) = ((𝐹 “ 𝐴) ∩ (𝐹 “ 𝐵))) |
|
Theorem | funimaexglem 5271 |
Lemma for funimaexg 5272. It constitutes the interesting part of
funimaexg 5272, in which 𝐵 ⊆ dom 𝐴. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon,
27-Dec-2018.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ dom 𝐴) → (𝐴 “ 𝐵) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | funimaexg 5272 |
Axiom of Replacement using abbreviations. Axiom 39(vi) of [Quine] p. 284.
Compare Exercise 9 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 29. (Contributed by NM,
10-Sep-2006.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → (𝐴 “ 𝐵) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | funimaex 5273 |
The image of a set under any function is also a set. Equivalent of
Axiom of Replacement. Axiom 39(vi) of [Quine] p. 284. Compare Exercise
9 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 29.
(Contributed by NM, 17-Nov-2002.)
|
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐴 → (𝐴 “ 𝐵) ∈ V) |
|
Theorem | isarep1 5274* |
Part of a study of the Axiom of Replacement used by the Isabelle prover.
The object PrimReplace is apparently the image of the function encoded
by 𝜑(𝑥, 𝑦) i.e. the class ({〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} “ 𝐴).
If so, we can prove Isabelle's "Axiom of Replacement"
conclusion without
using the Axiom of Replacement, for which I (N. Megill) currently have
no explanation. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2006.) (Proof shortened by
Mario Carneiro, 4-Dec-2016.)
|
⊢ (𝑏 ∈ ({〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} “ 𝐴) ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 [𝑏 / 𝑦]𝜑) |
|
Theorem | isarep2 5275* |
Part of a study of the Axiom of Replacement used by the Isabelle prover.
In Isabelle, the sethood of PrimReplace is apparently postulated
implicitly by its type signature "[ i,
[ i, i ] => o ]
=> i", which automatically asserts that it is a set without
using any
axioms. To prove that it is a set in Metamath, we need the hypotheses
of Isabelle's "Axiom of Replacement" as well as the Axiom of
Replacement
in the form funimaex 5273. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2006.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦∀𝑧((𝜑 ∧ [𝑧 / 𝑦]𝜑) → 𝑦 = 𝑧) ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑤 𝑤 = ({〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} “ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | fneq1 5276 |
Equality theorem for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by NM,
1-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 = 𝐺 → (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐺 Fn 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | fneq2 5277 |
Equality theorem for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by NM,
1-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐹 Fn 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | fneq1d 5278 |
Equality deduction for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by
Paul Chapman, 22-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 = 𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐺 Fn 𝐴)) |
|
Theorem | fneq2d 5279 |
Equality deduction for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by
Paul Chapman, 22-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐹 Fn 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | fneq12d 5280 |
Equality deduction for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by
NM, 26-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 = 𝐺)
& ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐺 Fn 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | fneq12 5281 |
Equality theorem for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by
Thierry Arnoux, 31-Jan-2017.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 = 𝐺 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝐵) → (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐺 Fn 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | fneq1i 5282 |
Equality inference for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by
Paul Chapman, 22-Jun-2011.)
|
⊢ 𝐹 = 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐺 Fn 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | fneq2i 5283 |
Equality inference for function predicate with domain. (Contributed by
NM, 4-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ↔ 𝐹 Fn 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | nffn 5284 |
Bound-variable hypothesis builder for a function with domain.
(Contributed by NM, 30-Jan-2004.)
|
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐹
& ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥 𝐹 Fn 𝐴 |
|
Theorem | fnfun 5285 |
A function with domain is a function. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 → Fun 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | fnrel 5286 |
A function with domain is a relation. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 → Rel 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | fndm 5287 |
The domain of a function. (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 → dom 𝐹 = 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | funfni 5288 |
Inference to convert a function and domain antecedent. (Contributed by
NM, 22-Apr-2004.)
|
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom 𝐹) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝜑) |
|
Theorem | fndmu 5289 |
A function has a unique domain. (Contributed by NM, 11-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹 Fn 𝐵) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | fnbr 5290 |
The first argument of binary relation on a function belongs to the
function's domain. (Contributed by NM, 7-May-2004.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵𝐹𝐶) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | fnop 5291 |
The first argument of an ordered pair in a function belongs to the
function's domain. (Contributed by NM, 8-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 〈𝐵, 𝐶〉 ∈ 𝐹) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) |
|
Theorem | fneu 5292* |
There is exactly one value of a function. (Contributed by NM,
22-Apr-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 17-Sep-2011.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ∃!𝑦 𝐵𝐹𝑦) |
|
Theorem | fneu2 5293* |
There is exactly one value of a function. (Contributed by NM,
7-Nov-1995.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ∃!𝑦〈𝐵, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | fnun 5294 |
The union of two functions with disjoint domains. (Contributed by NM,
22-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ (((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐺 Fn 𝐵) ∧ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅) → (𝐹 ∪ 𝐺) Fn (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) |
|
Theorem | fnunsn 5295 |
Extension of a function with a new ordered pair. (Contributed by NM,
28-Sep-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.)
|
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑌 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 Fn 𝐷)
& ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝐹 ∪ {〈𝑋, 𝑌〉}) & ⊢ 𝐸 = (𝐷 ∪ {𝑋}) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐺 Fn 𝐸) |
|
Theorem | fnco 5296 |
Composition of two functions. (Contributed by NM, 22-May-2006.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐺 Fn 𝐵 ∧ ran 𝐺 ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐹 ∘ 𝐺) Fn 𝐵) |
|
Theorem | fnresdm 5297 |
A function does not change when restricted to its domain. (Contributed by
NM, 5-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐴) = 𝐹) |
|
Theorem | fnresdisj 5298 |
A function restricted to a class disjoint with its domain is empty.
(Contributed by NM, 23-Sep-2004.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 → ((𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅ ↔ (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) = ∅)) |
|
Theorem | 2elresin 5299 |
Membership in two functions restricted by each other's domain.
(Contributed by NM, 8-Aug-1994.)
|
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐺 Fn 𝐵) → ((〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∈ 𝐹 ∧ 〈𝑥, 𝑧〉 ∈ 𝐺) ↔ (〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∈ (𝐹 ↾ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵)) ∧ 〈𝑥, 𝑧〉 ∈ (𝐺 ↾ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵))))) |
|
Theorem | fnssresb 5300 |
Restriction of a function with a subclass of its domain. (Contributed by
NM, 10-Oct-2007.)
|
⊢ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 → ((𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) Fn 𝐵 ↔ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) |