HomeHome Intuitionistic Logic Explorer
Theorem List (p. 30 of 156)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  ILE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Theorem List for Intuitionistic Logic Explorer - 2901-3000   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremelabgt 2901* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Closed theorem version of elabg 2906.) (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.)
((𝐴𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelabgf 2902 Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Compare Theorem 6.13 of [Quine] p. 44. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.)
𝑥𝐴    &   𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelabf 2903* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.)
𝑥𝜓    &   𝐴 ∈ V    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremelab 2904* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Compare Theorem 6.13 of [Quine] p. 44. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremelabd 2905* Explicit demonstration the class {𝑥𝜓} is not empty by the example 𝑋. (Contributed by RP, 12-Aug-2020.)
(𝜑𝑋 ∈ V)    &   (𝜑𝜒)    &   (𝑥 = 𝑋 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜓)
 
Theoremelabg 2906* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Compare Theorem 6.13 of [Quine] p. 44. (Contributed by NM, 14-Apr-1995.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelab2g 2907* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-1995.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝐵 = {𝑥𝜑}       (𝐴𝑉 → (𝐴𝐵𝜓))
 
Theoremelab2 2908* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-1995.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝐵 = {𝑥𝜑}       (𝐴𝐵𝜓)
 
Theoremelab4g 2909* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 17-Oct-2012.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝐵 = {𝑥𝜑}       (𝐴𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelab3gf 2910 Membership in a class abstraction, with a weaker antecedent than elabgf 2902. (Contributed by NM, 6-Sep-2011.)
𝑥𝐴    &   𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       ((𝜓𝐴𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelab3g 2911* Membership in a class abstraction, with a weaker antecedent than elabg 2906. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-2006.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       ((𝜓𝐴𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelab3 2912* Membership in a class abstraction using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 10-Nov-2000.)
(𝜓𝐴 ∈ V)    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremelrabi 2913* Implication for the membership in a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 31-Dec-2017.)
(𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝑉𝜑} → 𝐴𝑉)
 
Theoremelrabf 2914 Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2003.)
𝑥𝐴    &   𝑥𝐵    &   𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝐵𝜑} ↔ (𝐴𝐵𝜓))
 
Theoremelrab3t 2915* Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Closed theorem version of elrab3 2917.) (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 31-Aug-2017.)
((∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓)) ∧ 𝐴𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝐵𝜑} ↔ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelrab 2916* Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-1999.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝐵𝜑} ↔ (𝐴𝐵𝜓))
 
Theoremelrab3 2917* Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Oct-2006.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝐴𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝐵𝜑} ↔ 𝜓))
 
Theoremelrabd 2918* Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Deduction version of elrab 2916. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 23-Oct-2021.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   (𝜑𝐴𝐵)    &   (𝜑𝜒)       (𝜑𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝐵𝜓})
 
Theoremelrab2 2919* Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Nov-2006.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝐶 = {𝑥𝐵𝜑}       (𝐴𝐶 ↔ (𝐴𝐵𝜓))
 
Theoremralab 2920* Universal quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.)
(𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremralrab 2921* Universal quantification over a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.)
(𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝐴𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑥𝐴 (𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremrexab 2922* Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Jan-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.)
(𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremrexrab 2923* Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 17-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.)
(𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝐴𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∃𝑥𝐴 (𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremralab2 2924* Universal quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒))       (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦(𝜑𝜒))
 
Theoremralrab2 2925* Universal quantification over a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒))       (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝐴𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝐴 (𝜑𝜒))
 
Theoremrexab2 2926* Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒))       (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑦(𝜑𝜒))
 
Theoremrexrab2 2927* Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒))       (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦𝐴𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑦𝐴 (𝜑𝜒))
 
Theoremabidnf 2928* Identity used to create closed-form versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders for class expressions. (Contributed by NM, 10-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.)
(𝑥𝐴 → {𝑧 ∣ ∀𝑥 𝑧𝐴} = 𝐴)
 
Theoremdedhb 2929* A deduction theorem for converting the inference 𝑥𝐴 => 𝜑 into a closed theorem. Use nfa1 1552 and nfab 2341 to eliminate the hypothesis of the substitution instance 𝜓 of the inference. For converting the inference form into a deduction form, abidnf 2928 is useful. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2006.)
(𝐴 = {𝑧 ∣ ∀𝑥 𝑧𝐴} → (𝜑𝜓))    &   𝜓       (𝑥𝐴𝜑)
 
Theoremeqeu 2930* A condition which implies existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 8-Sep-2009.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       ((𝐴𝐵𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑𝑥 = 𝐴)) → ∃!𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremeueq 2931* Equality has existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 25-Nov-1994.)
(𝐴 ∈ V ↔ ∃!𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴)
 
Theoremeueq1 2932* Equality has existential uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.)
𝐴 ∈ V       ∃!𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴
 
Theoremeueq2dc 2933* Equality has existential uniqueness (split into 2 cases). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   𝐵 ∈ V       (DECID 𝜑 → ∃!𝑥((𝜑𝑥 = 𝐴) ∨ (¬ 𝜑𝑥 = 𝐵)))
 
Theoremeueq3dc 2934* Equality has existential uniqueness (split into 3 cases). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 28-Sep-2015.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   𝐵 ∈ V    &   𝐶 ∈ V    &    ¬ (𝜑𝜓)       (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ∃!𝑥((𝜑𝑥 = 𝐴) ∨ (¬ (𝜑𝜓) ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵) ∨ (𝜓𝑥 = 𝐶))))
 
Theoremmoeq 2935* There is at most one set equal to a class. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.)
∃*𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴
 
Theoremmoeq3dc 2936* "At most one" property of equality (split into 3 cases). (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 7-Jul-2018.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   𝐵 ∈ V    &   𝐶 ∈ V    &    ¬ (𝜑𝜓)       (DECID 𝜑 → (DECID 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥((𝜑𝑥 = 𝐴) ∨ (¬ (𝜑𝜓) ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵) ∨ (𝜓𝑥 = 𝐶))))
 
Theoremmosubt 2937* "At most one" remains true after substitution. (Contributed by Jim Kingdon, 18-Jan-2019.)
(∀𝑦∃*𝑥𝜑 → ∃*𝑥𝑦(𝑦 = 𝐴𝜑))
 
Theoremmosub 2938* "At most one" remains true after substitution. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.)
∃*𝑥𝜑       ∃*𝑥𝑦(𝑦 = 𝐴𝜑)
 
Theoremmo2icl 2939* Theorem for inferring "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 17-Oct-1996.)
(∀𝑥(𝜑𝑥 = 𝐴) → ∃*𝑥𝜑)
 
Theoremmob2 2940* Consequence of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2015.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       ((𝐴𝐵 ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑𝜑) → (𝑥 = 𝐴𝜓))
 
Theoremmoi2 2941* Consequence of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 29-Jun-2008.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (((𝐴𝐵 ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑) ∧ (𝜑𝜓)) → 𝑥 = 𝐴)
 
Theoremmob 2942* Equality implied by "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2006.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑𝜒))       (((𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷) ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑𝜓) → (𝐴 = 𝐵𝜒))
 
Theoremmoi 2943* Equality implied by "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2006.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑𝜒))       (((𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷) ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑 ∧ (𝜓𝜒)) → 𝐴 = 𝐵)
 
Theoremmorex 2944* Derive membership from uniqueness. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.)
𝐵 ∈ V    &   (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑𝜓))       ((∃𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑) → (𝜓𝐵𝐴))
 
Theoremeuxfr2dc 2945* Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   ∃*𝑦 𝑥 = 𝐴       (DECID𝑦𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴𝜑) → (∃!𝑥𝑦(𝑥 = 𝐴𝜑) ↔ ∃!𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremeuxfrdc 2946* Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.)
𝐴 ∈ V    &   ∃!𝑦 𝑥 = 𝐴    &   (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (DECID𝑦𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴𝜓) → (∃!𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∃!𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremeuind 2947* Existential uniqueness via an indirect equality. (Contributed by NM, 11-Oct-2010.)
𝐵 ∈ V    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦𝐴 = 𝐵)       ((∀𝑥𝑦((𝜑𝜓) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ∧ ∃𝑥𝜑) → ∃!𝑧𝑥(𝜑𝑧 = 𝐴))
 
Theoremreu2 2948* A way to express restricted uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 22-Nov-1994.)
(∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ [𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑) → 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremreu6 2949* A way to express restricted uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 20-Oct-2006.)
(∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦𝐴𝑥𝐴 (𝜑𝑥 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremreu3 2950* A way to express restricted uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.)
(∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦𝐴𝑥𝐴 (𝜑𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremreu6i 2951* A condition which implies existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Oct-2015.)
((𝐵𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴 (𝜑𝑥 = 𝐵)) → ∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑)
 
Theoremeqreu 2952* A condition which implies existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Oct-2015.)
(𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑𝜓))       ((𝐵𝐴𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴 (𝜑𝑥 = 𝐵)) → ∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑)
 
Theoremrmo4 2953* Restricted "at most one" using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐴 ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝑥 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremreu4 2954* Restricted uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 23-Nov-1994.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐴 ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremreu7 2955* Restricted uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐴 (𝜓𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremreu8 2956* Restricted uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃!𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑥𝐴 (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦𝐴 (𝜓𝑥 = 𝑦)))
 
Theoremrmo3f 2957* Restricted "at most one" using explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2012.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 8-Oct-2017.)
𝑥𝐴    &   𝑦𝐴    &   𝑦𝜑       (∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ [𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑) → 𝑥 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremrmo4f 2958* Restricted "at most one" using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 11-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 8-Mar-2017.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 8-Oct-2017.)
𝑥𝐴    &   𝑦𝐴    &   𝑥𝜓    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐴 ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝑥 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremreueq 2959* Equality has existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Sep-2015.)
(𝐵𝐴 ↔ ∃!𝑥𝐴 𝑥 = 𝐵)
 
Theoremrmoan 2960 Restricted "at most one" still holds when a conjunct is added. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jun-2017.)
(∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑 → ∃*𝑥𝐴 (𝜓𝜑))
 
Theoremrmoim 2961 Restricted "at most one" is preserved through implication (note wff reversal). (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.)
(∀𝑥𝐴 (𝜑𝜓) → (∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑))
 
Theoremrmoimia 2962 Restricted "at most one" is preserved through implication (note wff reversal). (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.)
(𝑥𝐴 → (𝜑𝜓))       (∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑)
 
Theoremrmoimi2 2963 Restricted "at most one" is preserved through implication (note wff reversal). (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.)
𝑥((𝑥𝐴𝜑) → (𝑥𝐵𝜓))       (∃*𝑥𝐵 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑)
 
Theorem2reuswapdc 2964* A condition allowing swap of uniqueness and existential quantifiers. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 7-Apr-2017.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.)
(DECID𝑥𝑦(𝑥𝐴 ∧ (𝑦𝐵𝜑)) → (∀𝑥𝐴 ∃*𝑦𝐵 𝜑 → (∃!𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐵 𝜑 → ∃!𝑦𝐵𝑥𝐴 𝜑)))
 
Theoremreuind 2965* Existential uniqueness via an indirect equality. (Contributed by NM, 16-Oct-2010.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   (𝑥 = 𝑦𝐴 = 𝐵)       ((∀𝑥𝑦(((𝐴𝐶𝜑) ∧ (𝐵𝐶𝜓)) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ∧ ∃𝑥(𝐴𝐶𝜑)) → ∃!𝑧𝐶𝑥((𝐴𝐶𝜑) → 𝑧 = 𝐴))
 
Theorem2rmorex 2966* Double restricted quantification with "at most one," analogous to 2moex 2128. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.)
(∃*𝑥𝐴𝑦𝐵 𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝐵 ∃*𝑥𝐴 𝜑)
 
Theoremnelrdva 2967* Deduce negative membership from an implication. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 27-Nov-2017.)
((𝜑𝑥𝐴) → 𝑥𝐵)       (𝜑 → ¬ 𝐵𝐴)
 
2.1.7  Conditional equality (experimental)

This is a very useless definition, which "abbreviates" (𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) as CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑). What this display hides, though, is that the first expression, even though it has a shorter constant string, is actually much more complicated in its parse tree: it is parsed as (wi (wceq (cv vx) (cv vy)) wph), while the CondEq version is parsed as (wcdeq vx vy wph). It also allows us to give a name to the specific ternary operation (𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑).

This is all used as part of a metatheorem: we want to say that (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑(𝑥) ↔ 𝜑(𝑦))) and (𝑥 = 𝑦𝐴(𝑥) = 𝐴(𝑦)) are provable, for any expressions 𝜑(𝑥) or 𝐴(𝑥) in the language. The proof is by induction, so the base case is each of the primitives, which is why you will see a theorem for each of the set.mm primitive operations.

The metatheorem comes with a disjoint variables condition: every variable in 𝜑(𝑥) is assumed disjoint from 𝑥 except 𝑥 itself. For such a proof by induction, we must consider each of the possible forms of 𝜑(𝑥). If it is a variable other than 𝑥, then we have CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝐴 = 𝐴) or CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜑)), which is provable by cdeqth 2972 and reflexivity. Since we are only working with class and wff expressions, it can't be 𝑥 itself in set.mm, but if it was we'd have to also prove CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦) (where set equality is being used on the right).

Otherwise, it is a primitive operation applied to smaller expressions. In these cases, for each setvar variable parameter to the operation, we must consider if it is equal to 𝑥 or not, which yields 2^n proof obligations. Luckily, all primitive operations in set.mm have either zero or one set variable, so we only need to prove one statement for the non-set constructors (like implication) and two for the constructors taking a set (the forall and the class builder).

In each of the primitive proofs, we are allowed to assume that 𝑦 is disjoint from 𝜑(𝑥) and vice versa, because this is maintained through the induction. This is how we satisfy the disjoint variable conditions of cdeqab1 2977 and cdeqab 2975.

 
Syntaxwcdeq 2968 Extend wff notation to include conditional equality. This is a technical device used in the proof that is the not-free predicate, and that definitions are conservative as a result.
wff CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)
 
Definitiondf-cdeq 2969 Define conditional equality. All the notation to the left of the is fake; the parentheses and arrows are all part of the notation, which could equally well be written CondEq𝑥𝑦𝜑. On the right side is the actual implication arrow. The reason for this definition is to "flatten" the structure on the right side (whose tree structure is something like (wi (wceq (cv vx) (cv vy)) wph) ) into just (wcdeq vx vy wph). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
(CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑) ↔ (𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremcdeqi 2970 Deduce conditional equality. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)
 
Theoremcdeqri 2971 Property of conditional equality. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       (𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)
 
Theoremcdeqth 2972 Deduce conditional equality from a theorem. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝜑       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)
 
Theoremcdeqnot 2973 Distribute conditional equality over negation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (¬ 𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓))
 
Theoremcdeqal 2974* Distribute conditional equality over quantification. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑧𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑧𝜓))
 
Theoremcdeqab 2975* Distribute conditional equality over abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → {𝑧𝜑} = {𝑧𝜓})
 
Theoremcdeqal1 2976* Distribute conditional equality over quantification. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜓))
 
Theoremcdeqab1 2977* Distribute conditional equality over abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → {𝑥𝜑} = {𝑦𝜓})
 
Theoremcdeqim 2978 Distribute conditional equality over implication. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))    &   CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜒𝜃))       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → ((𝜑𝜒) ↔ (𝜓𝜃)))
 
Theoremcdeqcv 2979 Conditional equality for set-to-class promotion. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremcdeqeq 2980 Distribute conditional equality over equality. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝐴 = 𝐵)    &   CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝐶 = 𝐷)       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝐴 = 𝐶𝐵 = 𝐷))
 
Theoremcdeqel 2981 Distribute conditional equality over elementhood. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝐴 = 𝐵)    &   CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝐶 = 𝐷)       CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝐴𝐶𝐵𝐷))
 
Theoremnfcdeq 2982* If we have a conditional equality proof, where 𝜑 is 𝜑(𝑥) and 𝜓 is 𝜑(𝑦), and 𝜑(𝑥) in fact does not have 𝑥 free in it according to , then 𝜑(𝑥) ↔ 𝜑(𝑦) unconditionally. This proves that 𝑥𝜑 is actually a not-free predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝜑    &   CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑𝜓))       (𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremnfccdeq 2983* Variation of nfcdeq 2982 for classes. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.)
𝑥𝐴    &   CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦𝐴 = 𝐵)       𝐴 = 𝐵
 
2.1.8  Russell's Paradox
 
Theoremru 2984 Russell's Paradox. Proposition 4.14 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 14.

In the late 1800s, Frege's Axiom of (unrestricted) Comprehension, expressed in our notation as 𝐴 ∈ V, asserted that any collection of sets 𝐴 is a set i.e. belongs to the universe V of all sets. In particular, by substituting {𝑥𝑥𝑥} (the "Russell class") for 𝐴, it asserted {𝑥𝑥𝑥} ∈ V, meaning that the "collection of all sets which are not members of themselves" is a set. However, here we prove {𝑥𝑥𝑥} ∉ V. This contradiction was discovered by Russell in 1901 (published in 1903), invalidating the Comprehension Axiom and leading to the collapse of Frege's system.

In 1908, Zermelo rectified this fatal flaw by replacing Comprehension with a weaker Subset (or Separation) Axiom asserting that 𝐴 is a set only when it is smaller than some other set 𝐵. The intuitionistic set theory IZF includes such a separation axiom, Axiom 6 of [Crosilla] p. "Axioms of CZF and IZF", which we include as ax-sep 4147. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.)

{𝑥𝑥𝑥} ∉ V
 
2.1.9  Proper substitution of classes for sets
 
Syntaxwsbc 2985 Extend wff notation to include the proper substitution of a class for a set. Read this notation as "the proper substitution of class 𝐴 for setvar variable 𝑥 in wff 𝜑".
wff [𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑
 
Definitiondf-sbc 2986 Define the proper substitution of a class for a set.

When 𝐴 is a proper class, our definition evaluates to false. This is somewhat arbitrary: we could have, instead, chosen the conclusion of sbc6 3011 for our definition, which always evaluates to true for proper classes.

Our definition also does not produce the same results as discussed in the proof of Theorem 6.6 of [Quine] p. 42 (although Theorem 6.6 itself does hold, as shown by dfsbcq 2987 below). Unfortunately, Quine's definition requires a recursive syntactical breakdown of 𝜑, and it does not seem possible to express it with a single closed formula.

If we did not want to commit to any specific proper class behavior, we could use this definition only to prove Theorem dfsbcq 2987, which holds for both our definition and Quine's, and from which we can derive a weaker version of df-sbc 2986 in the form of sbc8g 2993. However, the behavior of Quine's definition at proper classes is similarly arbitrary, and for practical reasons (to avoid having to prove sethood of 𝐴 in every use of this definition) we allow direct reference to df-sbc 2986 and assert that [𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑 is always false when 𝐴 is a proper class.

The related definition df-csb defines proper substitution into a class variable (as opposed to a wff variable). (Contributed by NM, 14-Apr-1995.) (Revised by NM, 25-Dec-2016.)

([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑})
 
Theoremdfsbcq 2987 This theorem, which is similar to Theorem 6.7 of [Quine] p. 42 and holds under both our definition and Quine's, provides us with a weak definition of the proper substitution of a class for a set. Since our df-sbc 2986 does not result in the same behavior as Quine's for proper classes, if we wished to avoid conflict with Quine's definition we could start with this theorem and dfsbcq2 2988 instead of df-sbc 2986. (dfsbcq2 2988 is needed because unlike Quine we do not overload the df-sb 1774 syntax.) As a consequence of these theorems, we can derive sbc8g 2993, which is a weaker version of df-sbc 2986 that leaves substitution undefined when 𝐴 is a proper class.

However, it is often a nuisance to have to prove the sethood hypothesis of sbc8g 2993, so we will allow direct use of df-sbc 2986. Proper substiution with a proper class is rarely needed, and when it is, we can simply use the expansion of Quine's definition. (Contributed by NM, 14-Apr-1995.)

(𝐴 = 𝐵 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑[𝐵 / 𝑥]𝜑))
 
Theoremdfsbcq2 2988 This theorem, which is similar to Theorem 6.7 of [Quine] p. 42 and holds under both our definition and Quine's, relates logic substitution df-sb 1774 and substitution for class variables df-sbc 2986. Unlike Quine, we use a different syntax for each in order to avoid overloading it. See remarks in dfsbcq 2987. (Contributed by NM, 31-Dec-2016.)
(𝑦 = 𝐴 → ([𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑[𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑))
 
Theoremsbsbc 2989 Show that df-sb 1774 and df-sbc 2986 are equivalent when the class term 𝐴 in df-sbc 2986 is a setvar variable. This theorem lets us reuse theorems based on df-sb 1774 for proofs involving df-sbc 2986. (Contributed by NM, 31-Dec-2016.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
([𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑[𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑)
 
Theoremsbceq1d 2990 Equality theorem for class substitution. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) (Revised by NM, 30-Jun-2018.)
(𝜑𝐴 = 𝐵)       (𝜑 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜓[𝐵 / 𝑥]𝜓))
 
Theoremsbceq1dd 2991 Equality theorem for class substitution. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.) (Revised by NM, 30-Jun-2018.)
(𝜑𝐴 = 𝐵)    &   (𝜑[𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜓)       (𝜑[𝐵 / 𝑥]𝜓)
 
Theoremsbceqbid 2992* Equality theorem for class substitution. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 4-Sep-2018.)
(𝜑𝐴 = 𝐵)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜓[𝐵 / 𝑥]𝜒))
 
Theoremsbc8g 2993 This is the closest we can get to df-sbc 2986 if we start from dfsbcq 2987 (see its comments) and dfsbcq2 2988. (Contributed by NM, 18-Nov-2008.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 29-Jun-2011.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝐴𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑𝐴 ∈ {𝑥𝜑}))
 
Theoremsbcex 2994 By our definition of proper substitution, it can only be true if the substituted expression is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 13-Oct-2016.)
([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑𝐴 ∈ V)
 
Theoremsbceq1a 2995 Equality theorem for class substitution. Class version of sbequ12 1782. (Contributed by NM, 26-Sep-2003.)
(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑[𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑))
 
Theoremsbceq2a 2996 Equality theorem for class substitution. Class version of sbequ12r 1783. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2017.)
(𝐴 = 𝑥 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑𝜑))
 
Theoremspsbc 2997 Specialization: if a formula is true for all sets, it is true for any class which is a set. Similar to Theorem 6.11 of [Quine] p. 44. See also stdpc4 1786 and rspsbc 3068. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jan-2004.)
(𝐴𝑉 → (∀𝑥𝜑[𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑))
 
Theoremspsbcd 2998 Specialization: if a formula is true for all sets, it is true for any class which is a set. Similar to Theorem 6.11 of [Quine] p. 44. See also stdpc4 1786 and rspsbc 3068. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2017.)
(𝜑𝐴𝑉)    &   (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)       (𝜑[𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜓)
 
Theoremsbcth 2999 A substitution into a theorem remains true (when 𝐴 is a set). (Contributed by NM, 5-Nov-2005.)
𝜑       (𝐴𝑉[𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑)
 
Theoremsbcthdv 3000* Deduction version of sbcth 2999. (Contributed by NM, 30-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.)
(𝜑𝜓)       ((𝜑𝐴𝑉) → [𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜓)
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13300 134 13301-13400 135 13401-13500 136 13501-13600 137 13601-13700 138 13701-13800 139 13801-13900 140 13901-14000 141 14001-14100 142 14101-14200 143 14201-14300 144 14301-14400 145 14401-14500 146 14501-14600 147 14601-14700 148 14701-14800 149 14801-14900 150 14901-15000 151 15001-15100 152 15101-15200 153 15201-15300 154 15301-15400 155 15401-15500 156 15501-15574
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >