HomeHome Metamath Proof Explorer
Theorem List (p. 348 of 466)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  MPE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Color key:    Metamath Proof Explorer  Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29289)
  Hilbert Space Explorer  Hilbert Space Explorer
(29290-30812)
  Users' Mathboxes  Users' Mathboxes
(30813-46532)
 

Theorem List for Metamath Proof Explorer - 34701-34800   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Theoremknoppndvlem1 34701 Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)       (𝜑 → ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀) ∈ ℝ)
 
Theoremknoppndvlem2 34702 Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑𝐼 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝐽 < 𝐼)       (𝜑 → (((2 · 𝑁)↑𝐼) · ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)) ∈ ℤ)
 
Theoremknoppndvlem3 34703 Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.)
(𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))       (𝜑 → (𝐶 ∈ ℝ ∧ (abs‘𝐶) < 1))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem4 34704* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   (𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → seq0( + , (𝐹𝐴)) ⇝ (𝑊𝐴))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem5 34705* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   (𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → Σ𝑖 ∈ (0...𝐽)((𝐹𝐴)‘𝑖) ∈ ℝ)
 
Theoremknoppndvlem6 34706* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → (𝑊𝐴) = Σ𝑖 ∈ (0...𝐽)((𝐹𝐴)‘𝑖))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem7 34707* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → ((𝐹𝐴)‘𝐽) = ((𝐶𝐽) · (𝑇‘(𝑀 / 2))))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem8 34708* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 2 ∥ 𝑀)       (𝜑 → ((𝐹𝐴)‘𝐽) = 0)
 
Theoremknoppndvlem9 34709* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → ¬ 2 ∥ 𝑀)       (𝜑 → ((𝐹𝐴)‘𝐽) = ((𝐶𝐽) / 2))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem10 34710* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 15-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   𝐵 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · (𝑀 + 1))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → (abs‘(((𝐹𝐵)‘𝐽) − ((𝐹𝐴)‘𝐽))) = (((abs‘𝐶)↑𝐽) / 2))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem11 34711* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 28-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   (𝜑𝐴 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝐵 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → (abs‘(Σ𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝐽 − 1))((𝐹𝐵)‘𝑖) − Σ𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝐽 − 1))((𝐹𝐴)‘𝑖))) ≤ ((abs‘(𝐵𝐴)) · Σ𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝐽 − 1))(((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶))↑𝑖)))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem12 34712 Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 29-Jun-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → (((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶)) ≠ 1 ∧ 1 < (((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶)) − 1)))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem13 34713 Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 1-Jul-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 5-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑𝐶 ≠ 0)
 
Theoremknoppndvlem14 34714* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 1-Jul-2021.) (Revised by Asger C. Ipsen, 7-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   𝐵 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · (𝑀 + 1))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → (abs‘(Σ𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝐽 − 1))((𝐹𝐵)‘𝑖) − Σ𝑖 ∈ (0...(𝐽 − 1))((𝐹𝐴)‘𝑖))) ≤ ((((abs‘𝐶)↑𝐽) / 2) · (1 / (((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶)) − 1))))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem15 34715* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 6-Jul-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   𝐵 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · (𝑀 + 1))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → ((((abs‘𝐶)↑𝐽) / 2) · (1 − (1 / (((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶)) − 1)))) ≤ (abs‘((𝑊𝐵) − (𝑊𝐴))))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem16 34716 Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 19-Jul-2021.)
𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   𝐵 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · (𝑀 + 1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → (𝐵𝐴) = (((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem17 34717* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 12-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑀)    &   𝐵 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · (𝑀 + 1))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑀 ∈ ℤ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → ((((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶))↑𝐽) · (1 − (1 / (((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶)) − 1)))) ≤ ((abs‘((𝑊𝐵) − (𝑊𝐴))) / (𝐵𝐴)))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem18 34718* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 14-Aug-2021.)
(𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑𝐷 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐸 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐺 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → ∃𝑗 ∈ ℕ0 ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝑗) / 2) < 𝐷𝐸 ≤ ((((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶))↑𝑗) · 𝐺)))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem19 34719* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 17-Aug-2021.)
𝐴 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · 𝑚)    &   𝐵 = ((((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) · (𝑚 + 1))    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝐻 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑 → ∃𝑚 ∈ ℤ (𝐴𝐻𝐻𝐵))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem20 34720 Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 18-Aug-2021.)
(𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → (1 − (1 / (((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶)) − 1))) ∈ ℝ+)
 
Theoremknoppndvlem21 34721* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 18-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   𝐺 = (1 − (1 / (((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶)) − 1)))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐷 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐸 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐻 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝐽 ∈ ℕ0)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))    &   (𝜑 → (((2 · 𝑁)↑-𝐽) / 2) < 𝐷)    &   (𝜑𝐸 ≤ ((((2 · 𝑁) · (abs‘𝐶))↑𝐽) · 𝐺))       (𝜑 → ∃𝑎 ∈ ℝ ∃𝑏 ∈ ℝ ((𝑎𝐻𝐻𝑏) ∧ ((𝑏𝑎) < 𝐷𝑎𝑏) ∧ 𝐸 ≤ ((abs‘((𝑊𝑏) − (𝑊𝑎))) / (𝑏𝑎))))
 
Theoremknoppndvlem22 34722* Lemma for knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 19-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝐷 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐸 ∈ ℝ+)    &   (𝜑𝐻 ∈ ℝ)    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → ∃𝑎 ∈ ℝ ∃𝑏 ∈ ℝ ((𝑎𝐻𝐻𝑏) ∧ ((𝑏𝑎) < 𝐷𝑎𝑏) ∧ 𝐸 ≤ ((abs‘((𝑊𝑏) − (𝑊𝑎))) / (𝑏𝑎))))
 
Theoremknoppndv 34723* The continuous nowhere differentiable function 𝑊 ( Knopp, K. (1918). Math. Z. 2, 1-26 ) is, in fact, nowhere differentiable. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 19-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑 → 1 < (𝑁 · (abs‘𝐶)))       (𝜑 → dom (ℝ D 𝑊) = ∅)
 
Theoremknoppf 34724* Knopp's function is a function. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 25-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)       (𝜑𝑊:ℝ⟶ℝ)
 
Theoremknoppcn2 34725* Variant of knoppcn 34693 with different codomain. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 25-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))    &   (𝜑𝑁 ∈ ℕ)    &   (𝜑𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1))       (𝜑𝑊 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ))
 
Theoremcnndvlem1 34726* Lemma for cnndv 34728. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 25-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ (((1 / 2)↑𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 3)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))       (𝑊 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ) ∧ dom (ℝ D 𝑊) = ∅)
 
Theoremcnndvlem2 34727* Lemma for cnndv 34728. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 26-Aug-2021.)
𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥)))    &   𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ (((1 / 2)↑𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 3)↑𝑛) · 𝑦)))))    &   𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹𝑤)‘𝑖))       𝑓(𝑓 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ) ∧ dom (ℝ D 𝑓) = ∅)
 
Theoremcnndv 34728 There exists a continuous nowhere differentiable function. The result follows directly from knoppcn 34693 and knoppndv 34723. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 26-Aug-2021.)
𝑓(𝑓 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ) ∧ dom (ℝ D 𝑓) = ∅)
 
20.15  Mathbox for BJ

In this mathbox, we try to respect the ordering of the sections of the main part. There are strengthenings of theorems of the main part, as well as work on reducing axiom dependencies.

 
20.15.1  Propositional calculus

Miscellaneous utility theorems of propositional calculus.

 
20.15.1.1  Derived rules of inference

In this section, we prove a few rules of inference derived from modus ponens ax-mp 5, and which do not depend on any other axioms.

 
Theorembj-mp2c 34729 A double modus ponens inference. Inference associated with mpd 15. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.)
𝜑    &   (𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       𝜒
 
Theorembj-mp2d 34730 A double modus ponens inference. Inference associated with mpcom 38. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.)
𝜑    &   (𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜓 → (𝜑𝜒))       𝜒
 
20.15.1.2  A syntactic theorem

In this section, we prove a syntactic theorem (bj-0 34731) asserting that some formula is well-formed. Then, we use this syntactic theorem to shorten the proof of a "usual" theorem (bj-1 34732) and explain in the comment of that theorem why this phenomenon is unusual.

 
Theorembj-0 34731 A syntactic theorem. See the section comment and the comment of bj-1 34732. The full proof (that is, with the syntactic, non-essential steps) does not appear on this webpage. It has five steps and reads $= wph wps wi wch wi $. The only other syntactic theorems in the main part of set.mm are wel 2108 and weq 1967. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
wff ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)
 
Theorembj-1 34732 In this proof, the use of the syntactic theorem bj-0 34731 allows to reduce the total length by one (non-essential) step. See also the section comment and the comment of bj-0 34731. Since bj-0 34731 is used in a non-essential step, this use does not appear on this webpage (but the present theorem appears on the webpage for bj-0 34731 as a theorem referencing it). The full proof reads $= wph wps wch bj-0 id $. (while, without using bj-0 34731, it would read $= wph wps wi wch wi id $.).

Now we explain why syntactic theorems are not useful in set.mm. Suppose that the syntactic theorem thm-0 proves that PHI is a well-formed formula, and that thm-0 is used to shorten the proof of thm-1. Assume that PHI does have proper non-atomic subformulas (which is not the case of the formula proved by weq 1967 or wel 2108). Then, the proof of thm-1 does not construct all the proper non-atomic subformulas of PHI (if it did, then using thm-0 would not shorten it). Therefore, thm-1 is a special instance of a more general theorem with essentially the same proof. In the present case, bj-1 34732 is a special instance of id 22. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)

(((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒) → ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒))
 
20.15.1.3  Minimal implicational calculus
 
Theorembj-a1k 34733 Weakening of ax-1 6. As a consequence, its associated inference is an instance (where we allow extra hypotheses) of ax-1 6. Its commuted form is 2a1 28 (but bj-a1k 34733 does not require ax-2 7). This shortens the proofs of dfwe2 7633 (937>925), ordunisuc2 7700 (789>777), r111 9542 (558>545), smo11 8204 (1176>1164). (Contributed by BJ, 11-Aug-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒𝜓)))
 
Theorembj-poni 34734 Inference associated with "pon", pm2.27 42. Its associated inference is ax-mp 5. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.)
𝜑       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜓)
 
Theorembj-nnclav 34735 When is substituted for 𝜓, this formula is the Clavius law with a doubly negated consequent, which is therefore a minimalistic tautology. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from peirce 201 and pm2.27 42 chained using syl 17. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Dec-2023.)
(((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜑) → ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜓))
 
Theorembj-nnclavi 34736 Inference associated with bj-nnclav 34735. Its associated inference is an instance of syl 17. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from bj-peircei 34755 and bj-poni 34734. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.)
((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜑)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜓)
 
Theorembj-nnclavc 34737 Commuted form of bj-nnclav 34735. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from bj-peircei 34755 and imim1i 63. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.) A proof which is shorter when compressed uses embantd 59. (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((𝜑𝜓) → (((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜑) → 𝜓))
 
Theorembj-nnclavci 34738 Inference associated with bj-nnclavc 34737. Its associated inference is an instance of syl 17. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from peirce 201 and syl 17. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜑) → 𝜓)
 
Theorembj-jarrii 34739 Inference associated with jarri 107. Contrary to it , it does not require ax-2 7, but only ax-mp 5 and ax-1 6. (Contributed by BJ, 29-Mar-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)    &   𝜓       𝜒
 
Theorembj-imim21 34740 The propositional function (𝜒 → (. → 𝜃)) is decreasing. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Jul-2019.)
((𝜑𝜓) → ((𝜒 → (𝜓𝜃)) → (𝜒 → (𝜑𝜃))))
 
Theorembj-imim21i 34741 Inference associated with bj-imim21 34740. Its associated inference is syl5 34. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Jul-2019.)
(𝜑𝜓)       ((𝜒 → (𝜓𝜃)) → (𝜒 → (𝜑𝜃)))
 
Theorembj-peircestab 34742 Over minimal implicational calculus, Peirce's law implies the double negation of the stability of any formula (that is the interpretation when is substituted for 𝜓 and for 𝜒). Therefore, the double negation of the stability of any formula is provable in classical refutability calculus. It is also provable in intuitionistic calculus (see iset.mm/bj-nnst) but it is not provable in minimal calculus (see bj-stabpeirce 34743). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Nov-2023.) Axiom ax-3 8 is only used through Peirce's law peirce 201. (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(((((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒) → 𝜑) → 𝜒) → 𝜒)
 
Theorembj-stabpeirce 34743 This minimal implicational calculus tautology is used in the following argument: When 𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒, 𝜃, 𝜏 are replaced respectively by (𝜑 → ⊥), ⊥, 𝜑, ⊥, ⊥, the antecedent becomes ¬ ¬ (¬ ¬ 𝜑𝜑), that is, the double negation of the stability of 𝜑. If that statement were provable in minimal calculus, then, since plays no particular role in minimal calculus, also the statement with 𝜓 in place of would be provable. The corresponding consequent is (((𝜓𝜑) → 𝜓) → 𝜓), that is, the non-intuitionistic Peirce law. Therefore, the double negation of the stability of any formula is not provable in minimal calculus. However, it is provable both in intuitionistic calculus (see iset.mm/bj-nnst) and in classical refutability calculus (see bj-peircestab 34742). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Nov-2023.) (Revised by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(((((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒) → 𝜃) → 𝜏) → (((𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃) → 𝜏))
 
20.15.1.4  Positive calculus

Positive calculus is understood to be intuitionistic.

 
Theorembj-syl66ib 34744 A mixed syllogism inference derived from syl6ib 250. In addition to bj-dvelimdv1 35045, it can also shorten alexsubALTlem4 23210 (4821>4812), supsrlem 10876 (2868>2863). (Contributed by BJ, 20-Oct-2021.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜃))    &   (𝜃𝜏)    &   (𝜏𝜒)       (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))
 
Theorembj-orim2 34745 Proof of orim2 965 from the axiomatic definition of disjunction (olc 865, orc 864, jao 958) and minimal implicational calculus. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Apr-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((𝜑𝜓) → ((𝜒𝜑) → (𝜒𝜓)))
 
Theorembj-currypeirce 34746 Curry's axiom curryax 891 (a non-intuitionistic positive statement sometimes called a paradox of material implication) implies Peirce's axiom peirce 201 over minimal implicational calculus and the axiomatic definition of disjunction (actually, only the elimination axiom jao 958 via its inference form jaoi 854; the introduction axioms olc 865 and orc 864 are not needed). Note that this theorem shows that actually, the standard instance of curryax 891 implies the standard instance of peirce 201, which is not the case for the converse bj-peircecurry 34747. (Contributed by BJ, 15-Jun-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((𝜑 ∨ (𝜑𝜓)) → (((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜑) → 𝜑))
 
Theorembj-peircecurry 34747 Peirce's axiom peirce 201 implies Curry's axiom curryax 891 over minimal implicational calculus and the axiomatic definition of disjunction (actually, only the introduction axioms olc 865 and orc 864; the elimination axiom jao 958 is not needed). See bj-currypeirce 34746 for the converse. (Contributed by BJ, 15-Jun-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 ∨ (𝜑𝜓))
 
Theorembj-animbi 34748 Conjunction in terms of implication and biconditional. Note that the proof is intuitionistic (use of ax-3 8 comes from the unusual definition of the biconditional in set.mm). (Contributed by BJ, 23-Sep-2023.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theorembj-currypara 34749 Curry's paradox. Note that the proof is intuitionistic (use ax-3 8 comes from the unusual definition of the biconditional in set.mm). The paradox comes from the case where 𝜑 is the self-referential sentence "If this sentence is true, then 𝜓", so that one can prove everything. Therefore, a consistent system cannot allow the formation of such self-referential sentences. This has lead to the study of logics rejecting contraction pm2.43 56, such as affine logic and linear logic. (Contributed by BJ, 23-Sep-2023.)
((𝜑 ↔ (𝜑𝜓)) → 𝜓)
 
20.15.1.5  Implication and negation
 
Theorembj-con2com 34750 A commuted form of the contrapositive, true in minimal calculus. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.)
(𝜑 → ((𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑) → ¬ 𝜓))
 
Theorembj-con2comi 34751 Inference associated with bj-con2com 34750. Its associated inference is mt2 199. TODO: when in the main part, add to mt2 199 that it is the inference associated with bj-con2comi 34751. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.)
𝜑       ((𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑) → ¬ 𝜓)
 
Theorembj-pm2.01i 34752 Inference associated with the weak Clavius law pm2.01 188. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2020.)
(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑)        ¬ 𝜑
 
Theorembj-nimn 34753 If a formula is true, then it does not imply its negation. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.) A shorter proof is possible using id 22 and jc 161, however, the present proof uses theorems that are more basic than jc 161. (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑))
 
Theorembj-nimni 34754 Inference associated with bj-nimn 34753. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.)
𝜑        ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑)
 
Theorembj-peircei 34755 Inference associated with peirce 201. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2020.)
((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜑)       𝜑
 
Theorembj-looinvi 34756 Inference associated with looinv 202. Its associated inference is bj-looinvii 34757. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2020.)
((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜓)       ((𝜓𝜑) → 𝜑)
 
Theorembj-looinvii 34757 Inference associated with bj-looinvi 34756. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2020.)
((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜓)    &   (𝜓𝜑)       𝜑
 
Theorembj-mt2bi 34758 Version of mt2 199 where the major premise is a biconditional. Another proof is also possible via con2bii 358 and mpbi 229. The current mt2bi 364 should be relabeled, maybe to imfal. (Contributed by BJ, 5-Oct-2024.)
𝜑    &   (𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜑)        ¬ 𝜓
 
Theorembj-ntrufal 34759 The negation of a theorem is equivalent to false. This can shorten dfnul2 4260. (Contributed by BJ, 5-Oct-2024.)
𝜑       𝜑 ↔ ⊥)
 
Theorembj-fal 34760 Shortening of fal 1553 using bj-mt2bi 34758. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 11-Mar-2012.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
¬ ⊥
 
20.15.1.6  Disjunction

A few lemmas about disjunction. The fundamental theorems in this family are the dual statements pm4.71 558 and pm4.72 947. See also biort 933 and biorf 934.

 
Theorembj-jaoi1 34761 Shortens orfa2 36253 (58>53), pm1.2 901 (20>18), pm1.2 901 (20>18), pm2.4 904 (31>25), pm2.41 905 (31>25), pm2.42 940 (38>32), pm3.2ni 878 (43>39), pm4.44 994 (55>51). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.)
(𝜑𝜓)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜓)
 
Theorembj-jaoi2 34762 Shortens consensus 1050 (110>106), elnn0z 12341 (336>329), pm1.2 901 (20>19), pm3.2ni 878 (43>39), pm4.44 994 (55>51). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.)
(𝜑𝜓)       ((𝜓𝜑) → 𝜓)
 
20.15.1.7  Logical equivalence

A few other characterizations of the bicondional. The inter-definability of logical connectives offers many ways to express a given statement. Some useful theorems in this regard are df-or 845, df-an 397, pm4.64 846, imor 850, pm4.62 853 through pm4.67 399, and, for the De Morgan laws, ianor 979 through pm4.57 988.

 
Theorembj-dfbi4 34763 Alternate definition of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Oct-2019.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ ¬ (𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theorembj-dfbi5 34764 Alternate definition of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Oct-2019.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theorembj-dfbi6 34765 Alternate definition of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Oct-2019.)
((𝜑𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ↔ (𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theorembj-bijust0ALT 34766 Alternate proof of bijust0 203; shorter but using additional intermediate results. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1999.) (Proof shortened by Josh Purinton, 29-Dec-2000.) (Revised by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
¬ ((𝜑𝜑) → ¬ (𝜑𝜑))
 
Theorembj-bijust00 34767 A self-implication does not imply the negation of a self-implication. Most general theorem of which bijust 204 is an instance (bijust0 203 and bj-bijust0ALT 34766 are therefore also instances of it). (Contributed by BJ, 7-Sep-2022.)
¬ ((𝜑𝜑) → ¬ (𝜓𝜓))
 
20.15.1.8  The conditional operator for propositions
 
Theorembj-consensus 34768 Version of consensus 1050 expressed using the conditional operator. (Remark: it may be better to express it as consensus 1050, using only binary connectives, and hinting at the fact that it is a Boolean algebra identity, like the absorption identities.) (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.)
((if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓𝜒)) ↔ if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒))
 
Theorembj-consensusALT 34769 Alternate proof of bj-consensus 34768. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓𝜒)) ↔ if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒))
 
Theorembj-df-ifc 34770* Candidate definition for the conditional operator for classes. This is in line with the definition of a class as the extension of a predicate in df-clab 2717. We reprove the current df-if 4461 from it in bj-dfif 34771. (Contributed by BJ, 20-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
if(𝜑, 𝐴, 𝐵) = {𝑥 ∣ if-(𝜑, 𝑥𝐴, 𝑥𝐵)}
 
Theorembj-dfif 34771* Alternate definition of the conditional operator for classes, which used to be the main definition. (Contributed by BJ, 26-Dec-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
if(𝜑, 𝐴, 𝐵) = {𝑥 ∣ ((𝜑𝑥𝐴) ∨ (¬ 𝜑𝑥𝐵))}
 
Theorembj-ififc 34772 A biconditional connecting the conditional operator for propositions and the conditional operator for classes. Note that there is no sethood hypothesis on 𝑋: it is implied by either side. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) Generalize statement from setvar 𝑥 to class 𝑋. (Revised by BJ, 26-Dec-2023.)
(𝑋 ∈ if(𝜑, 𝐴, 𝐵) ↔ if-(𝜑, 𝑋𝐴, 𝑋𝐵))
 
20.15.1.9  Propositional calculus: miscellaneous

Miscellaneous theorems of propositional calculus.

 
Theorembj-imbi12 34773 Uncurried (imported) form of imbi12 347. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.)
(((𝜑𝜓) ∧ (𝜒𝜃)) → ((𝜑𝜒) ↔ (𝜓𝜃)))
 
Theorembj-biorfi 34774 This should be labeled "biorfi" while the current biorfi 936 should be labeled "biorfri". The dual of biorf 934 is not biantr 803 but iba 528 (and ibar 529). So there should also be a "biorfr". (Note that these four statements can actually be strengthened to biconditionals.) (Contributed by BJ, 26-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
¬ 𝜑       (𝜓 ↔ (𝜑𝜓))
 
Theorembj-falor 34775 Dual of truan 1550 (which has biconditional reversed). (Contributed by BJ, 26-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 ↔ (⊥ ∨ 𝜑))
 
Theorembj-falor2 34776 Dual of truan 1550. (Contributed by BJ, 26-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((⊥ ∨ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜑)
 
Theorembj-bibibi 34777 A property of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 26-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theorembj-imn3ani 34778 Duplication of bnj1224 32790. Three-fold version of imnani 401. (Contributed by Jonathan Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.) (Revised by BJ, 22-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
¬ (𝜑𝜓𝜒)       ((𝜑𝜓) → ¬ 𝜒)
 
Theorembj-andnotim 34779 Two ways of expressing a certain ternary connective. Note the respective positions of the three formulas on each side of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 6-Oct-2018.)
(((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) → 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ 𝜒))
 
Theorembj-bi3ant 34780 This used to be in the main part. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 14-May-2013.) (Revised by BJ, 14-Jun-2019.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (((𝜃𝜏) → 𝜑) → (((𝜏𝜃) → 𝜓) → ((𝜃𝜏) → 𝜒)))
 
Theorembj-bisym 34781 This used to be in the main part. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 14-May-2013.) (Revised by BJ, 14-Jun-2019.)
(((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜒𝜃)) → (((𝜓𝜑) → (𝜃𝜒)) → ((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜒𝜃))))
 
Theorembj-bixor 34782 Equivalence of two ternary operations. Note the identical order and parenthesizing of the three arguments in both expressions. (Contributed by BJ, 31-Dec-2023.)
((𝜑 ↔ (𝜓𝜒)) ↔ (𝜑 ⊻ (𝜓𝜒)))
 
20.15.2  Modal logic

In this section, we prove some theorems related to modal logic. For modal logic, we refer to https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kripke_semantics, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Modal_logic and https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-modal/.

Monadic first-order logic (i.e., with quantification over only one variable) is bi-interpretable with modal logic, by mapping 𝑥 to "necessity" (generally denoted by a box) and 𝑥 to "possibility" (generally denoted by a diamond). Therefore, we use these quantifiers so as not to introduce new symbols. (To be strictly within modal logic, we should add disjoint variable conditions between 𝑥 and any other metavariables appearing in the statements.)

For instance, ax-gen 1798 corresponds to the necessitation rule of modal logic, and ax-4 1812 corresponds to the distributivity axiom (K) of modal logic, also called the Kripke scheme. Modal logics satisfying these rule and axiom are called "normal modal logics", of which the most important modal logics are.

The minimal normal modal logic is also denoted by (K). Here are a few normal modal logics with their axiomatizations (on top of (K)): (K) axiomatized by no supplementary axioms; (T) axiomatized by the axiom T; (K4) axiomatized by the axiom 4; (S4) axiomatized by the axioms T,4; (S5) axiomatized by the axioms T,5 or D,B,4; (GL) axiomatized by the axiom GL.

The last one, called Gödel–Löb logic or provability logic, is important because it describes exactly the properties of provability in Peano arithmetic, as proved by Robert Solovay. See for instance https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-provability/ 1812. A basic result in this logic is bj-gl4 34786.

 
Theorembj-axdd2 34783 This implication, proved using only ax-gen 1798 and ax-4 1812 on top of propositional calculus (hence holding, up to the standard interpretation, in any normal modal logic), shows that the axiom scheme 𝑥 implies the axiom scheme (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑). These correspond to the modal axiom (D), and in predicate calculus, they assert that the universe of discourse is nonempty. For the converse, see bj-axd2d 34784. (Contributed by BJ, 16-May-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(∃𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∃𝑥𝜓))
 
Theorembj-axd2d 34784 This implication, proved using only ax-gen 1798 on top of propositional calculus (hence holding, up to the standard interpretation, in any modal logic), shows that the axiom scheme (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) implies the axiom scheme 𝑥. These correspond to the modal axiom (D), and in predicate calculus, they assert that the universe of discourse is nonempty. For the converse, see bj-axdd2 34783. (Contributed by BJ, 16-May-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((∀𝑥⊤ → ∃𝑥⊤) → ∃𝑥⊤)
 
Theorembj-axtd 34785 This implication, proved from propositional calculus only (hence holding, up to the standard interpretation, in any modal logic), shows that the axiom scheme (∀𝑥𝜑𝜑) (modal T) implies the axiom scheme (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) (modal D). See also bj-axdd2 34783 and bj-axd2d 34784. (Contributed by BJ, 16-May-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑) → ((∀𝑥𝜑𝜑) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑)))
 
Theorembj-gl4 34786 In a normal modal logic, the modal axiom GL implies the modal axiom (4). Translated to first-order logic, Axiom GL reads (∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑𝜑) → ∀𝑥𝜑). Note that the antecedent of bj-gl4 34786 is an instance of the axiom GL, with 𝜑 replaced by (∀𝑥𝜑𝜑), which is a modality sometimes called the "strong necessity" of 𝜑. (Contributed by BJ, 12-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((∀𝑥(∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑𝜑) → (∀𝑥𝜑𝜑)) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑𝜑)) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑥𝜑))
 
Theorembj-axc4 34787 Over minimal calculus, the modal axiom (4) (hba1 2291) and the modal axiom (K) (ax-4 1812) together imply axc4 2316. (Contributed by BJ, 29-Nov-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝑥𝜑) → ((∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) → (∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓))))
 
20.15.3  Provability logic

In this section, we assume that, on top of propositional calculus, there is given a provability predicate Prv satisfying the three axioms ax-prv1 34789 and ax-prv2 34790 and ax-prv3 34791. Note the similarity with ax-gen 1798, ax-4 1812 and hba1 2291 respectively. These three properties of Prv are often called the Hilbert–Bernays–Löb derivability conditions, or the Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions.

This corresponds to the modal logic (K4) (see previous section for modal logic). The interpretation of provability logic is the following: we are given a background first-order theory T, the wff Prv 𝜑 means "𝜑 is provable in T", and the turnstile indicates provability in T.

Beware that "provability logic" often means (K) augmented with the Gödel–Löb axiom GL, which we do not assume here (at least for the moment). See for instance https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-provability/ 2291.

Provability logic is worth studying because whenever T is a first-order theory containing Robinson arithmetic (a fragment of Peano arithmetic), one can prove (using Gödel numbering, and in the much weaker primitive recursive arithmetic) that there exists in T a provability predicate Prv satisfying the above three axioms. (We do not construct this predicate in this section; this is still a project.)

The main theorems of this section are the "easy parts" of the proofs of Gödel's second incompleteness theorem (bj-babygodel 34794) and Löb's theorem (bj-babylob 34795). See the comments of these theorems for details.

 
Syntaxcprvb 34788 Syntax for the provability predicate.
wff Prv 𝜑
 
Axiomax-prv1 34789 First property of three of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.)
𝜑       Prv 𝜑
 
Axiomax-prv2 34790 Second property of three of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.)
(Prv (𝜑𝜓) → (Prv 𝜑 → Prv 𝜓))
 
Axiomax-prv3 34791 Third property of three of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.)
(Prv 𝜑 → Prv Prv 𝜑)
 
Theoremprvlem1 34792 An elementary property of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (Prv 𝜑 → Prv 𝜓)
 
Theoremprvlem2 34793 An elementary property of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (Prv 𝜑 → (Prv 𝜓 → Prv 𝜒))
 
Theorembj-babygodel 34794 See the section header comments for the context.

The first hypothesis reads "𝜑 is true if and only if it is not provable in T" (and having this first hypothesis means that we can prove this fact in T). The wff 𝜑 is a formal version of the sentence "This sentence is not provable". The hard part of the proof of Gödel's theorem is to construct such a 𝜑, called a "Gödel–Rosser sentence", for a first-order theory T which is effectively axiomatizable and contains Robinson arithmetic, through Gödel diagonalization (this can be done in primitive recursive arithmetic). The second hypothesis means that is not provable in T, that is, that the theory T is consistent (and having this second hypothesis means that we can prove in T that the theory T is consistent). The conclusion is the falsity, so having the conclusion means that T can prove the falsity, that is, T is inconsistent.

Therefore, taking the contrapositive, this theorem expresses that if a first-order theory is consistent (and one can prove in it that some formula is true if and only if it is not provable in it), then this theory does not prove its own consistency.

This proof is due to George Boolos, Gödel's Second Incompleteness Theorem Explained in Words of One Syllable, Mind, New Series, Vol. 103, No. 409 (January 1994), pp. 1--3.

(Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.)

(𝜑 ↔ ¬ Prv 𝜑)    &    ¬ Prv ⊥       
 
Theorembj-babylob 34795 See the section header comments for the context, as well as the comments for bj-babygodel 34794.

Löb's theorem when the Löb sentence is given as a hypothesis (the hard part of the proof of Löb's theorem is to construct this Löb sentence; this can be done, using Gödel diagonalization, for any first-order effectively axiomatizable theory containing Robinson arithmetic). More precisely, the present theorem states that if a first-order theory proves that the provability of a given sentence entails its truth (and if one can construct in this theory a provability predicate and a Löb sentence, given here as the first hypothesis), then the theory actually proves that sentence.

See for instance, Eliezer Yudkowsky, The Cartoon Guide to Löb's Theorem (available at http://yudkowsky.net/rational/lobs-theorem/ 34794).

(Contributed by BJ, 20-Apr-2019.)

(𝜓 ↔ (Prv 𝜓𝜑))    &   (Prv 𝜑𝜑)       𝜑
 
Theorembj-godellob 34796 Proof of Gödel's theorem from Löb's theorem (see comments at bj-babygodel 34794 and bj-babylob 34795 for details). (Contributed by BJ, 20-Apr-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 ↔ ¬ Prv 𝜑)    &    ¬ Prv ⊥       
 
20.15.4  First-order logic

Utility lemmas or strengthenings of theorems in the main part (biconditional or closed forms, or fewer disjoint variable conditions, or disjoint variable conditions replaced with nonfreeness hypotheses...). Sorted in the same order as in the main part.

 
20.15.4.1  Adding ax-gen
 
Theorembj-genr 34797 Generalization rule on the right conjunct. See 19.28 2222. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorembj-genl 34798 Generalization rule on the left conjunct. See 19.27 2221. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝜑𝜓)
 
Theorembj-genan 34799 Generalization rule on a conjunction. Forward inference associated with 19.26 1874. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Jul-2021.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓)
 
Theorembj-mpgs 34800 From a closed form theorem (the major premise) with an antecedent in the "strong necessity" modality (in the language of modal logic), deduce the inference 𝜑𝜓. Strong necessity is stronger than necessity, and equivalent to it when sp 2177 (modal T) is available. Therefore, this theorem is stronger than mpg 1800 when sp 2177 is not available. (Contributed by BJ, 1-Nov-2023.)
𝜑    &   ((𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜑) → 𝜓)       𝜓
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13300 134 13301-13400 135 13401-13500 136 13501-13600 137 13601-13700 138 13701-13800 139 13801-13900 140 13901-14000 141 14001-14100 142 14101-14200 143 14201-14300 144 14301-14400 145 14401-14500 146 14501-14600 147 14601-14700 148 14701-14800 149 14801-14900 150 14901-15000 151 15001-15100 152 15101-15200 153 15201-15300 154 15301-15400 155 15401-15500 156 15501-15600 157 15601-15700 158 15701-15800 159 15801-15900 160 15901-16000 161 16001-16100 162 16101-16200 163 16201-16300 164 16301-16400 165 16401-16500 166 16501-16600 167 16601-16700 168 16701-16800 169 16801-16900 170 16901-17000 171 17001-17100 172 17101-17200 173 17201-17300 174 17301-17400 175 17401-17500 176 17501-17600 177 17601-17700 178 17701-17800 179 17801-17900 180 17901-18000 181 18001-18100 182 18101-18200 183 18201-18300 184 18301-18400 185 18401-18500 186 18501-18600 187 18601-18700 188 18701-18800 189 18801-18900 190 18901-19000 191 19001-19100 192 19101-19200 193 19201-19300 194 19301-19400 195 19401-19500 196 19501-19600 197 19601-19700 198 19701-19800 199 19801-19900 200 19901-20000 201 20001-20100 202 20101-20200 203 20201-20300 204 20301-20400 205 20401-20500 206 20501-20600 207 20601-20700 208 20701-20800 209 20801-20900 210 20901-21000 211 21001-21100 212 21101-21200 213 21201-21300 214 21301-21400 215 21401-21500 216 21501-21600 217 21601-21700 218 21701-21800 219 21801-21900 220 21901-22000 221 22001-22100 222 22101-22200 223 22201-22300 224 22301-22400 225 22401-22500 226 22501-22600 227 22601-22700 228 22701-22800 229 22801-22900 230 22901-23000 231 23001-23100 232 23101-23200 233 23201-23300 234 23301-23400 235 23401-23500 236 23501-23600 237 23601-23700 238 23701-23800 239 23801-23900 240 23901-24000 241 24001-24100 242 24101-24200 243 24201-24300 244 24301-24400 245 24401-24500 246 24501-24600 247 24601-24700 248 24701-24800 249 24801-24900 250 24901-25000 251 25001-25100 252 25101-25200 253 25201-25300 254 25301-25400 255 25401-25500 256 25501-25600 257 25601-25700 258 25701-25800 259 25801-25900 260 25901-26000 261 26001-26100 262 26101-26200 263 26201-26300 264 26301-26400 265 26401-26500 266 26501-26600 267 26601-26700 268 26701-26800 269 26801-26900 270 26901-27000 271 27001-27100 272 27101-27200 273 27201-27300 274 27301-27400 275 27401-27500 276 27501-27600 277 27601-27700 278 27701-27800 279 27801-27900 280 27901-28000 281 28001-28100 282 28101-28200 283 28201-28300 284 28301-28400 285 28401-28500 286 28501-28600 287 28601-28700 288 28701-28800 289 28801-28900 290 28901-29000 291 29001-29100 292 29101-29200 293 29201-29300 294 29301-29400 295 29401-29500 296 29501-29600 297 29601-29700 298 29701-29800 299 29801-29900 300 29901-30000 301 30001-30100 302 30101-30200 303 30201-30300 304 30301-30400 305 30401-30500 306 30501-30600 307 30601-30700 308 30701-30800 309 30801-30900 310 30901-31000 311 31001-31100 312 31101-31200 313 31201-31300 314 31301-31400 315 31401-31500 316 31501-31600 317 31601-31700 318 31701-31800 319 31801-31900 320 31901-32000 321 32001-32100 322 32101-32200 323 32201-32300 324 32301-32400 325 32401-32500 326 32501-32600 327 32601-32700 328 32701-32800 329 32801-32900 330 32901-33000 331 33001-33100 332 33101-33200 333 33201-33300 334 33301-33400 335 33401-33500 336 33501-33600 337 33601-33700 338 33701-33800 339 33801-33900 340 33901-34000 341 34001-34100 342 34101-34200 343 34201-34300 344 34301-34400 345 34401-34500 346 34501-34600 347 34601-34700 348 34701-34800 349 34801-34900 350 34901-35000 351 35001-35100 352 35101-35200 353 35201-35300 354 35301-35400 355 35401-35500 356 35501-35600 357 35601-35700 358 35701-35800 359 35801-35900 360 35901-36000 361 36001-36100 362 36101-36200 363 36201-36300 364 36301-36400 365 36401-36500 366 36501-36600 367 36601-36700 368 36701-36800 369 36801-36900 370 36901-37000 371 37001-37100 372 37101-37200 373 37201-37300 374 37301-37400 375 37401-37500 376 37501-37600 377 37601-37700 378 37701-37800 379 37801-37900 380 37901-38000 381 38001-38100 382 38101-38200 383 38201-38300 384 38301-38400 385 38401-38500 386 38501-38600 387 38601-38700 388 38701-38800 389 38801-38900 390 38901-39000 391 39001-39100 392 39101-39200 393 39201-39300 394 39301-39400 395 39401-39500 396 39501-39600 397 39601-39700 398 39701-39800 399 39801-39900 400 39901-40000 401 40001-40100 402 40101-40200 403 40201-40300 404 40301-40400 405 40401-40500 406 40501-40600 407 40601-40700 408 40701-40800 409 40801-40900 410 40901-41000 411 41001-41100 412 41101-41200 413 41201-41300 414 41301-41400 415 41401-41500 416 41501-41600 417 41601-41700 418 41701-41800 419 41801-41900 420 41901-42000 421 42001-42100 422 42101-42200 423 42201-42300 424 42301-42400 425 42401-42500 426 42501-42600 427 42601-42700 428 42701-42800 429 42801-42900 430 42901-43000 431 43001-43100 432 43101-43200 433 43201-43300 434 43301-43400 435 43401-43500 436 43501-43600 437 43601-43700 438 43701-43800 439 43801-43900 440 43901-44000 441 44001-44100 442 44101-44200 443 44201-44300 444 44301-44400 445 44401-44500 446 44501-44600 447 44601-44700 448 44701-44800 449 44801-44900 450 44901-45000 451 45001-45100 452 45101-45200 453 45201-45300 454 45301-45400 455 45401-45500 456 45501-45600 457 45601-45700 458 45701-45800 459 45801-45900 460 45901-46000 461 46001-46100 462 46101-46200 463 46201-46300 464 46301-46400 465 46401-46500 466 46501-46532
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >