![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 53 of 491) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30946) |
![]() (30947-32469) |
![]() (32470-49035) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | sbcbr123 5201 | Move substitution in and out of a binary relation. (Contributed by NM, 13-Dec-2005.) (Revised by NM, 22-Aug-2018.) |
⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝐵𝑅𝐶 ↔ ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐵⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝑅⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐶) | ||
Theorem | sbcbr 5202* | Move substitution in and out of a binary relation. (Contributed by NM, 23-Aug-2018.) |
⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝐵𝑅𝐶 ↔ 𝐵⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝑅𝐶) | ||
Theorem | sbcbr12g 5203* | Move substitution in and out of a binary relation. (Contributed by NM, 13-Dec-2005.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝐵𝑅𝐶 ↔ ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐵𝑅⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | sbcbr1g 5204* | Move substitution in and out of a binary relation. (Contributed by NM, 13-Dec-2005.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝐵𝑅𝐶 ↔ ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐵𝑅𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | sbcbr2g 5205* | Move substitution in and out of a binary relation. (Contributed by NM, 13-Dec-2005.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝐵𝑅𝐶 ↔ 𝐵𝑅⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | brsymdif 5206 | Characterization of the symmetric difference of two binary relations. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 11-Apr-2012.) |
⊢ (𝐴(𝑅 △ 𝑆)𝐵 ↔ ¬ (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ↔ 𝐴𝑆𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | brralrspcev 5207* | Restricted existential specialization with a restricted universal quantifier over a relation, closed form. (Contributed by AV, 20-Aug-2022.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑌 𝐴𝑅𝐵) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑌 𝐴𝑅𝑥) | ||
Theorem | brimralrspcev 5208* | Restricted existential specialization with a restricted universal quantifier over an implication with a relation in the antecedent, closed form. (Contributed by AV, 20-Aug-2022.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑌 ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴𝑅𝐵) → 𝜓)) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑌 ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴𝑅𝑥) → 𝜓)) | ||
Syntax | copab 5209 | Extend class notation to include ordered-pair class abstraction (class builder). |
class {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} | ||
Definition | df-opab 5210* | Define the class abstraction of a collection of ordered pairs. Definition 3.3 of [Monk1] p. 34. Usually 𝑥 and 𝑦 are distinct, although the definition does not require it (see dfid2 5584 for a case where they are not distinct). The brace notation is called "class abstraction" by Quine; it is also called "class builder" in the literature. An alternate definition using no existential quantifiers is shown by dfopab2 8075. An example is given by ex-opab 30460. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑧 ∣ ∃𝑥∃𝑦(𝑧 = 〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∧ 𝜑)} | ||
Theorem | opabss 5211* | The collection of ordered pairs in a class is a subclass of it. (Contributed by NM, 27-Dec-1996.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝑥𝑅𝑦} ⊆ 𝑅 | ||
Theorem | opabbid 5212 | Equivalent wff's yield equal ordered-pair class abstractions (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 21-Feb-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓} = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜒}) | ||
Theorem | opabbidv 5213* | Equivalent wff's yield equal ordered-pair class abstractions (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 15-May-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓} = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜒}) | ||
Theorem | opabbii 5214 | Equivalent wff's yield equal class abstractions. (Contributed by NM, 15-May-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | nfopabd 5215* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for class abstraction. Deduction form. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 26-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑧𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑧{〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓}) | ||
Theorem | nfopab 5216* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for class abstraction. (Contributed by NM, 1-Sep-1999.) Remove disjoint variable conditions. (Revised by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) (Revised by Scott Fenton, 26-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑧{〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} | ||
Theorem | nfopab1 5217 | The first abstraction variable in an ordered-pair class abstraction is effectively not free. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥{〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} | ||
Theorem | nfopab2 5218 | The second abstraction variable in an ordered-pair class abstraction is effectively not free. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦{〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab 5219* | Rule used to change bound variables in an ordered-pair class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑤𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜓 & ⊢ ((𝑥 = 𝑧 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑤〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopabv 5220* | Rule used to change bound variables in an ordered-pair class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 15-Oct-1996.) Reduce axiom usage. (Revised by GG, 15-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 = 𝑧 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑤〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopabvOLD 5221* | Obsolete version of cbvopabv 5220 as of 15-Oct-2024. (Contributed by NM, 15-Oct-1996.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 = 𝑧 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝑤) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑤〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab1 5222* | Change first bound variable in an ordered-pair class abstraction, using explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 6-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) Add disjoint variable condition to avoid ax-13 2374. See cbvopab1g 5223 for a less restrictive version requiring more axioms. (Revised by GG, 17-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab1g 5223* | Change first bound variable in an ordered-pair class abstraction, using explicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2374. See cbvopab1 5222 for a version with more disjoint variable conditions, but not requiring ax-13 2374. (Contributed by NM, 6-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab2 5224* | Change second bound variable in an ordered-pair class abstraction, using explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 22-Aug-2013.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑥, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab1s 5225* | Change first bound variable in an ordered-pair class abstraction, using explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-2003.) |
⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑦〉 ∣ [𝑧 / 𝑥]𝜑} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab1v 5226* | Rule used to change the first bound variable in an ordered pair abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-2003.) (Proof shortened by Eric Schmidt, 4-Apr-2007.) Reduce axiom usage. (Revised by GG, 17-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab1vOLD 5227* | Obsolete version of cbvopab1v 5226 as of 17-Nov-2024. (Contributed by NM, 31-Jul-2003.) (Proof shortened by Eric Schmidt, 4-Apr-2007.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑧, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | cbvopab2v 5228* | Rule used to change the second bound variable in an ordered pair abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Sep-1999.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} = {〈𝑥, 𝑧〉 ∣ 𝜓} | ||
Theorem | unopab 5229 | Union of two ordered pair class abstractions. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2002.) |
⊢ ({〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜑} ∪ {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝜓}) = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)} | ||
Syntax | cmpt 5230 | Extend the definition of a class to include maps-to notation for defining a function via a rule. |
class (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) | ||
Definition | df-mpt 5231* | Define maps-to notation for defining a function via a rule. Read as "the function which maps 𝑥 (in 𝐴) to 𝐵(𝑥)". The class expression 𝐵 is the value of the function at 𝑥 and normally contains the variable 𝑥. An example is the square function for complex numbers, (𝑥 ∈ ℂ ↦ (𝑥↑2)). Similar to the definition of mapping in [ChoquetDD] p. 2. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2008.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝐵)} | ||
Theorem | mpteq12da 5232 | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 23-Oct-2021.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2138. (Revised by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12df 5233 | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. Compare mpteq12dv 5238. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Dec-2016.) (Proof shortened by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12dfOLD 5234 | Obsolete version of mpteq12df 5233 as of 11-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Aug-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Dec-2016.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12f 5235 | An equality theorem for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥 𝐴 = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = 𝐷) → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12dva 5236* | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jan-2017.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2138, ax-12 2174. (Revised by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12dvaOLD 5237* | Obsolete version of mpteq12dva 5236 as of 11-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jan-2017.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12dv 5238* | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by NM, 24-Aug-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2138, ax-12 2174. (Revised by SN and GG, 1-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12 5239* | An equality theorem for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by NM, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = 𝐷) → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq1 5240* | An equality theorem for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) (Proof shortened by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq1OLD 5241* | Obsolete version of mpteq1 5240 as of 11-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq1d 5242* | An equality theorem for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq1i 5243 | An equality theorem for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 17-Aug-2020.) Remove all disjoint variable conditions. (Revised by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mpteq1iOLD 5244* | Obsolete version of mpteq1i 5243 as of 15-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 17-Aug-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2da 5245 | Slightly more general equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by FL, 14-Sep-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) (Proof shortened by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2daOLD 5246 | Obsolete version of mpteq2da 5245 as of 11-Nov-2024. (Contributed by FL, 14-Sep-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2dva 5247* | Slightly more general equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Apr-2012.) Remove dependency on ax-10 2138. (Revised by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2dvaOLD 5248* | Obsolete version of mpteq2dva 5247 as of 11-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Apr-2012.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2dv 5249* | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Aug-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2ia 5250 | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) (Proof shortened by SN, 11-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2iaOLD 5251 | Obsolete version of mpteq2ia 5250 as of 11-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mpteq2i 5252 | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐵 = 𝐶 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mpteq12i 5253 | An equality inference for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 27-Oct-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐶 & ⊢ 𝐵 = 𝐷 ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 ↦ 𝐷) | ||
Theorem | nfmpt 5254* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by NM, 20-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐵 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | nfmpt1 5255 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the maps-to notation. (Contributed by FL, 17-Feb-2008.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | cbvmptf 5256* | Rule to change the bound variable in a maps-to function, using implicit substitution. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2011.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 9-Mar-2017.) Add disjoint variable condition to avoid ax-13 2374. See cbvmptfg 5257 for a less restrictive version requiring more axioms. (Revised by GG, 17-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐶 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvmptfg 5257 | Rule to change the bound variable in a maps-to function, using implicit substitution. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2374. See cbvmptf 5256 for a version with more disjoint variable conditions, but not requiring ax-13 2374. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2011.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 9-Mar-2017.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐶 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvmpt 5258* | Rule to change the bound variable in a maps-to function, using implicit substitution. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2011.) Add disjoint variable condition to avoid ax-13 2374. See cbvmptg 5259 for a less restrictive version requiring more axioms. (Revised by GG, 17-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐶 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvmptg 5259* | Rule to change the bound variable in a maps-to function, using implicit substitution. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2374. See cbvmpt 5258 for a version with more disjoint variable conditions, but not requiring ax-13 2374. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2011.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐶 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvmptv 5260* | Rule to change the bound variable in a maps-to function, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 19-Feb-2013.) Add disjoint variable condition to avoid auxiliary axioms . See cbvmptvg 5262 for a less restrictive version requiring more axioms. (Revised by GG, 17-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvmptvOLD 5261* | Obsolete version of cbvmptv 5260 as of 17-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 19-Feb-2013.) Add disjoint variable condition to avoid ax-13 2374. See cbvmptvg 5262 for a less restrictive version requiring more axioms. (Revised by GG, 17-Jan-2024.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | cbvmptvg 5262* | Rule to change the bound variable in a maps-to function, using implicit substitution. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2374. See cbvmptv 5260 for a version with more disjoint variable conditions, but not requiring ax-13 2374. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 19-Feb-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | mptv 5263* | Function with universal domain in maps-to notation. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ 𝐵) = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝑦 = 𝐵} | ||
Syntax | wtr 5264 | Extend wff notation to include transitive classes. Notation from [TakeutiZaring] p. 35. |
wff Tr 𝐴 | ||
Definition | df-tr 5265 | Define the transitive class predicate. Not to be confused with a transitive relation (see cotr 6132). Definition of [Enderton] p. 71 extended to arbitrary classes. For alternate definitions, see dftr2 5266 (which is suggestive of the word "transitive"), dftr2c 5267, dftr3 5270, dftr4 5271, dftr5 5268, and (when 𝐴 is a set) unisuc 6464. The term "complete" is used instead of "transitive" in Definition 3 of [Suppes] p. 130. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∪ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dftr2 5266* | An alternate way of defining a transitive class. Exercise 7 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 40. Using dftr2c 5267 instead may avoid dependences on ax-11 2154. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥∀𝑦((𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dftr2c 5267* | Variant of dftr2 5266 with commuted quantifiers, useful for shortening proofs and avoiding ax-11 2154. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 28-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑦∀𝑥((𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dftr5 5268* | An alternate way of defining a transitive class. Definition 1.1 of [Schloeder] p. 1. (Contributed by NM, 20-Mar-2004.) Avoid ax-11 2154. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 28-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dftr5OLD 5269* | Obsolete version of dftr5 5268 as of 28-Dec-2024. (Contributed by NM, 20-Mar-2004.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dftr3 5270* | An alternate way of defining a transitive class. Definition 7.1 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 35. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dftr4 5271 | An alternate way of defining a transitive class. Definition of [Enderton] p. 71. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝒫 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | treq 5272 | Equality theorem for the transitive class predicate. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1993.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (Tr 𝐴 ↔ Tr 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | trel 5273 | In a transitive class, the membership relation is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 19-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 9-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 → ((𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | trel3 5274 | In a transitive class, the membership relation is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 19-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 → ((𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | trss 5275 | An element of a transitive class is a subset of the class. (Contributed by NM, 7-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by JJ, 26-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 → (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | trin 5276 | The intersection of transitive classes is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 9-May-1994.) |
⊢ ((Tr 𝐴 ∧ Tr 𝐵) → Tr (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | tr0 5277 | The empty set is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 16-Sep-1993.) |
⊢ Tr ∅ | ||
Theorem | trv 5278 | The universe is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 14-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ Tr V | ||
Theorem | triun 5279 | An indexed union of a class of transitive sets is transitive. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 Tr 𝐵 → Tr ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | truni 5280* | The union of a class of transitive sets is transitive. Exercise 5(a) of [Enderton] p. 73. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Feb-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2014.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 Tr 𝑥 → Tr ∪ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | triin 5281 | An indexed intersection of a class of transitive sets is transitive. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Oct-2022.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 Tr 𝐵 → Tr ∩ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | trint 5282* | The intersection of a class of transitive sets is transitive. Exercise 5(b) of [Enderton] p. 73. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Feb-2011.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 3-Oct-2022.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 Tr 𝑥 → Tr ∩ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | trintss 5283 | Any nonempty transitive class includes its intersection. Exercise 3 in [TakeutiZaring] p. 44 (which mistakenly does not include the nonemptiness hypothesis). (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 3-Mar-2011.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 14-Nov-2011.) |
⊢ ((Tr 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → ∩ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Axiom | ax-rep 5284* |
Axiom of Replacement. An axiom scheme of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory.
Axiom 5 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 19.
It tells us that the image of any set
under a function is also a set (see the variant funimaex 6655). Although
𝜑 may be any wff whatsoever, this
axiom is useful (i.e. its
antecedent is satisfied) when we are given some function and 𝜑
encodes the predicate "the value of the function at 𝑤 is
𝑧".
Thus, 𝜑 will ordinarily have free variables
𝑤
and 𝑧- think
of it informally as 𝜑(𝑤, 𝑧). We prefix 𝜑 with the
quantifier ∀𝑦 in order to "protect" the
axiom from any 𝜑
containing 𝑦, thus allowing us to eliminate any
restrictions on
𝜑. Another common variant is derived
as axrep5 5292, where you can
find some further remarks. A slightly more compact version is shown as
axrep2 5287. A quite different variant is zfrep6 7977, which if used in
place of ax-rep 5284 would also require that the Separation Scheme
axsep 5300
be stated as a separate axiom.
There is a very strong generalization of Replacement that doesn't demand function-like behavior of 𝜑. Two versions of this generalization are called the Collection Principle cp 9928 and the Boundedness Axiom bnd 9929. Many developments of set theory distinguish the uses of Replacement from uses of the weaker axioms of Separation axsep 5300, Null Set axnul 5310, and Pairing axpr 5432, all of which we derive from Replacement. In order to make it easier to identify the uses of those redundant axioms, we restate them as Axioms ax-sep 5301, ax-nul 5311, and ax-pr 5437 below the theorems that prove them. (Contributed by NM, 23-Dec-1993.) |
⊢ (∀𝑤∃𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑦𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ ∃𝑤(𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axrep1 5285* | The version of the Axiom of Replacement used in the Metamath Solitaire applet https://us.metamath.org/mmsolitaire/mms.html. Equivalence is shown via the path ax-rep 5284 → axrep1 5285 → axrep2 5287 → axrepnd 10631 → zfcndrep 10651 = ax-rep 5284. (Contributed by NM, 19-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-Nov-2016.) Remove dependency on ax-13 2374. (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥(∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axreplem 5286* | Lemma for axrep2 5287 and axrep3 5288. (Contributed by BJ, 6-Aug-2022.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∃𝑢(𝜑 → ∀𝑣(𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑤(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜒))) ↔ ∃𝑢(𝜑 → ∀𝑣(𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑤(𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ 𝜒))))) | ||
Theorem | axrep2 5287* | Axiom of Replacement expressed with the fewest number of different variables and without any restrictions on 𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) Remove dependency on ax-13 2374. (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥(∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axrep3 5288* | Axiom of Replacement slightly strengthened from axrep2 5287; 𝑤 may occur free in 𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-1997.) Remove dependency on ax-13 2374. (Revised by BJ, 31-May-2019.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥(∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axrep4v 5289* | Version of axrep4 5290 with a disjoint variable condition, requiring fewer axioms. (Contributed by Matthew House, 18-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝑦 = 𝑧) → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axrep4 5290* | A more traditional version of the Axiom of Replacement. (Contributed by NM, 14-Aug-1994.) (Proof shortened by Matthew House, 18-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝑦 = 𝑧) → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axrep4OLD 5291* | Obsolete version of axrep4 5290 as of 18-Sep-2025. (Contributed by NM, 14-Aug-1994.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝑦 = 𝑧) → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axrep5 5292* | Axiom of Replacement (similar to Axiom Rep of [BellMachover] p. 463). The antecedent tells us 𝜑 is analogous to a "function" from 𝑥 to 𝑦 (although it is not really a function since it is a wff and not a class). In the consequent we postulate the existence of a set 𝑧 that corresponds to the "image" of 𝜑 restricted to some other set 𝑤. The hypothesis says 𝑧 must not be free in 𝜑. (Contributed by NM, 26-Nov-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑧𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑤 → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axrep6 5293* | A condensed form of ax-rep 5284. (Contributed by SN, 18-Sep-2023.) (Proof shortened by Matthew House, 18-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ (∀𝑤∃*𝑧𝜑 → ∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | axrep6OLD 5294* | Obsolete version of axrep6 5293 as of 18-Sep-2025. (Contributed by SN, 18-Sep-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑤∃*𝑧𝜑 → ∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | axrep6g 5295* | axrep6 5293 in class notation. It is equivalent to both ax-rep 5284 and abrexexg 7983, providing a direct link between the two. (Contributed by SN, 11-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦𝜓) → {𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | zfrepclf 5296* | An inference based on the Axiom of Replacement. Typically, 𝜑 defines a function from 𝑥 to 𝑦. (Contributed by NM, 26-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | zfrep3cl 5297* | An inference based on the Axiom of Replacement. Typically, 𝜑 defines a function from 𝑥 to 𝑦. (Contributed by NM, 26-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | zfrep4 5298* | A version of Replacement using class abstractions. (Contributed by NM, 26-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ∈ V & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑧∀𝑦(𝜓 → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑦 ∣ ∃𝑥(𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)} ∈ V | ||
Theorem | axsepgfromrep 5299* | A more general version axsepg 5302 of the axiom scheme of separation ax-sep 5301 derived from the axiom scheme of replacement ax-rep 5284 (and first-order logic). The extra generality consists in the absence of a disjoint variable condition on 𝑧, 𝜑 (that is, variable 𝑧 may occur in formula 𝜑). See linked statements for more information. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2006.) Remove dependencies on ax-9 2115 to ax-13 2374. (Revised by SN, 25-Sep-2023.) Use ax-sep 5301 instead (or axsepg 5302 if the extra generality is needed). (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑦∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | axsep 5300* | Axiom scheme of separation ax-sep 5301 derived from the axiom scheme of replacement ax-rep 5284. The statement is identical to that of ax-sep 5301, and therefore shows that ax-sep 5301 is redundant when ax-rep 5284 is allowed. See ax-sep 5301 for more information. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2006.) Use ax-sep 5301 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑦∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝜑)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |