HomeHome Metamath Proof Explorer
Theorem List (p. 357 of 466)
< Previous  Next >
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version.

Mirrors  >  Metamath Home Page  >  MPE Home Page  >  Theorem List Contents  >  Recent Proofs       This page: Page List

Color key:    Metamath Proof Explorer  Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29289)
  Hilbert Space Explorer  Hilbert Space Explorer
(29290-30812)
  Users' Mathboxes  Users' Mathboxes
(30813-46532)
 

Theorem List for Metamath Proof Explorer - 35601-35700   *Has distinct variable group(s)
TypeLabelDescription
Statement
 
Axiomax-luk3 35601 3 of 3 axioms for propositional calculus due to Lukasiewicz. Copy of luk-3 1660 and pm2.24 124, but introduced as an axiom. One might think that the similar pm2.21 123 𝜑 → (𝜑𝜓)) is a valid replacement for this axiom. But this is not true, ax-3 8 is not derivable from this modification. This can be shown by designing carefully operators ¬ and on a finite set of primitive statements. In propositional logic such statements are and , but we can assume more and other primitives in our universe of statements. So we denote our primitive statements as phi0 , phi1 and phi2. The actual meaning of the statements are not important in this context, it rather counts how they behave under our operations ¬ and , and which of them we assume to hold unconditionally (phi1, phi2). For our disproving model, I give that information in tabular form below. The interested reader may check by hand, that all possible interpretations of ax-mp 5, ax-luk1 35599, ax-luk2 35600 and pm2.21 123 result in phi1 or phi2, meaning they always hold. But for wl-luk-ax3 35613 we can find a counter example resulting in phi0, not a statement always true. The verification of a particular set of axioms in a given model is tedious and error prone, so I wrote a computer program, first checking this for me, and second, hunting for a counter example. Here is the result, after 9165 fruitlessly computer generated models:

ax-3 fails for phi2, phi2
number of statements: 3
always true phi1 phi2

Negation is defined as
----------------------------------------------------------------------
-. phi0-. phi1-. phi2
phi1phi0phi1

Implication is defined as
----------------------------------------------------------------------
p->qq: phi0q: phi1q: phi2
p: phi0phi1phi1phi1
p: phi1phi0phi1phi1
p: phi2phi0phi0phi0

(Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (¬ 𝜑𝜓))
 
20.18.1  1. Bootstrapping
 
Theoremwl-section-boot 35602 In this section, I provide the first steps needed for convenient proving. The presented theorems follow no common concept other than being useful in themselves, and apt to rederive ax-1 6, ax-2 7 and ax-3 8. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑       𝜑
 
Theoremwl-luk-imim1i 35603 Inference adding common consequents in an implication, thereby interchanging the original antecedent and consequent. Copy of imim1i 63 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.)
(𝜑𝜓)       ((𝜓𝜒) → (𝜑𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-luk-syl 35604 An inference version of the transitive laws for implication luk-1 1658. Copy of syl 17 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜓𝜒)       (𝜑𝜒)
 
Theoremwl-luk-imtrid 35605 A syllogism rule of inference. The first premise is used to replace the second antecedent of the second premise. Copy of syl5 34 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜃))       (𝜒 → (𝜑𝜃))
 
Theoremwl-luk-pm2.18d 35606 Deduction based on reductio ad absurdum. Copy of pm2.18d 127 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓𝜓))       (𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremwl-luk-con4i 35607 Inference rule. Copy of con4i 114 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓)       (𝜓𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-luk-pm2.24i 35608 Inference rule. Copy of pm2.24i 150 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑       𝜑𝜓)
 
Theoremwl-luk-a1i 35609 Inference rule. Copy of a1i 11 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑       (𝜓𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-luk-mpi 35610 A nested modus ponens inference. Copy of mpi 20 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜓    &   (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑𝜒)
 
Theoremwl-luk-imim2i 35611 Inference adding common antecedents in an implication. Copy of imim2i 16 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑𝜓)       ((𝜒𝜑) → (𝜒𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-luk-imtrdi 35612 A syllogism rule of inference. The second premise is used to replace the consequent of the first premise. Copy of syl6 35 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   (𝜒𝜃)       (𝜑 → (𝜓𝜃))
 
Theoremwl-luk-ax3 35613 ax-3 8 proved from Lukasiewicz's axioms. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((¬ 𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) → (𝜓𝜑))
 
Theoremwl-luk-ax1 35614 ax-1 6 proved from Lukasiewicz's axioms. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜑))
 
Theoremwl-luk-pm2.27 35615 This theorem, called "Assertion", can be thought of as closed form of modus ponens ax-mp 5. Theorem *2.27 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 104. Copy of pm2.27 42 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-luk-com12 35616 Inference that swaps (commutes) antecedents in an implication. Copy of com12 32 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜓 → (𝜑𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-luk-pm2.21 35617 From a wff and its negation, anything follows. Theorem *2.21 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 104. Also called the Duns Scotus law. Copy of pm2.21 123 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑 → (𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-luk-con1i 35618 A contraposition inference. Copy of con1i 147 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑𝜓)       𝜓𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-luk-ja 35619 Inference joining the antecedents of two premises. Copy of ja 186 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑𝜒)    &   (𝜓𝜒)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)
 
Theoremwl-luk-imim2 35620 A closed form of syllogism (see syl 17). Theorem *2.05 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 100. Copy of imim2 58 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((𝜑𝜓) → ((𝜒𝜑) → (𝜒𝜓)))
 
Theoremwl-luk-a1d 35621 Deduction introducing an embedded antecedent. Copy of imim2 58 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑 → (𝜒𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-luk-ax2 35622 ax-2 7 proved from Lukasiewicz's axioms. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒)) → ((𝜑𝜓) → (𝜑𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-luk-id 35623 Principle of identity. Theorem *2.08 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 101. Copy of id 22 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-luk-notnotr 35624 Converse of double negation. Theorem *2.14 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 102. In classical logic (our logic) this is always true. In intuitionistic logic this is not always true; in intuitionistic logic, when this is true for some 𝜑, then 𝜑 is stable. Copy of notnotr 130 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2018.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(¬ ¬ 𝜑𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-luk-pm2.04 35625 Swap antecedents. Theorem *2.04 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 100. This was the third axiom in Frege's logic system, specifically Proposition 8 of [Frege1879] p. 35. Copy of pm2.04 90 with a different proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 7-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
((𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒)) → (𝜓 → (𝜑𝜒)))
 
20.18.2  Implication chains
 
Theoremwl-section-impchain 35626 An implication like (𝜓𝜑) with one antecedent can easily be extended by prepending more and more antecedents, as in (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑)) or (𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑))). I call these expressions implication chains, and the number of antecedents (number of nodes minus one) denotes their length. A given length often marks just a required minimum value, since the consequent 𝜑 itself may represent an implication, or even an implication chain, such hiding part of the whole chain. As an extension, it is useful to consider a single variable 𝜑 as a degenerate implication chain of length zero.

Implication chains play a particular role in logic, as all propositional expressions turn out to be convertible to one or more implication chains, their nodes as simple as a variable, or its negation.

So there is good reason to focus on implication chains as a sort of normalized expressions, and build some general theorems around them, with proofs using recursive patterns. This allows for theorems referring to longer and longer implication chains in an automated way.

The theorem names in this section contain the text fragment 'impchain' to point out their relevance to implication chains, followed by a number indicating the (minimal) length of the longest chain involved. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 6-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)

𝜑       𝜑
 
Theoremwl-impchain-mp-x 35627 This series of theorems provide a means of exchanging the consequent of an implication chain via a simple implication. In the main part, Theorems ax-mp 5, syl 17, syl6 35, syl8 76 form the beginning of this series. These theorems are replicated here, but with proofs that aim at a recursive scheme, allowing to base a proof on that of the previous one in the series. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Nov-2019.)
 
Theoremwl-impchain-mp-0 35628 This theorem is the start of a proof recursion scheme where we replace the consequent of an implication chain. The number '0' in the theorem name indicates that the modified chain has no antecedents.

This theorem is in fact a copy of ax-mp 5, and is repeated here to emphasize the recursion using similar theorem names. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 6-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)

𝜓    &   (𝜓𝜑)       𝜑
 
Theoremwl-impchain-mp-1 35629 This theorem is in fact a copy of wl-luk-syl 35604, and repeated here to demonstrate a recursive proof scheme. The number '1' in the theorem name indicates that a chain of length 1 is modified. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 6-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜒𝜓)    &   (𝜓𝜑)       (𝜒𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-impchain-mp-2 35630 This theorem is in fact a copy of wl-luk-imtrdi 35612, and repeated here to demonstrate a recursive proof scheme. The number '2' in the theorem name indicates that a chain of length 2 is modified. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 6-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜃 → (𝜒𝜓))    &   (𝜓𝜑)       (𝜃 → (𝜒𝜑))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-1.x 35631 It is often convenient to have the antecedent under focus in first position, so we can apply immediate theorem forms (as opposed to deduction, tautology form). This series of theorems swaps the first with the last antecedent in an implication chain. This kind of swapping is self-inverse, whence we prefer it over, say, rotating theorems. A consequent can hide a tail of a longer chain, so theorems of this series appear as swapping a pair of antecedents with fixed offsets. This form of swapping antecedents is flexible enough to allow for any permutation of antecedents in an implication chain.

The first elements of this series correspond to com12 32, com13 88, com14 96 and com15 101 in the main part.

The proofs of this series aim at automated proving using a simple recursive scheme. It employs the previous theorem in the series along with a sample from the wl-impchain-mp-x 35627 series developed before. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Nov-2019.)

 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-1.1 35632 A degenerate form of antecedent swapping. The number '1' in the theorem name indicates that it handles a chain of length 1.

Since there is just one antecedent in the chain, there is nothing to swap. Nondegenerated forms begin with wl-impchain-com-1.2 35633, for more see there. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 7-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)

(𝜓𝜑)       (𝜓𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-1.2 35633 This theorem is in fact a copy of wl-luk-com12 35616, and repeated here to demonstrate a simple proof scheme. The number '2' in the theorem name indicates that a chain of length 2 is modified.

See wl-impchain-com-1.x 35631 for more information how this proof is generated. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 7-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)

(𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑))       (𝜓 → (𝜒𝜑))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-1.3 35634 This theorem is in fact a copy of com13 88, and repeated here to demonstrate a simple proof scheme. The number '3' in the theorem name indicates that a chain of length 3 is modified.

See wl-impchain-com-1.x 35631 for more information how this proof is generated. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 7-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)

(𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑)))       (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃𝜑)))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-1.4 35635 This theorem is in fact a copy of com14 96, and repeated here to demonstrate a simple proof scheme. The number '4' in the theorem name indicates that a chain of length 4 is modified.

See wl-impchain-com-1.x 35631 for more information how this proof is generated. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 7-Jul-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)

(𝜂 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑))))       (𝜓 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜂𝜑))))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-n.m 35636 This series of theorems allow swapping any two antecedents in an implication chain. The theorem names follow a pattern wl-impchain-com-n.m with integral numbers n < m, that swaps the m-th antecedent with n-th one in an implication chain. It is sufficient to restrict the length of the chain to m, too, since the consequent can be assumed to be the tail right of the m-th antecedent of any arbitrary sized implication chain. We further assume n > 1, since the wl-impchain-com-1.x 35631 series already covers the special case n = 1.

Being able to swap any two antecedents in an implication chain lays the foundation of permuting its antecedents arbitrarily.

The proofs of this series aim at automated proofing using a simple scheme. Any instance of this series is a triple step of swapping the first and n-th antecedent, then the first and the m-th, then the first and the n-th antecedent again. Each of these steps is an instance of the wl-impchain-com-1.x 35631 series. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Nov-2019.)

 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-2.3 35637 This theorem is in fact a copy of com23 86. It starts a series of theorems named after wl-impchain-com-n.m 35636. For more information see there. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 12-Nov-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑)))       (𝜃 → (𝜓 → (𝜒𝜑)))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-2.4 35638 This theorem is in fact a copy of com24 95. It is another instantiation of theorems named after wl-impchain-com-n.m 35636. For more information see there. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Nov-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜂 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑))))       (𝜂 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃𝜑))))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-com-3.2.1 35639 This theorem is in fact a copy of com3r 87. The proof is an example of how to arrive at arbitrary permutations of antecedents, using only swapping theorems. The recursion principle is to first swap the correct antecedent to the position just before the consequent, and then employ a theorem handling an implication chain of length one less to reorder the others. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Nov-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜃 → (𝜒 → (𝜓𝜑)))       (𝜓 → (𝜃 → (𝜒𝜑)))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-a1-x 35640 If an implication chain is assumed (hypothesis) or proven (theorem) to hold, then we may add any extra antecedent to it, without changing its truth. This is expressed in its simplest form in wl-luk-a1i 35609, that allows us prepending an arbitrary antecedent to an implication chain. Using our antecedent swapping theorems described in wl-impchain-com-n.m 35636, we may then move such a prepended antecedent to any desired location within all antecedents. The first series of theorems of this kind adds a single antecedent somewhere to an implication chain. The appended number in the theorem name indicates its position within all antecedents, 1 denoting the head position. A second theorem series extends this idea to multiple additions (TODO).

Adding antecedents to an implication chain usually weakens their universality. The consequent afterwards dependends on more conditions than before, which renders the implication chain less versatile. So you find this proof technique mostly when you adjust a chain to a hypothesis of a rule. A common case are syllogisms merging two implication chains into one.

The first elements of the first series correspond to a1i 11, a1d 25 and a1dd 50 in the main part.

The proofs of this series aim at automated proving using a simple recursive scheme. It employs the previous theorem in the series along with a sample from the wl-impchain-com-1.x 35631 series developed before. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Jun-2020.)

 
Theoremwl-impchain-a1-1 35641 Inference rule, a copy of a1i 11. Head start of a recursive proof pattern. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Jun-2020.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
𝜑       (𝜓𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-impchain-a1-2 35642 Inference rule, a copy of a1d 25. First recursive proof based on the previous instance. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Jun-2020.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑𝜓)       (𝜑 → (𝜒𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-impchain-a1-3 35643 Inference rule, a copy of a1dd 50. A recursive proof depending on previous instances, and demonstrating the proof pattern. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Jun-2020.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))       (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃𝜒)))
 
20.18.3  Theorems around the conditional operator
 
Theoremwl-ifp-ncond1 35644 If one case of an if- condition is false, the other automatically follows. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2024.)
𝜓 → (if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ (¬ 𝜑𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-ifp-ncond2 35645 If one case of an if- condition is false, the other automatically follows. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jul-2024.)
𝜒 → (if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ (𝜑𝜓)))
 
Theoremwl-ifpimpr 35646 If one case of an if- condition is a consequence of the other, the expression in df-ifp 1061 can be shortened. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 12-Jun-2024.)
((𝜒𝜓) → (if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ 𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-ifp4impr 35647 If one case of an if- condition is a consequence of the other, the expression in dfifp4 1064 can be shortened. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 18-Jun-2024.)
((𝜒𝜓) → (if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜒) ∧ 𝜓)))
 
20.18.4  Alternative development of hadd, cadd
 
Theoremwl-df-3xor 35648 Alternative definition of whad 1594 based on hadifp 1607. See df-had 1595 to learn how it is currently introduced. The only use case so far is being a binary addition primitive for df-sad 16167. If inputs are viewed as binary digits (true is 1, false is 0), the result is what a binary single-bit addition with carry-in yields in the low bit of their sum.

The core meaning is to check whether an odd number of three inputs are true. The operation tests this for two inputs. So, if the first input is true, the two remaining inputs need to amount to an even (or: not an odd) number, else to an odd number.

The idea of an odd number of inputs being true carries over to other than 3 inputs by recursion: In an informal notation we depend the case with n+1 inputs, 𝜑 being the additional one, recursively on that of n inputs: "(n+1)-xor" ↔ if-(𝜑, ¬ "n-xor" , "n-xor" ). The base case is "0-xor" being , because zero inputs never contain an odd number among them. Then we find, after simplifying, in our informal notation:

"2-xor" (𝜑, 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑𝜓) (see wl-2xor 35663).

Our definition here follows exactly the above pattern.

In microprocessor technology an addition limited to a range (a one-bit range in our case) is called a "wrap-around operation". The name "had", as in df-had 1595, by contrast, is somehow suggestive of a "half adder" instead. Such a circuit, for one, takes two inputs only, no carry-in, and then yields two outputs - both sum and carry. That's why we use "3xor" instead of "had" here. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 24-Apr-2024.)

(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ if-(𝜑, ¬ (𝜓𝜒), (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-df3xor2 35649 Alternative definition of wl-df-3xor 35648, using triple exclusive disjunction, or XOR3. You can add more input by appending each one with a . Copy of hadass 1598. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 1-May-2024.)
(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ (𝜑 ⊻ (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-df3xor3 35650 Alternative form of wl-df3xor2 35649. Copy of df-had 1595. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 1-May-2024.)
(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ⊻ 𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-3xortru 35651 If the first input is true, then triple xor is equivalent to the biconditionality of the other two inputs. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 24-Apr-2024.)
(𝜑 → (hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ¬ (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-3xorfal 35652 If the first input is false, then triple xor is equivalent to the exclusive disjunction of the other two inputs. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 29-Apr-2024.)
𝜑 → (hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-3xorbi 35653 Triple xor can be replaced with a triple biconditional. Unlike , you cannot add more inputs by simply stacking up more biconditionals, and still express an "odd number of inputs". (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 24-Apr-2024.)
(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-3xorbi2 35654 Alternative form of wl-3xorbi 35653. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 24-Apr-2024.)
(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ↔ 𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-3xorbi123d 35655 Equivalence theorem for triple xor. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 24-Apr-2024.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜃𝜏))    &   (𝜑 → (𝜂𝜁))       (𝜑 → (hadd(𝜓, 𝜃, 𝜂) ↔ hadd(𝜒, 𝜏, 𝜁)))
 
Theoremwl-3xorbi123i 35656 Equivalence theorem for triple xor. Copy of hadbi123i 1597. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.)
(𝜓𝜒)    &   (𝜃𝜏)    &   (𝜂𝜁)       (hadd(𝜓, 𝜃, 𝜂) ↔ hadd(𝜒, 𝜏, 𝜁))
 
Theoremwl-3xorrot 35657 Rotation law for triple xor. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 24-Apr-2024.)
(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ hadd(𝜓, 𝜒, 𝜑))
 
Theoremwl-3xorcoma 35658 Commutative law for triple xor. Copy of hadcoma 1600. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 17-Dec-2023.)
(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ hadd(𝜓, 𝜑, 𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-3xorcomb 35659 Commutative law for triple xor. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-had redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 24-Apr-2024.)
(hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ hadd(𝜑, 𝜒, 𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-3xornot1 35660 Flipping the first input flips the triple xor. wl-3xorrot 35657 can rotate any input to the front, so flipping any one of them does the same. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 1-May-2024.)
(¬ hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ hadd(¬ 𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-3xornot 35661 Triple xor distributes over negation. Copy of hadnot 1604. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Jul-2020.)
(¬ hadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ hadd(¬ 𝜑, ¬ 𝜓, ¬ 𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-1xor 35662 In the recursive scheme

"(n+1)-xor" ↔ if-(𝜑, ¬ "n-xor" , "n-xor" )

we set n = 0 to formally arrive at an expression for "1-xor". The base case "0-xor" is replaced with , as a sequence of 0 inputs never has an odd number being part of it. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2024.)

(if-(𝜓, ¬ ⊥, ⊥) ↔ 𝜓)
 
Theoremwl-2xor 35663 In the recursive scheme

"(n+1)-xor" ↔ if-(𝜑, ¬ "n-xor" , "n-xor" )

we set n = 1 to formally arrive at an expression for "2-xor". It is based on "1-xor", that is known to be equivalent to its only input (see wl-1xor 35662). (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 11-May-2024.)

(if-(𝜑, ¬ 𝜓, 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-df-3mintru2 35664 Alternative definition of wcad 1608. See df-cad 1609 to learn how it is currently introduced. The only use case so far is being a binary addition primitive for df-sad 16167. If inputs are viewed as binary digits (true is 1, false is 0), the result is whether ordinary binary full addition yields a carry bit. That is what the name df-cad 1609 is derived from: "carry of an addition". Here we stick with this abbreviated form of our notation above, but still use "adder carry" as a shorthand for "at least 2 out of 3" in text.

The core meaning is to check whether at least two of three inputs are true. So, if the first input is true, at least one of the two remaining must be true, else even both. This theorem is the in-between of "at least 1 out of 3", given by triple disjunction df-3or 1087, and "(at least) 3 out of 3", expressed by triple conjunction df-3an 1088.

The notion above can be generalized to other input numbers with other minimum values as follows. Let us introduce informally a logical operation "n-mintru-m" taking n inputs, and requiring at least m of them be true to let the operation itself be true. There now exists a recursive scheme to define it for increasing n, m. We start with the base case n = 0. Here "n-mintru-0" is equivalent to (any sequence of inputs contains at least zero true inputs), the other "0-mintru-m" is for any m > 0 equivalent to , because a sequence of zero inputs never has a positive number of them true. The general case adds a new input 𝜑 to a given sequence of n inputs, and reduces that case for all integers m to that of the smaller sequence by recursion, informally written as:

"(n+1)-mintru-(m+1)" ↔ if-(𝜑, "n-mintru-m" , "n-mintru-(m+1)" )

Our definition here matches "3-mintru-2" with inputs 𝜑, 𝜓 and 𝜒. Starting from the base cases we find after simplifications: "2-mintru-2" (𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓𝜒) (wl-2mintru2 35671), and "2-mintru-1" (𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓𝜒) (wl-2mintru1 35670). Plugging these expressions into the formula above for n = 3, m = 2 yields exactly our definition here. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 2-May-2024.)

(cadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ if-(𝜑, (𝜓𝜒), (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-df2-3mintru2 35665 The adder carry in disjunctive normal form. An alternative highly symmetric definition emphasizing the independence of order of the inputs 𝜑, 𝜓 and 𝜒. Copy of cador 1610. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-cad redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 12-Jun-2024.)
(cadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (𝜑𝜒) ∨ (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-df3-3mintru2 35666 The adder carry in conjunctive normal form. An alternative highly symmetric definition emphasizing the independence of order of the inputs 𝜑, 𝜓 and 𝜒. Copy of cadan 1611. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-cad redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 18-Jun-2024.)
(cadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∧ (𝜑𝜒) ∧ (𝜓𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-df4-3mintru2 35667 An alternative definition of the adder carry. Copy of df-cad 1609. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Sep-2016.) df-cad redefined. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 19-Jun-2024.)
(cadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (𝜒 ∧ (𝜑𝜓))))
 
Theoremwl-1mintru1 35668 Using the recursion formula:

"(n+1)-mintru-(m+1)" ↔ if-(𝜑, "n-mintru-m" , "n-mintru-(m+1)" )

for "1-mintru-1" (meaning "at least 1 out of 1 input is true") by plugging in n = 0, m = 0, and simplifying. The expressions "0-mintru-0" and "0-mintru-1" are base cases of the recursion, meaning "in a sequence of zero inputs, at least 0 / 1 input is true", respectively equvalent to / .

Negating an "n-mintru1" operation means: All n inputs 𝜑.. 𝜃 are false. This is also conveniently expressed as ¬ (𝜑.. 𝜃). Applying this idea here (n = 1) yields the obvious result that in an input sequence of size 1 only then all will be false, if its single input is. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 10-May-2024.)

(if-(𝜒, ⊤, ⊥) ↔ 𝜒)
 
Theoremwl-1mintru2 35669 Using the recursion formula:

"(n+1)-mintru-(m+1)" ↔ if-(𝜑, "n-mintru-m" , "n-mintru-(m+1)" )

for "1-mintru-2" (meaning "at least 2 out of a single input are true") by plugging in n = 0, m = 1, and simplifying. The expressions "0-mintru-1" and "0-mintru-2" are base cases of the recursion, meaning "in a sequence of zero inputs at least 1 / 2 input is true", evaluate both to .

Since no sequence of inputs has a longer subsequence of whatever property, the resulting is to be expected.

Negating a "n-mintru2" operation has an interesting interpretation: at most one input is true, so all inputs exclude each other mutually. Such an exclusion is expressed by a NAND operation (𝜑𝜓), not by a XOR. Applying this idea here (n = 1) leads to the obvious "In a single input sequence 'at most one is true' always holds". (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 10-May-2024.)

(if-(𝜒, ⊥, ⊥) ↔ ⊥)
 
Theoremwl-2mintru1 35670 Using the recursion formula

"(n+1)-mintru-(m+1)" ↔ if-(𝜑, "n-mintru-m" , "n-mintru-(m+1)" )

for "2-mintru-1" (meaning "at least 1 out of 2 inputs is true") by plugging in n = 1, m = 0, and simplifying. The expression "1-mintru-0" is a base case (meaning at least zero inputs out of 1 are true), evaluating to , and wl-1mintru1 35668 shows "1-mintru-1" is equivalent to the only input.

Negating an "n-mintru1" operation means: All n inputs 𝜑.. 𝜃 are false. This is also conveniently expressed as ¬ (𝜑.. 𝜃), in accordance with the result here. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 10-May-2024.)

(if-(𝜓, ⊤, 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-2mintru2 35671 Using the recursion formula

"(n+1)-mintru-(m+1)" ↔ if-(𝜑, "n-mintru-m" , "n-mintru-(m+1)" )

for "2-mintru-2" (meaning "2 out of 2 inputs are true") by plugging in n = 1, m = 1, and simplifying. See wl-1mintru1 35668 and wl-1mintru2 35669 to see that "1-mintru-1" / "1-mintru-2" evaluate to 𝜒 / respectively.

Negating a "n-mintru2" operation means 'at most one input is true', so all inputs exclude each other mutually. Such an exclusion is expressed by a NAND operation (𝜑𝜓), not by a XOR. Applying this idea here (n = 2) yields the expected NAND in case of a pair of inputs. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 10-May-2024.)

(if-(𝜓, 𝜒, ⊥) ↔ (𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-df3maxtru1 35672 Assuming "(n+1)-maxtru1" ↔ ¬ "(n+1)-mintru-2", we can deduce from the recursion formula given in wl-df-3mintru2 35664, that a similiar one

"(n+1)-maxtru1" ↔ if-(𝜑,-. "n-mintru-1" , "n-maxtru1" )

is valid for expressing 'at most one input is true'. This can also be rephrased as a mutual exclusivity of propositional expressions (no two of a sequence of inputs can simultaniously be true). Of course, this suggests that all inputs depend on variables 𝜂, 𝜁... Whatever wellformed expression we plugin for these variables, it will render at most one of the inputs true.

The here introduced mutual exclusivity is possibly useful for case studies, where we want the cases be sort of 'disjoint'. One can further imagine that a complete case scenario demands that the 'at most' is sharpened to 'exactly one'. This does not impose any difficulty here, as one of the inputs will then be the negation of all others be or'ed. As one input is determined, 'at most one' is sufficient to describe the general form here.

Since cadd is an alias for 'at least 2 out of three are true', its negation is under focus here. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 23-Jun-2024.)

(¬ cadd(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ↔ if-(𝜑, (𝜓 𝜒), (𝜓𝜒)))
 
20.18.5  An alternative axiom ~ ax-13
 
Axiomax-wl-13v 35673* A version of ax13v 2374 with a distinctor instead of a distinct variable condition.

Had we additionally required 𝑥 and 𝑦 be distinct, too, this theorem would have been a direct consequence of ax-5 1914. So essentially this theorem states, that a distinct variable condition between set variables can be replaced with a distinctor expression. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 23-Jul-2021.)

(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑦 = 𝑧 → ∀𝑥 𝑦 = 𝑧))
 
Theoremwl-ax13lem1 35674* A version of ax-wl-13v 35673 with one distinct variable restriction dropped. For convenience, 𝑦 is kept on the right side of equations. This proof bases on ideas from NM, 24-Dec-2015. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 23-Jul-2021.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑧 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑥 𝑧 = 𝑦))
 
20.18.6  Other stuff
 
Theoremwl-mps 35675 Replacing a nested consequent. A sort of modus ponens in antecedent position. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Sep-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑 → (𝜓𝜒))    &   ((𝜑𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremwl-syls1 35676 Replacing a nested consequent. A sort of syllogism in antecedent position. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Sep-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜓𝜒)    &   ((𝜑𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremwl-syls2 35677 Replacing a nested antecedent. A sort of syllogism in antecedent position. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Sep-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
(𝜑𝜓)    &   ((𝜑𝜒) → 𝜃)       ((𝜓𝜒) → 𝜃)
 
Theoremwl-embant 35678 A true wff can always be added as a nested antecedent to an antecedent. Note: this theorem is intuitionistically valid. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 4-Oct-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.)
𝜑    &   (𝜓𝜒)       ((𝜑𝜓) → 𝜒)
 
Theoremwl-orel12 35679 In a conjunctive normal form a pair of nodes like (𝜑𝜓) ∧ (¬ 𝜑𝜒) eliminates the need of a node (𝜓𝜒). This theorem allows simplifications in that respect. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 20-Jun-2020.)
(((𝜑𝜓) ∧ (¬ 𝜑𝜒)) → (𝜓𝜒))
 
Theoremwl-cases2-dnf 35680 A particular instance of orddi 1007 and anddi 1008 converting between disjunctive and conjunctive normal forms, when both 𝜑 and ¬ 𝜑 appear. This theorem in fact rephrases cases2 1045, and is related to consensus 1050. I restate it here in DNF and CNF. The proof deliberately does not use df-ifp 1061 and dfifp4 1064, by which it can be shortened. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 21-Jun-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(((𝜑𝜓) ∨ (¬ 𝜑𝜒)) ↔ ((¬ 𝜑𝜓) ∧ (𝜑𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-cbvmotv 35681* Change bound variable. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. Part of Lemma 7 of [KalishMontague] p. 86. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 5-Mar-2023.)
(∃*𝑥⊤ → ∃*𝑦⊤)
 
Theoremwl-moteq 35682 Change bound variable. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. Part of Lemma 7 of [KalishMontague] p. 86. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 5-Mar-2023.)
(∃*𝑥⊤ → 𝑦 = 𝑧)
 
Theoremwl-motae 35683 Change bound variable. Uses only Tarski's FOL axiom schemes. Part of Lemma 7 of [KalishMontague] p. 86. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 5-Mar-2023.)
(∃*𝑢⊤ → ∀𝑥 𝑦 = 𝑧)
 
Theoremwl-moae 35684* Two ways to express "at most one thing exists" or, in this context equivalently, "exactly one thing exists" . The equivalence results from the presence of ax-6 1972 in the proof, that ensures "at least one thing exists". For other equivalences see wl-euae 35685 and exists1 2663. Gerard Lang pointed out, that 𝑦𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 with disjoint 𝑥 and 𝑦 (df-mo 2541, trut 1545) also means "exactly one thing exists" . (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) State the theorem using truth constant . (Revised by BJ, 7-Oct-2022.) Reduce axiom dependencies, and use ∃*. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 7-Mar-2023.)
(∃*𝑥⊤ ↔ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremwl-euae 35685* Two ways to express "exactly one thing exists" . (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 5-Mar-2023.)
(∃!𝑥⊤ ↔ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremwl-nax6im 35686* The following series of theorems are centered around the empty domain, where no set exists. As a consequence, a set variable like 𝑥 has no instance to assign to. An expression like 𝑥 = 𝑦 is not really meaningful then. What does it evaluate to, true or false? In fact, the grammar extension weq 1967 requires us to formally assign a boolean value to an equation, say always false, unless you want to give up on exmid 892, for example. Whatever it is, we start out with the contraposition of ax-6 1972, that guarantees the existence of at least one set. Our hypothesis here expresses tentatively it might not hold. We can simplify the antecedent then, to the point where we do not need equation any more. This suggests what a decent characterization of the empty domain of discourse could be. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 12-Mar-2023.)
(¬ ∃𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝜑)       (¬ ∃𝑥⊤ → 𝜑)
 
Theoremwl-hbae1 35687 This specialization of hbae 2432 does not depend on ax-11 2155. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 8-Aug-2021.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑦𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremwl-naevhba1v 35688* An instance of hbn1w 2050 applied to equality. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 7-Apr-2021.)
(¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑥 ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremwl-spae 35689 Prove an instance of sp 2177 from ax-13 2373 and Tarski's FOL only, without distinct variable conditions. The antecedent 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 holds in a multi-object universe only if 𝑦 is substituted for 𝑥, or vice versa, i.e. both variables are effectively the same. The converse ¬ ∀𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 indicates that both variables are distinct, and it so provides a simple translation of a distinct variable condition to a logical term. In case studies 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 and ¬ ∀𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 can help eliminating distinct variable conditions.

The antecedent 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 is expressed in the theorem's name by the abbreviation ae standing for 'all equal'.

Note that we cannot provide a logical predicate telling us directly whether a logical expression contains a particular variable, as such a construct would usually contradict ax-12 2172.

Note that this theorem is also provable from ax-12 2172 alone, so you can pick the axiom it is based on.

Compare this result to 19.3v 1986 and spaev 2056 having distinct variable conditions, but a smaller footprint on axiom usage. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 5-Apr-2021.)

(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦𝑥 = 𝑦)
 
Theoremwl-speqv 35690* Under the assumption ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 a specialized version of sp 2177 is provable from Tarski's FOL and ax13v 2374 only. Note that this reverts the implication in ax13lem1 2375, so in fact 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝑧 = 𝑦𝑧 = 𝑦)) holds. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Apr-2021.)
𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥 𝑧 = 𝑦𝑧 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremwl-19.8eqv 35691* Under the assumption ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 a specialized version of 19.8a 2175 is provable from Tarski's FOL and ax13v 2374 only. Note that this reverts the implication in ax13lem2 2377, so in fact 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∃𝑥𝑧 = 𝑦𝑧 = 𝑦)) holds. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Apr-2021.)
𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝑧 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑥 𝑧 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremwl-19.2reqv 35692* Under the assumption ¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 the reverse direction of 19.2 1981 is provable from Tarski's FOL and ax13v 2374 only. Note that in conjunction with 19.2 1981 in fact 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝑧 = 𝑦 ↔ ∃𝑥𝑧 = 𝑦)) holds. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 17-Apr-2021.)
𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∃𝑥 𝑧 = 𝑦 → ∀𝑥 𝑧 = 𝑦))
 
Theoremwl-nfalv 35693* If 𝑥 is not present in 𝜑, it is not free in 𝑦𝜑. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 11-Jan-2020.)
𝑥𝑦𝜑
 
Theoremwl-nfimf1 35694 An antecedent is irrelevant to a not-free property, if it always holds. I used this variant of nfim 1900 in dvelimdf 2450 to simplify the proof. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 14-Oct-2018.)
(∀𝑥𝜑 → (Ⅎ𝑥(𝜑𝜓) ↔ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓))
 
Theoremwl-nfae1 35695 Unlike nfae 2434, this specialized theorem avoids ax-11 2155. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 26-Jun-2019.)
𝑥𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥
 
Theoremwl-nfnae1 35696 Unlike nfnae 2435, this specialized theorem avoids ax-11 2155. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 27-Jun-2019.)
𝑥 ¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥
 
Theoremwl-aetr 35697 A transitive law for variable identifying expressions. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 30-Jun-2019.)
(∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑧 → ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑧))
 
Theoremwl-axc11r 35698 Same as axc11r 2367, but using ax12 2424 instead of ax-12 2172 directly. This better reflects axiom usage in theorems dependent on it. (Contributed by NM, 25-Jul-2015.) Avoid direct use of ax-12 2172. (Revised by Wolf Lammen, 30-Mar-2024.)
(∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥 → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜑))
 
Theoremwl-dral1d 35699 A version of dral1 2440 with a context. Note: At first glance one might be tempted to generalize this (or a similar) theorem by weakening the first two hypotheses adding a 𝑥 = 𝑦, 𝑥𝑥 = 𝑦 or 𝜑 antecedent. wl-equsal1i 35711 and nf5di 2283 show that this is in fact pointless. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jul-2019.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑦𝜑    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜒)))
 
Theoremwl-cbvalnaed 35700 wl-cbvalnae 35701 with a context. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jul-2019.)
𝑥𝜑    &   𝑦𝜑    &   (𝜑 → (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → Ⅎ𝑦𝜓))    &   (𝜑 → (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜒))    &   (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓𝜒)))       (𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦𝜒))
    < Previous  Next >

Page List
Jump to page: Contents  1 1-100 2 101-200 3 201-300 4 301-400 5 401-500 6 501-600 7 601-700 8 701-800 9 801-900 10 901-1000 11 1001-1100 12 1101-1200 13 1201-1300 14 1301-1400 15 1401-1500 16 1501-1600 17 1601-1700 18 1701-1800 19 1801-1900 20 1901-2000 21 2001-2100 22 2101-2200 23 2201-2300 24 2301-2400 25 2401-2500 26 2501-2600 27 2601-2700 28 2701-2800 29 2801-2900 30 2901-3000 31 3001-3100 32 3101-3200 33 3201-3300 34 3301-3400 35 3401-3500 36 3501-3600 37 3601-3700 38 3701-3800 39 3801-3900 40 3901-4000 41 4001-4100 42 4101-4200 43 4201-4300 44 4301-4400 45 4401-4500 46 4501-4600 47 4601-4700 48 4701-4800 49 4801-4900 50 4901-5000 51 5001-5100 52 5101-5200 53 5201-5300 54 5301-5400 55 5401-5500 56 5501-5600 57 5601-5700 58 5701-5800 59 5801-5900 60 5901-6000 61 6001-6100 62 6101-6200 63 6201-6300 64 6301-6400 65 6401-6500 66 6501-6600 67 6601-6700 68 6701-6800 69 6801-6900 70 6901-7000 71 7001-7100 72 7101-7200 73 7201-7300 74 7301-7400 75 7401-7500 76 7501-7600 77 7601-7700 78 7701-7800 79 7801-7900 80 7901-8000 81 8001-8100 82 8101-8200 83 8201-8300 84 8301-8400 85 8401-8500 86 8501-8600 87 8601-8700 88 8701-8800 89 8801-8900 90 8901-9000 91 9001-9100 92 9101-9200 93 9201-9300 94 9301-9400 95 9401-9500 96 9501-9600 97 9601-9700 98 9701-9800 99 9801-9900 100 9901-10000 101 10001-10100 102 10101-10200 103 10201-10300 104 10301-10400 105 10401-10500 106 10501-10600 107 10601-10700 108 10701-10800 109 10801-10900 110 10901-11000 111 11001-11100 112 11101-11200 113 11201-11300 114 11301-11400 115 11401-11500 116 11501-11600 117 11601-11700 118 11701-11800 119 11801-11900 120 11901-12000 121 12001-12100 122 12101-12200 123 12201-12300 124 12301-12400 125 12401-12500 126 12501-12600 127 12601-12700 128 12701-12800 129 12801-12900 130 12901-13000 131 13001-13100 132 13101-13200 133 13201-13300 134 13301-13400 135 13401-13500 136 13501-13600 137 13601-13700 138 13701-13800 139 13801-13900 140 13901-14000 141 14001-14100 142 14101-14200 143 14201-14300 144 14301-14400 145 14401-14500 146 14501-14600 147 14601-14700 148 14701-14800 149 14801-14900 150 14901-15000 151 15001-15100 152 15101-15200 153 15201-15300 154 15301-15400 155 15401-15500 156 15501-15600 157 15601-15700 158 15701-15800 159 15801-15900 160 15901-16000 161 16001-16100 162 16101-16200 163 16201-16300 164 16301-16400 165 16401-16500 166 16501-16600 167 16601-16700 168 16701-16800 169 16801-16900 170 16901-17000 171 17001-17100 172 17101-17200 173 17201-17300 174 17301-17400 175 17401-17500 176 17501-17600 177 17601-17700 178 17701-17800 179 17801-17900 180 17901-18000 181 18001-18100 182 18101-18200 183 18201-18300 184 18301-18400 185 18401-18500 186 18501-18600 187 18601-18700 188 18701-18800 189 18801-18900 190 18901-19000 191 19001-19100 192 19101-19200 193 19201-19300 194 19301-19400 195 19401-19500 196 19501-19600 197 19601-19700 198 19701-19800 199 19801-19900 200 19901-20000 201 20001-20100 202 20101-20200 203 20201-20300 204 20301-20400 205 20401-20500 206 20501-20600 207 20601-20700 208 20701-20800 209 20801-20900 210 20901-21000 211 21001-21100 212 21101-21200 213 21201-21300 214 21301-21400 215 21401-21500 216 21501-21600 217 21601-21700 218 21701-21800 219 21801-21900 220 21901-22000 221 22001-22100 222 22101-22200 223 22201-22300 224 22301-22400 225 22401-22500 226 22501-22600 227 22601-22700 228 22701-22800 229 22801-22900 230 22901-23000 231 23001-23100 232 23101-23200 233 23201-23300 234 23301-23400 235 23401-23500 236 23501-23600 237 23601-23700 238 23701-23800 239 23801-23900 240 23901-24000 241 24001-24100 242 24101-24200 243 24201-24300 244 24301-24400 245 24401-24500 246 24501-24600 247 24601-24700 248 24701-24800 249 24801-24900 250 24901-25000 251 25001-25100 252 25101-25200 253 25201-25300 254 25301-25400 255 25401-25500 256 25501-25600 257 25601-25700 258 25701-25800 259 25801-25900 260 25901-26000 261 26001-26100 262 26101-26200 263 26201-26300 264 26301-26400 265 26401-26500 266 26501-26600 267 26601-26700 268 26701-26800 269 26801-26900 270 26901-27000 271 27001-27100 272 27101-27200 273 27201-27300 274 27301-27400 275 27401-27500 276 27501-27600 277 27601-27700 278 27701-27800 279 27801-27900 280 27901-28000 281 28001-28100 282 28101-28200 283 28201-28300 284 28301-28400 285 28401-28500 286 28501-28600 287 28601-28700 288 28701-28800 289 28801-28900 290 28901-29000 291 29001-29100 292 29101-29200 293 29201-29300 294 29301-29400 295 29401-29500 296 29501-29600 297 29601-29700 298 29701-29800 299 29801-29900 300 29901-30000 301 30001-30100 302 30101-30200 303 30201-30300 304 30301-30400 305 30401-30500 306 30501-30600 307 30601-30700 308 30701-30800 309 30801-30900 310 30901-31000 311 31001-31100 312 31101-31200 313 31201-31300 314 31301-31400 315 31401-31500 316 31501-31600 317 31601-31700 318 31701-31800 319 31801-31900 320 31901-32000 321 32001-32100 322 32101-32200 323 32201-32300 324 32301-32400 325 32401-32500 326 32501-32600 327 32601-32700 328 32701-32800 329 32801-32900 330 32901-33000 331 33001-33100 332 33101-33200 333 33201-33300 334 33301-33400 335 33401-33500 336 33501-33600 337 33601-33700 338 33701-33800 339 33801-33900 340 33901-34000 341 34001-34100 342 34101-34200 343 34201-34300 344 34301-34400 345 34401-34500 346 34501-34600 347 34601-34700 348 34701-34800 349 34801-34900 350 34901-35000 351 35001-35100 352 35101-35200 353 35201-35300 354 35301-35400 355 35401-35500 356 35501-35600 357 35601-35700 358 35701-35800 359 35801-35900 360 35901-36000 361 36001-36100 362 36101-36200 363 36201-36300 364 36301-36400 365 36401-36500 366 36501-36600 367 36601-36700 368 36701-36800 369 36801-36900 370 36901-37000 371 37001-37100 372 37101-37200 373 37201-37300 374 37301-37400 375 37401-37500 376 37501-37600 377 37601-37700 378 37701-37800 379 37801-37900 380 37901-38000 381 38001-38100 382 38101-38200 383 38201-38300 384 38301-38400 385 38401-38500 386 38501-38600 387 38601-38700 388 38701-38800 389 38801-38900 390 38901-39000 391 39001-39100 392 39101-39200 393 39201-39300 394 39301-39400 395 39401-39500 396 39501-39600 397 39601-39700 398 39701-39800 399 39801-39900 400 39901-40000 401 40001-40100 402 40101-40200 403 40201-40300 404 40301-40400 405 40401-40500 406 40501-40600 407 40601-40700 408 40701-40800 409 40801-40900 410 40901-41000 411 41001-41100 412 41101-41200 413 41201-41300 414 41301-41400 415 41401-41500 416 41501-41600 417 41601-41700 418 41701-41800 419 41801-41900 420 41901-42000 421 42001-42100 422 42101-42200 423 42201-42300 424 42301-42400 425 42401-42500 426 42501-42600 427 42601-42700 428 42701-42800 429 42801-42900 430 42901-43000 431 43001-43100 432 43101-43200 433 43201-43300 434 43301-43400 435 43401-43500 436 43501-43600 437 43601-43700 438 43701-43800 439 43801-43900 440 43901-44000 441 44001-44100 442 44101-44200 443 44201-44300 444 44301-44400 445 44401-44500 446 44501-44600 447 44601-44700 448 44701-44800 449 44801-44900 450 44901-45000 451 45001-45100 452 45101-45200 453 45201-45300 454 45301-45400 455 45401-45500 456 45501-45600 457 45601-45700 458 45701-45800 459 45801-45900 460 45901-46000 461 46001-46100 462 46101-46200 463 46201-46300 464 46301-46400 465 46401-46500 466 46501-46532
  Copyright terms: Public domain < Previous  Next >