![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 426 of 479) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30171) |
![]() (30172-31694) |
![]() (31695-47852) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | frege87d 42501 | If the images of both {𝐴} and 𝑈 are subsets of 𝑈 and 𝐶 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅 and 𝐵 follows 𝐶 in 𝑅, then 𝐵 is an element of 𝑈. Similar to Proposition 87 of [Frege1879] p. 66. Compare with frege87 42701. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶𝑅𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 “ {𝐴}) ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 “ 𝑈) ⊆ 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | frege91d 42502 | If 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in 𝑅 then 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅. Similar to Proposition 91 of [Frege1879] p. 68. Comparw with frege91 42705. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴𝑅𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐵) | ||
Theorem | frege97d 42503 | If 𝐴 contains all elements after those in 𝑈 in the transitive closure of 𝑅, then the image under 𝑅 of 𝐴 is a subclass of 𝐴. Similar to Proposition 97 of [Frege1879] p. 71. Compare with frege97 42711. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = ((t+‘𝑅) “ 𝑈)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | frege98d 42504 | If 𝐶 follows 𝐴 and 𝐵 follows 𝐶 in the transitive closure of 𝑅, then 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅. Similar to Proposition 98 of [Frege1879] p. 71. Compare with frege98 42712. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶(t+‘𝑅)𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐵) | ||
Theorem | frege102d 42505 | If either 𝐴 and 𝐶 are the same or 𝐶 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅 and 𝐵 is the successor to 𝐶, then 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅. Similar to Proposition 102 of [Frege1879] p. 72. Compare with frege102 42716. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐶 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐶)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶𝑅𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐵) | ||
Theorem | frege106d 42506 | If 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in 𝑅, then either 𝐴 and 𝐵 are the same or 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in 𝑅. Similar to Proposition 106 of [Frege1879] p. 73. Compare with frege106 42720. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴𝑅𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | frege108d 42507 | If either 𝐴 and 𝐶 are the same or 𝐶 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅 and 𝐵 is the successor to 𝐶, then either 𝐴 and 𝐵 are the same or 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅. Similar to Proposition 108 of [Frege1879] p. 74. Compare with frege108 42722. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐶 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐶)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶𝑅𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | frege109d 42508 | If 𝐴 contains all elements of 𝑈 and all elements after those in 𝑈 in the transitive closure of 𝑅, then the image under 𝑅 of 𝐴 is a subclass of 𝐴. Similar to Proposition 109 of [Frege1879] p. 74. Compare with frege109 42723. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = (𝑈 ∪ ((t+‘𝑅) “ 𝑈))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | frege114d 42509 | If either 𝑅 relates 𝐴 and 𝐵 or 𝐴 and 𝐵 are the same, then either 𝐴 and 𝐵 are the same, 𝑅 relates 𝐴 and 𝐵, 𝑅 relates 𝐵 and 𝐴. Similar to Proposition 114 of [Frege1879] p. 76. Compare with frege114 42728. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴𝑅𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵𝑅𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | frege111d 42510 | If either 𝐴 and 𝐶 are the same or 𝐶 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅 and 𝐵 is the successor to 𝐶, then either 𝐴 and 𝐵 are the same or 𝐴 follows 𝐵 or 𝐵 and 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝑅. Similar to Proposition 111 of [Frege1879] p. 75. Compare with frege111 42725. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐶 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐶)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶𝑅𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝑅)𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵(t+‘𝑅)𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | frege122d 42511 | If 𝐹 is a function, 𝐴 is the successor of 𝑋, and 𝐵 is the successor of 𝑋, then 𝐴 and 𝐵 are the same (or 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝐹). Similar to Proposition 122 of [Frege1879] p. 79. Compare with frege122 42736. (Contributed by RP, 15-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = (𝐹‘𝑋)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = (𝐹‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝐹)𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | frege124d 42512 | If 𝐹 is a function, 𝐴 is the successor of 𝑋, and 𝐵 follows 𝑋 in the transitive closure of 𝐹, then 𝐴 and 𝐵 are the same or 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝐹. Similar to Proposition 124 of [Frege1879] p. 80. Compare with frege124 42738. (Contributed by RP, 16-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ dom 𝐹) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = (𝐹‘𝑋)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋(t+‘𝐹)𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝐹)𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | frege126d 42513 | If 𝐹 is a function, 𝐴 is the successor of 𝑋, and 𝐵 follows 𝑋 in the transitive closure of 𝐹, then (for distinct 𝐴 and 𝐵) either 𝐴 follows 𝐵 or 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝐹. Similar to Proposition 126 of [Frege1879] p. 81. Compare with frege126 42740. (Contributed by RP, 16-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ dom 𝐹) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = (𝐹‘𝑋)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋(t+‘𝐹)𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝐹)𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵(t+‘𝐹)𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | frege129d 42514 | If 𝐹 is a function and (for distinct 𝐴 and 𝐵) either 𝐴 follows 𝐵 or 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝐹, the successor of 𝐴 is either 𝐵 or it follows 𝐵 or it comes before 𝐵 in the transitive closure of 𝐹. Similar to Proposition 129 of [Frege1879] p. 83. Comparw with frege129 42743. (Contributed by RP, 16-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ dom 𝐹) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 = (𝐹‘𝐴)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝐹)𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵(t+‘𝐹)𝐴)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐵(t+‘𝐹)𝐶 ∨ 𝐵 = 𝐶 ∨ 𝐶(t+‘𝐹)𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | frege131d 42515 | If 𝐹 is a function and 𝐴 contains all elements of 𝑈 and all elements before or after those elements of 𝑈 in the transitive closure of 𝐹, then the image under 𝐹 of 𝐴 is a subclass of 𝐴. Similar to Proposition 131 of [Frege1879] p. 85. Compare with frege131 42745. (Contributed by RP, 17-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = (𝑈 ∪ ((◡(t+‘𝐹) “ 𝑈) ∪ ((t+‘𝐹) “ 𝑈)))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | frege133d 42516 | If 𝐹 is a function and 𝐴 and 𝐵 both follow 𝑋 in the transitive closure of 𝐹, then (for distinct 𝐴 and 𝐵) either 𝐴 follows 𝐵 or 𝐵 follows 𝐴 in the transitive closure of 𝐹 (or both if it loops). Similar to Proposition 133 of [Frege1879] p. 86. Compare with frege133 42747. (Contributed by RP, 18-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋(t+‘𝐹)𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋(t+‘𝐹)𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → Fun 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴(t+‘𝐹)𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵(t+‘𝐹)𝐴)) | ||
In 1879, Frege introduced notation for documenting formal reasoning about propositions (and classes) which covered elements of propositional logic, predicate calculus and reasoning about relations. However, due to the pitfalls of naive set theory, adapting this work for inclusion in set.mm required dividing statements about propositions from those about classes and identifying when a restriction to sets is required. For an overview comparing the details of Frege's two-dimensional notation and that used in set.mm, see mmfrege.html. See ru 3777 for discussion of an example of a class that is not a set. Numbered propositions from [Frege1879]. ax-frege1 42541, ax-frege2 42542, ax-frege8 42560, ax-frege28 42581, ax-frege31 42585, ax-frege41 42596, frege52 (see ax-frege52a 42608, frege52b 42640, and ax-frege52c 42639 for translations), frege54 (see ax-frege54a 42613, frege54b 42644 and ax-frege54c 42643 for translations) and frege58 (see ax-frege58a 42626, ax-frege58b 42652 and frege58c 42672 for translations) are considered "core" or axioms. However, at least ax-frege8 42560 can be derived from ax-frege1 42541 and ax-frege2 42542, see axfrege8 42558. Frege introduced implication, negation and the universal quantifier as primitives and did not in the numbered propositions use other logical connectives other than equivalence introduced in ax-frege52a 42608, frege52b 42640, and ax-frege52c 42639. In dffrege69 42683, Frege introduced 𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 to say that relation 𝑅, when restricted to operate on elements of class 𝐴, will only have elements of class 𝐴 in its domain; see df-he 42524 for a definition in terms of image and subset. In dffrege76 42690, Frege introduced notation for the concept of two sets related by the transitive closure of a relation, for which we write 𝑋(t+‘𝑅)𝑌, which requires 𝑅 to also be a set. In dffrege99 42713, Frege introduced notation for the concept of two sets either identical or related by the transitive closure of a relation, for which we write 𝑋((t+‘𝑅) ∪ I )𝑌, which is a superclass of sets related by the reflexive-transitive relation 𝑋(t*‘𝑅)𝑌. Finally, in dffrege115 42729, Frege introduced notation for the concept of a relation having the property elements in its domain pair up with only one element each in its range, for which we write Fun ◡◡𝑅 (to ignore any non-relational content of the class 𝑅). Frege did this without the expressing concept of a relation (or its transitive closure) as a class, and needed to invent conventions for discussing indeterminate propositions with two slots free and how to recognize which of the slots was domain and which was range. See mmfrege.html 42729 for details. English translations for specific propositions lifted in part from a translation by Stefan Bauer-Mengelberg as reprinted in From Frege to Goedel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931. An attempt to align these propositions in the larger set.mm database has also been made. See frege77d 42497 for an example. | ||
Section 2 introduces the turnstile ⊢ which turns an idea which may be true 𝜑 into an assertion that it does hold true ⊢ 𝜑. Section 5 introduces implication, (𝜑 → 𝜓). Section 6 introduces the single rule of interference relied upon, modus ponens ax-mp 5. Section 7 introduces negation and with in synonyms for or (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓), and ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓), and two for exclusive-or corresponding to df-or 847, df-an 398, dfxor4 42517, dfxor5 42518. Section 8 introduces the problematic notation for identity of conceptual content which must be separated into cases for biconditional (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) or class equality 𝐴 = 𝐵 in this adaptation. Section 10 introduces "truth functions" for one or two variables in equally troubling notation, as the arguments may be understood to be logical predicates or collections. Here f(𝜑) is interpreted to mean if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) where the content of the "function" is specified by the latter two argments or logical equivalent, while g(𝐴) is read as 𝐴 ∈ 𝐺 and h(𝐴, 𝐵) as 𝐴𝐻𝐵. This necessarily introduces a need for set theory as both 𝐴 ∈ 𝐺 and 𝐴𝐻𝐵 cannot hold unless 𝐴 is a set. (Also 𝐵.) Section 11 introduces notation for generality, but there is no standard notation for generality when the variable is a proposition because it was realized after Frege that the universe of all possible propositions includes paradoxical constructions leading to the failure of naive set theory. So adopting f(𝜑) as if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) would result in the translation of ∀𝜑 f (𝜑) as (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒). For collections, we must generalize over set variables or run into the same problems; this leads to ∀𝐴 g(𝐴) being translated as ∀𝑎𝑎 ∈ 𝐺 and so forth. Under this interpreation the text of section 11 gives us sp 2177 (or simpl 484 and simpr 486 and anifp 1071 in the propositional case) and statements similar to cbvalivw 2011, ax-gen 1798, alrimiv 1931, and alrimdv 1933. These last four introduce a generality and have no useful definition in terms of propositional variables. Section 12 introduces some combinations of primitive symbols and their human language counterparts. Using class notation, these can also be expressed without dummy variables. All are A, ∀𝑥𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, ¬ ∃𝑥¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 alex 1829, 𝐴 = V eqv 3484; Some are not B, ¬ ∀𝑥𝑥 ∈ 𝐵, ∃𝑥¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 exnal 1830, 𝐵 ⊊ V pssv 4447, 𝐵 ≠ V nev 42521; There are no C, ∀𝑥¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐶, ¬ ∃𝑥𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 alnex 1784, 𝐶 = ∅ eq0 4344; There exist D, ¬ ∀𝑥¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐷, ∃𝑥𝑥 ∈ 𝐷 df-ex 1783, ∅ ⊊ 𝐷 0pss 4445, 𝐷 ≠ ∅ n0 4347. Notation for relations between expressions also can be written in various ways. All E are P, ∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐸 → 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃), ¬ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐸 ∧ ¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃) dfss6 3972, 𝐸 = (𝐸 ∩ 𝑃) df-ss 3966, 𝐸 ⊆ 𝑃 dfss2 3969; No F are P, ∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐹 → ¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃), ¬ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐹 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃) alinexa 1846, (𝐹 ∩ 𝑃) = ∅ disj1 4451; Some G are not P, ¬ ∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐺 → 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃), ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ ¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃) exanali 1863, (𝐺 ∩ 𝑃) ⊊ 𝐺 nssinpss 4257, ¬ 𝐺 ⊆ 𝑃 nss 4047; Some H are P, ¬ ∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐻 → ¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃), ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐻 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑃) exnalimn 1847, ∅ ⊊ (𝐻 ∩ 𝑃) 0pssin 42522, (𝐻 ∩ 𝑃) ≠ ∅ ndisj 4368. | ||
Theorem | dfxor4 42517 | Express exclusive-or in terms of implication and negation. Statement in [Frege1879] p. 12. (Contributed by RP, 14-Apr-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | dfxor5 42518 | Express exclusive-or in terms of implication and negation. Statement in [Frege1879] p. 12. (Contributed by RP, 14-Apr-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ⊻ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ ((𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) → ¬ (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | df3or2 42519 | Express triple-or in terms of implication and negation. Statement in [Frege1879] p. 11. (Contributed by RP, 25-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒) ↔ (¬ 𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | df3an2 42520 | Express triple-and in terms of implication and negation. Statement in [Frege1879] p. 12. (Contributed by RP, 25-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ↔ ¬ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → ¬ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | nev 42521* | Express that not every set is in a class. (Contributed by RP, 16-Apr-2020.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≠ V ↔ ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | 0pssin 42522* | Express that an intersection is not empty. (Contributed by RP, 16-Apr-2020.) |
⊢ (∅ ⊊ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
The statement 𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 means relation 𝑅 is hereditary (in the sense of Frege) in the class 𝐴 or (𝑅 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴. The former is only a slight reduction in the number of symbols, but this reduces the number of floating hypotheses needed to be checked. As Frege was not using the language of classes or sets, this naturally differs from the set-theoretic notion that a set is hereditary in a property: that all of its elements have a property and all of their elements have the property and so-on. | ||
Syntax | whe 42523 | The property of relation 𝑅 being hereditary in class 𝐴. |
wff 𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 | ||
Definition | df-he 42524 | The property of relation 𝑅 being hereditary in class 𝐴. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 ↔ (𝑅 “ 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dfhe2 42525 | The property of relation 𝑅 being hereditary in class 𝐴. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 ↔ (𝑅 ↾ 𝐴) ⊆ (𝐴 × 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dfhe3 42526* | The property of relation 𝑅 being hereditary in class 𝐴. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → ∀𝑦(𝑥𝑅𝑦 → 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | heeq12 42527 | Equality law for relations being herditary over a class. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 = 𝑆 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝐵) → (𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 hereditary 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | heeq1 42528 | Equality law for relations being herditary over a class. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = 𝑆 → (𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 hereditary 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | heeq2 42529 | Equality law for relations being herditary over a class. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 ↔ 𝑅 hereditary 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | sbcheg 42530 | Distribute proper substitution through herditary relation. (Contributed by RP, 29-Jun-2020.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]𝐵 hereditary 𝐶 ↔ ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐵 hereditary ⦋𝐴 / 𝑥⦌𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | hess 42531 | Subclass law for relations being herditary over a class. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝑆 ⊆ 𝑅 → (𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 → 𝑆 hereditary 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | xphe 42532 | Any Cartesian product is hereditary in its second class. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) (Proof shortened by OpenAI, 3-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ (𝐴 × 𝐵) hereditary 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | 0he 42533 | The empty relation is hereditary in any class. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ ∅ hereditary 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | 0heALT 42534 | The empty relation is hereditary in any class. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∅ hereditary 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | he0 42535 | Any relation is hereditary in the empty set. (Contributed by RP, 27-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ 𝐴 hereditary ∅ | ||
Theorem | unhe1 42536 | The union of two relations hereditary in a class is also hereditary in a class. (Contributed by RP, 28-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 hereditary 𝐴 ∧ 𝑆 hereditary 𝐴) → (𝑅 ∪ 𝑆) hereditary 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | snhesn 42537 | Any singleton is hereditary in any singleton. (Contributed by RP, 28-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ {⟨𝐴, 𝐴⟩} hereditary {𝐵} | ||
Theorem | idhe 42538 | The identity relation is hereditary in any class. (Contributed by RP, 28-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ I hereditary 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | psshepw 42539 | The relation between sets and their proper subsets is hereditary in the powerclass of any class. (Contributed by RP, 28-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ ◡ [⊊] hereditary 𝒫 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | sshepw 42540 | The relation between sets and their subsets is hereditary in the powerclass of any class. (Contributed by RP, 28-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (◡ [⊊] ∪ I ) hereditary 𝒫 𝐴 | ||
Axiom | ax-frege1 42541 | The case in which 𝜑 is denied, 𝜓 is affirmed, and 𝜑 is affirmed is excluded. This is evident since 𝜑 cannot at the same time be denied and affirmed. Axiom 1 of [Frege1879] p. 26. Identical to ax-1 6. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜑)) | ||
Axiom | ax-frege2 42542 | If a proposition 𝜒 is a necessary consequence of two propositions 𝜓 and 𝜑 and one of those, 𝜓, is in turn a necessary consequence of the other, 𝜑, then the proposition 𝜒 is a necessary consequence of the latter one, 𝜑, alone. Axiom 2 of [Frege1879] p. 26. Identical to ax-2 7. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | rp-simp2-frege 42543 | Simplification of triple conjunction. Compare with simp2 1138. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | rp-simp2 42544 | Simplification of triple conjunction. Identical to simp2 1138. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | rp-frege3g 42545 |
Add antecedent to ax-frege2 42542. More general statement than frege3 42546.
Like ax-frege2 42542, it is essentially a closed form of mpd 15,
however it
has an extra antecedent.
It would be more natural to prove from a1i 11 and ax-frege2 42542 in Metamath. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜓 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | frege3 42546 | Add antecedent to ax-frege2 42542. Special case of rp-frege3g 42545. Proposition 3 of [Frege1879] p. 29. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) → ((𝜒 → 𝜑) → (𝜒 → 𝜓)))) | ||
Theorem | rp-misc1-frege 42547 | Double-use of ax-frege2 42542. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) → ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | rp-frege24 42548 | Introducing an embedded antecedent. Alternate proof for frege24 42566. Closed form for a1d 25. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | rp-frege4g 42549 | Deduction related to distribution. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) → (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜓 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | frege4 42550 | Special case of closed form of a2d 29. Special case of rp-frege4g 42549. Proposition 4 of [Frege1879] p. 31. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜓))) → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → 𝜑) → (𝜒 → 𝜓)))) | ||
Theorem | frege5 42551 | A closed form of syl 17. Identical to imim2 58. Theorem *2.05 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 100. Proposition 5 of [Frege1879] p. 32. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → 𝜑) → (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | rp-7frege 42552 | Distribute antecedent and add another. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜃 → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | rp-4frege 42553 | Elimination of a nested antecedent of special form. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜑) → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | rp-6frege 42554 | Elimination of a nested antecedent of special form. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → ((𝜒 → 𝜓) → 𝜃)) → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | rp-8frege 42555 | Eliminate antecedent when it is implied by previous antecedent. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → ((𝜒 → 𝜓) → 𝜃))) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | rp-frege25 42556 | Closed form for a1dd 50. Alternate route to Proposition 25 of [Frege1879] p. 42. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | frege6 42557 | A closed form of imim2d 57 which is a deduction adding nested antecedents. Proposition 6 of [Frege1879] p. 33. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → ((𝜃 → 𝜓) → (𝜃 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | axfrege8 42558 |
Swap antecedents. Identical to pm2.04 90. This demonstrates that Axiom 8
of [Frege1879] p. 35 is redundant.
Proof follows closely proof of pm2.04 90 in https://us.metamath.org/mmsolitaire/pmproofs.txt 90, but in the style of Frege's 1879 work. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | frege7 42559 | A closed form of syl6 35. The first antecedent is used to replace the consequent of the second antecedent. Proposition 7 of [Frege1879] p. 34. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜑)) → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜓)))) | ||
Axiom | ax-frege8 42560 | Swap antecedents. If two conditions have a proposition as a consequence, their order is immaterial. Third axiom of Frege's 1879 work but identical to pm2.04 90 which can be proved from only ax-mp 5, ax-frege1 42541, and ax-frege2 42542. (Redundant) Axiom 8 of [Frege1879] p. 35. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | frege26 42561 | Identical to idd 24. Proposition 26 of [Frege1879] p. 42. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | frege27 42562 | We cannot (at the same time) affirm 𝜑 and deny 𝜑. Identical to id 22. Proposition 27 of [Frege1879] p. 43. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | frege9 42563 | Closed form of syl 17 with swapped antecedents. This proposition differs from frege5 42551 only in an unessential way. Identical to imim1 83. Proposition 9 of [Frege1879] p. 35. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | frege12 42564 | A closed form of com23 86. Proposition 12 of [Frege1879] p. 37. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) → (𝜑 → (𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | frege11 42565 | Elimination of a nested antecedent as a partial converse of ja 186. If the proposition that 𝜓 takes place or 𝜑 does not is a sufficient condition for 𝜒, then 𝜓 by itself is a sufficient condition for 𝜒. Identical to jarr 106. Proposition 11 of [Frege1879] p. 36. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | frege24 42566 | Closed form for a1d 25. Deduction introducing an embedded antecedent. Identical to rp-frege24 42548 which was proved without relying on ax-frege8 42560. Proposition 24 of [Frege1879] p. 42. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | frege16 42567 | A closed form of com34 91. Proposition 16 of [Frege1879] p. 38. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))))) | ||
Theorem | frege25 42568 | Closed form for a1dd 50. Proposition 25 of [Frege1879] p. 42. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | frege18 42569 | Closed form of a syllogism followed by a swap of antecedents. Proposition 18 of [Frege1879] p. 39. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜃 → 𝜑) → (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜒)))) | ||
Theorem | frege22 42570 | A closed form of com45 97. Proposition 22 of [Frege1879] p. 41. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → (𝜏 → 𝜂))))) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜏 → (𝜃 → 𝜂)))))) | ||
Theorem | frege10 42571 | Result commuting antecedents within an antecedent. Proposition 10 of [Frege1879] p. 36. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → 𝜃) → ((𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | frege17 42572 | A closed form of com3l 89. Proposition 17 of [Frege1879] p. 39. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | frege13 42573 | A closed form of com3r 87. Proposition 13 of [Frege1879] p. 37. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | frege14 42574 | Closed form of a deduction based on com3r 87. Proposition 14 of [Frege1879] p. 37. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) → (𝜑 → (𝜃 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))))) | ||
Theorem | frege19 42575 | A closed form of syl6 35. Proposition 19 of [Frege1879] p. 39. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜒 → 𝜃) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | frege23 42576 | Syllogism followed by rotation of three antecedents. Proposition 23 of [Frege1879] p. 42. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) → ((𝜏 → 𝜑) → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜏 → 𝜃))))) | ||
Theorem | frege15 42577 | A closed form of com4r 94. Proposition 15 of [Frege1879] p. 38. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)))) → (𝜃 → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))))) | ||
Theorem | frege21 42578 | Replace antecedent in antecedent. Proposition 21 of [Frege1879] p. 40. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → ((𝜑 → 𝜃) → ((𝜃 → 𝜓) → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | frege20 42579 | A closed form of syl8 76. Proposition 20 of [Frege1879] p. 40. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃))) → ((𝜃 → 𝜏) → (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜏))))) | ||
Theorem | axfrege28 42580 | Contraposition. Identical to con3 153. Theorem *2.16 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 103. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (¬ 𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Axiom | ax-frege28 42581 | Contraposition. Identical to con3 153. Theorem *2.16 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 103. Axiom 28 of [Frege1879] p. 43. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (¬ 𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | frege29 42582 | Closed form of con3d 152. Proposition 29 of [Frege1879] p. 43. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜒 → ¬ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | frege30 42583 | Commuted, closed form of con3d 152. Proposition 30 of [Frege1879] p. 44. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜓 → (¬ 𝜒 → ¬ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axfrege31 42584 | Identical to notnotr 130. Axiom 31 of [Frege1879] p. 44. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ (¬ ¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-frege31 42585 | 𝜑 cannot be denied and (at the same time ) ¬ ¬ 𝜑 affirmed. Duplex negatio affirmat. The denial of the denial is affirmation. Identical to notnotr 130. Axiom 31 of [Frege1879] p. 44. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ ¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | frege32 42586 | Deduce con1 146 from con3 153. Proposition 32 of [Frege1879] p. 44. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → (¬ 𝜓 → ¬ ¬ 𝜑)) → ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | frege33 42587 | If 𝜑 or 𝜓 takes place, then 𝜓 or 𝜑 takes place. Identical to con1 146. Proposition 33 of [Frege1879] p. 44. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | frege34 42588 | If as a consequence of the occurrence of the circumstance 𝜑, when the obstacle 𝜓 is removed, 𝜒 takes place, then from the circumstance that 𝜒 does not take place while 𝜑 occurs the occurrence of the obstacle 𝜓 can be inferred. Closed form of con1d 145. Proposition 34 of [Frege1879] p. 45. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | frege35 42589 | Commuted, closed form of con1d 145. Proposition 35 of [Frege1879] p. 45. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (¬ 𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | frege36 42590 | The case in which 𝜓 is denied, ¬ 𝜑 is affirmed, and 𝜑 is affirmed does not occur. If 𝜑 occurs, then (at least) one of the two, 𝜑 or 𝜓, takes place (no matter what 𝜓 might be). Identical to pm2.24 124. Proposition 36 of [Frege1879] p. 45. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | frege37 42591 | If 𝜒 is a necessary consequence of the occurrence of 𝜓 or 𝜑, then 𝜒 is a necessary consequence of 𝜑 alone. Similar to a closed form of orcs 874. Proposition 37 of [Frege1879] p. 46. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | frege38 42592 | Identical to pm2.21 123. Proposition 38 of [Frege1879] p. 46. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | frege39 42593 | Syllogism between pm2.18 128 and pm2.24 124. Proposition 39 of [Frege1879] p. 46. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑) → (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | frege40 42594 | Anything implies pm2.18 128. Proposition 40 of [Frege1879] p. 46. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → ((¬ 𝜓 → 𝜓) → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | axfrege41 42595 | Identical to notnot 142. Axiom 41 of [Frege1879] p. 47. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Axiom | ax-frege41 42596 | The affirmation of 𝜑 denies the denial of 𝜑. Identical to notnot 142. Axiom 41 of [Frege1879] p. 47. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | frege42 42597 | Not not id 22. Proposition 42 of [Frege1879] p. 47. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ¬ ¬ (𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | frege43 42598 | If there is a choice only between 𝜑 and 𝜑, then 𝜑 takes place. Identical to pm2.18 128. Proposition 43 of [Frege1879] p. 47. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑) → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | frege44 42599 | Similar to a commuted pm2.62 899. Proposition 44 of [Frege1879] p. 47. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜓 → 𝜑) → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | frege45 42600 | Deduce pm2.6 190 from con1 146. Proposition 45 of [Frege1879] p. 47. (Contributed by RP, 24-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜑)) → ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |