![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 57 of 491) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30946) |
![]() (30947-32469) |
![]() (32470-49035) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | poeq12d 5601 | Equality deduction for partial orderings. (Contributed by Matthew House, 10-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 Po 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 Po 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | nfpo 5602 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for partial orders. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑅 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥 𝑅 Po 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | nfso 5603 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for total orders. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑅 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥 𝑅 Or 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | pocl 5604 | Characteristic properties of a partial order in class notation. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1997.) Reduce axiom usage and shorten proof. (Revised by GG, 3-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Po 𝐴 → ((𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴) → (¬ 𝐵𝑅𝐵 ∧ ((𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐷) → 𝐵𝑅𝐷)))) | ||
Theorem | ispod 5605* | Sufficient conditions for a partial order. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → ¬ 𝑥𝑅𝑥) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴)) → ((𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∧ 𝑦𝑅𝑧) → 𝑥𝑅𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Po 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | swopolem 5606* | Perform the substitutions into the strict weak ordering law. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝑥𝑅𝑦 → (𝑥𝑅𝑧 ∨ 𝑧𝑅𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝑋𝑅𝑌 → (𝑋𝑅𝑍 ∨ 𝑍𝑅𝑌))) | ||
Theorem | swopo 5607* | A strict weak order is a partial order. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝑦𝑅𝑧 → ¬ 𝑧𝑅𝑦)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝑥𝑅𝑦 → (𝑥𝑅𝑧 ∨ 𝑧𝑅𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Po 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | poirr 5608 | A partial order is irreflexive. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Po 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ¬ 𝐵𝑅𝐵) | ||
Theorem | potr 5609 | A partial order is a transitive relation. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Po 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)) → ((𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐷) → 𝐵𝑅𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | po2nr 5610 | A partial order has no 2-cycle loops. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Po 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → ¬ (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | po3nr 5611 | A partial order has no 3-cycle loops. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Po 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)) → ¬ (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐷 ∧ 𝐷𝑅𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | po2ne 5612 | Two sets related by a partial order are not equal. (Contributed by AV, 13-Mar-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Po 𝑉 ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) ∧ 𝐴𝑅𝐵) → 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | po0 5613 | Any relation is a partial order on the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ 𝑅 Po ∅ | ||
Theorem | pofun 5614* | The inverse image of a partial order is a partial order. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 18-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝑋𝑅𝑌} & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝑋 = 𝑌) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 Po 𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝑆 Po 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | sopo 5615 | A strict linear order is a strict partial order. (Contributed by NM, 28-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Or 𝐴 → 𝑅 Po 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | soss 5616 | Subset theorem for the strict ordering predicate. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (𝑅 Or 𝐵 → 𝑅 Or 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | soeq1 5617 | Equality theorem for the strict ordering predicate. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = 𝑆 → (𝑅 Or 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 Or 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | soeq2 5618 | Equality theorem for the strict ordering predicate. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝑅 Or 𝐴 ↔ 𝑅 Or 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | soeq12d 5619 | Equality deduction for total orderings. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Jan-2015.) (Proof shortened by Matthew House, 10-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 Or 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 Or 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | sonr 5620 | A strict order relation is irreflexive. (Contributed by NM, 24-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ¬ 𝐵𝑅𝐵) | ||
Theorem | sotr 5621 | A strict order relation is a transitive relation. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-1996.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)) → ((𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐷) → 𝐵𝑅𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | solin 5622 | A strict order relation is linear (satisfies trichotomy). (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-1996.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∨ 𝐵 = 𝐶 ∨ 𝐶𝑅𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | so2nr 5623 | A strict order relation has no 2-cycle loops. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-1996.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → ¬ (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | so3nr 5624 | A strict order relation has no 3-cycle loops. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-1996.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)) → ¬ (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐷 ∧ 𝐷𝑅𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | sotric 5625 | A strict order relation satisfies strict trichotomy. (Contributed by NM, 19-Feb-1996.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ↔ ¬ (𝐵 = 𝐶 ∨ 𝐶𝑅𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | sotrieq 5626 | Trichotomy law for strict order relation. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1996.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝐵 = 𝐶 ↔ ¬ (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∨ 𝐶𝑅𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | sotrieq2 5627 | Trichotomy law for strict order relation. (Contributed by NM, 5-May-1999.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝐵 = 𝐶 ↔ (¬ 𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ ¬ 𝐶𝑅𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | soasym 5628 | Asymmetry law for strict orderings. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 24-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝑋𝑅𝑌 → ¬ 𝑌𝑅𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | sotr2 5629 | A transitivity relation. (Read 𝐵 ≤ 𝐶 and 𝐶 < 𝐷 implies 𝐵 < 𝐷.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 10-May-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐴)) → ((¬ 𝐶𝑅𝐵 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐷) → 𝐵𝑅𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | issod 5630* | An irreflexive, transitive, linear relation is a strict ordering. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Po 𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∨ 𝑥 = 𝑦 ∨ 𝑦𝑅𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Or 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | issoi 5631* | An irreflexive, transitive, linear relation is a strict ordering. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jan-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → ¬ 𝑥𝑅𝑥) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴) → ((𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∧ 𝑦𝑅𝑧) → 𝑥𝑅𝑧)) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∨ 𝑥 = 𝑦 ∨ 𝑦𝑅𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝑅 Or 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | isso2i 5632* | Deduce strict ordering from its properties. (Contributed by NM, 29-Jan-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝑥𝑅𝑦 ↔ ¬ (𝑥 = 𝑦 ∨ 𝑦𝑅𝑥))) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴) → ((𝑥𝑅𝑦 ∧ 𝑦𝑅𝑧) → 𝑥𝑅𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝑅 Or 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | so0 5633 | Any relation is a strict ordering of the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ 𝑅 Or ∅ | ||
Theorem | somo 5634* | A totally ordered set has at most one minimal element. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Or 𝐴 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥) | ||
Theorem | sotrine 5635 | Trichotomy law for strict orderings. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝐵 ≠ 𝐶 ↔ (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∨ 𝐶𝑅𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | sotr3 5636 | Transitivity law for strict orderings. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 24-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Or 𝐴 ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐴)) → ((𝑋𝑅𝑌 ∧ ¬ 𝑍𝑅𝑌) → 𝑋𝑅𝑍)) | ||
Syntax | wfr 5637 | Extend wff notation to include the well-founded predicate. Read: "𝑅 is a well-founded relation on 𝐴". |
wff 𝑅 Fr 𝐴 | ||
Syntax | wse 5638 | Extend wff notation to include the set-like predicate. Read: "𝑅 is set-like on 𝐴". |
wff 𝑅 Se 𝐴 | ||
Syntax | wwe 5639 | Extend wff notation to include the well-ordering predicate. Read: "𝑅 well-orders 𝐴". |
wff 𝑅 We 𝐴 | ||
Definition | df-fr 5640* | Define the well-founded relation predicate. Definition 6.24(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 30. For alternate definitions, see dffr2 5649 and dffr3 6119. A class is called well-founded when the membership relation E (see df-eprel 5588) is well-founded on it, that is, 𝐴 is well-founded if E Fr 𝐴 (some sources request that the membership relation be well-founded on its transitive closure). (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ¬ 𝑧𝑅𝑦)) | ||
Definition | df-se 5641* | Define the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 19-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Se 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝑦𝑅𝑥} ∈ V) | ||
Definition | df-we 5642 | Define the well-ordering predicate. For an alternate definition, see dfwe2 7792. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝑅 We 𝐴 ↔ (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ∧ 𝑅 Or 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dffr6 5643* | Alternate definition of df-fr 5640. See dffr5 35733 for a definition without dummy variables (but note that their equivalence uses ax-sep 5301). (Contributed by BJ, 16-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ (𝒫 𝐴 ∖ {∅})∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ¬ 𝑧𝑅𝑦) | ||
Theorem | frd 5644* | A nonempty subset of an 𝑅-well-founded class has an 𝑅-minimal element (deduction form). (Contributed by BJ, 16-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Fr 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ≠ ∅) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥) | ||
Theorem | fri 5645* | A nonempty subset of an 𝑅-well-founded class has an 𝑅-minimal element (inference form). (Contributed by BJ, 16-Nov-2024.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 19-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (((𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝑅 Fr 𝐴) ∧ (𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥) | ||
Theorem | friOLD 5646* | Obsolete version of fri 5645 as of 16-Nov-2024. (Contributed by NM, 18-Mar-1997.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝑅 Fr 𝐴) ∧ (𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥) | ||
Theorem | seex 5647* | The 𝑅-preimage of an element of the base set in a set-like relation is a set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 19-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Se 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝑥𝑅𝐵} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | exse 5648 | Any relation on a set is set-like on it. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dffr2 5649* | Alternate definition of well-founded relation. Similar to Definition 6.21 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 30. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 27-Aug-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 23-Jun-2015.) Avoid ax-10 2138, ax-11 2154, ax-12 2174, but use ax-8 2107. (Revised by GG, 3-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 {𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∣ 𝑧𝑅𝑦} = ∅)) | ||
Theorem | dffr2ALT 5650* | Alternate proof of dffr2 5649, which avoids ax-8 2107 but requires ax-10 2138, ax-11 2154, ax-12 2174. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 27-Aug-2011.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 23-Jun-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 {𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∣ 𝑧𝑅𝑦} = ∅)) | ||
Theorem | frc 5651* | Property of well-founded relation (one direction of definition using class variables). (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 {𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝑦𝑅𝑥} = ∅) | ||
Theorem | frss 5652 | Subset theorem for the well-founded predicate. Exercise 1 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 31. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (𝑅 Fr 𝐵 → 𝑅 Fr 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | sess1 5653 | Subset theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 ⊆ 𝑆 → (𝑆 Se 𝐴 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | sess2 5654 | Subset theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (𝑅 Se 𝐵 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | freq1 5655 | Equality theorem for the well-founded predicate. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = 𝑆 → (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 Fr 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | freq2 5656 | Equality theorem for the well-founded predicate. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ 𝑅 Fr 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | freq12d 5657 | Equality deduction for well-founded relations. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Jan-2015.) (Proof shortened by Matthew House, 10-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 Fr 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | seeq1 5658 | Equality theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = 𝑆 → (𝑅 Se 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 Se 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | seeq2 5659 | Equality theorem for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝑅 Se 𝐴 ↔ 𝑅 Se 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | seeq12d 5660 | Equality deduction for the set-like predicate. (Contributed by Matthew House, 10-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 Se 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 Se 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | nffr 5661 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for well-founded relations. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑅 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥 𝑅 Fr 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | nfse 5662 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for set-like relations. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑅 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥 𝑅 Se 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | nfwe 5663 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for well-orderings. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 20-Jan-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑅 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥 𝑅 We 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | frirr 5664 | A well-founded relation is irreflexive. Special case of Proposition 6.23 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 30. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ¬ 𝐵𝑅𝐵) | ||
Theorem | fr2nr 5665 | A well-founded relation has no 2-cycle loops. Special case of Proposition 6.23 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 30. (Contributed by NM, 30-May-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → ¬ (𝐵𝑅𝐶 ∧ 𝐶𝑅𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | fr0 5666 | Any relation is well-founded on the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1993.) |
⊢ 𝑅 Fr ∅ | ||
Theorem | frminex 5667* | If an element of a well-founded set satisfies a property 𝜑, then there is a minimal element that satisfies 𝜑. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 18-Jun-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 18-Nov-2016.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 → (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜓 → ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥)))) | ||
Theorem | efrirr 5668 | A well-founded class does not belong to itself. (Contributed by NM, 18-Apr-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ( E Fr 𝐴 → ¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | efrn2lp 5669 | A well-founded class contains no 2-cycle loops. (Contributed by NM, 19-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (( E Fr 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → ¬ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | epse 5670 | The membership relation is set-like on any class. (This is the origin of the term "set-like": a set-like relation "acts like" the membership relation of sets and their elements.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ E Se 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | tz7.2 5671 | Similar to Theorem 7.2 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 35, except that the Axiom of Regularity is not required due to the antecedent E Fr 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 4-May-1994.) |
⊢ ((Tr 𝐴 ∧ E Fr 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dfepfr 5672* | An alternate way of saying that the membership relation is well-founded. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 23-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ( E Fr 𝐴 ↔ ∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑥 ∩ 𝑦) = ∅)) | ||
Theorem | epfrc 5673* | A subset of a well-founded class has a minimal element. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2004.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 22-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (( E Fr 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 (𝐵 ∩ 𝑥) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | wess 5674 | Subset theorem for the well-ordering predicate. Exercise 4 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 31. (Contributed by NM, 19-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → (𝑅 We 𝐵 → 𝑅 We 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | weeq1 5675 | Equality theorem for the well-ordering predicate. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = 𝑆 → (𝑅 We 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 We 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | weeq2 5676 | Equality theorem for the well-ordering predicate. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → (𝑅 We 𝐴 ↔ 𝑅 We 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | weeq12d 5677 | Equality deduction for well-orderings. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Jan-2015.) (Proof shortened by Matthew House, 10-Sep-2025.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 = 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅 We 𝐴 ↔ 𝑆 We 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | wefr 5678 | A well-ordering is well-founded. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (𝑅 We 𝐴 → 𝑅 Fr 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | weso 5679 | A well-ordering is a strict ordering. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ (𝑅 We 𝐴 → 𝑅 Or 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | wecmpep 5680 | The elements of a class well-ordered by membership are comparable. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1994.) |
⊢ (( E We 𝐴 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴)) → (𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∨ 𝑥 = 𝑦 ∨ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | wetrep 5681 | On a class well-ordered by membership, the membership predicate is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 22-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ (( E We 𝐴 ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴)) → ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧)) | ||
Theorem | wefrc 5682* | A nonempty subclass of a class well-ordered by membership has a minimal element. Special case of Proposition 6.26 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 31. (Contributed by NM, 17-Feb-2004.) |
⊢ (( E We 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅) → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 (𝐵 ∩ 𝑥) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | we0 5683 | Any relation is a well-ordering of the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 16-Mar-1997.) |
⊢ 𝑅 We ∅ | ||
Theorem | wereu 5684* | A nonempty subset of an 𝑅-well-ordered class has a unique 𝑅 -minimal element. (Contributed by NM, 18-Mar-1997.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 We 𝐴 ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥) | ||
Theorem | wereu2 5685* | A nonempty subclass of an 𝑅-well-ordered and 𝑅-setlike class has a unique 𝑅-minimal element. Proposition 6.26 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 31. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 29-Jan-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝑅 We 𝐴 ∧ 𝑅 Se 𝐴) ∧ (𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) → ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥) | ||
Syntax | cxp 5686 | Extend the definition of a class to include the Cartesian product. |
class (𝐴 × 𝐵) | ||
Syntax | ccnv 5687 | Extend the definition of a class to include the converse of a class. |
class ◡𝐴 | ||
Syntax | cdm 5688 | Extend the definition of a class to include the domain of a class. |
class dom 𝐴 | ||
Syntax | crn 5689 | Extend the definition of a class to include the range of a class. |
class ran 𝐴 | ||
Syntax | cres 5690 | Extend the definition of a class to include the restriction of a class. Read: "the restriction of 𝐴 to 𝐵". |
class (𝐴 ↾ 𝐵) | ||
Syntax | cima 5691 | Extend the definition of a class to include the image of a class. Read: "the image of 𝐵 under 𝐴". |
class (𝐴 “ 𝐵) | ||
Syntax | ccom 5692 | Extend the definition of a class to include the composition of two classes. (Read: The composition of 𝐴 and 𝐵.) |
class (𝐴 ∘ 𝐵) | ||
Syntax | wrel 5693 | Extend the definition of a wff to include the relation predicate. Read: "𝐴 is a relation". |
wff Rel 𝐴 | ||
Definition | df-xp 5694* | Define the Cartesian product of two classes. This is also sometimes called the "cross product" but that term also has other meanings; we intentionally choose a less ambiguous term. Definition 9.11 of [Quine] p. 64. For example, ({1, 5} × {2, 7}) = ({〈1, 2〉, 〈1, 7〉} ∪ {〈5, 2〉, 〈5, 7〉}) (ex-xp 30464). Another example is that the set of rational numbers is defined in df-q 12988 using the Cartesian product (ℤ × ℕ); the left- and right-hand sides of the Cartesian product represent the top (integer) and bottom (natural) numbers of a fraction. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 × 𝐵) = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵)} | ||
Definition | df-rel 5695 | Define the relation predicate. Definition 6.4(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 23. For alternate definitions, see dfrel2 6210 and dfrel3 6219. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (Rel 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 ⊆ (V × V)) | ||
Definition | df-cnv 5696* |
Define the converse of a class. Definition 9.12 of [Quine] p. 64. The
converse of a binary relation swaps its arguments, i.e., if 𝐴 ∈
V
and 𝐵 ∈ V then (𝐴◡𝑅𝐵 ↔ 𝐵𝑅𝐴), as proven in brcnv 5895
(see df-br 5148 and df-rel 5695 for more on relations). For example,
◡{〈2,
6〉, 〈3, 9〉} = {〈6, 2〉, 〈9, 3〉}
(ex-cnv 30465).
We use Quine's breve accent (smile) notation. Like Quine, we use it as a prefix, which eliminates the need for parentheses. "Converse" is Quine's terminology. Some authors use a "minus one" exponent and call it "inverse", especially when the argument is a function, although this is not in general a genuine inverse. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
⊢ ◡𝐴 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ 𝑦𝐴𝑥} | ||
Definition | df-co 5697* | Define the composition of two classes. Definition 6.6(3) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. For example, ((exp ∘ cos)‘0) = e (ex-co 30466) because (cos‘0) = 1 (see cos0 16182) and (exp‘1) = e (see df-e 16100). Note that Definition 7 of [Suppes] p. 63 reverses 𝐴 and 𝐵, uses / instead of ∘, and calls the operation "relative product". (Contributed by NM, 4-Jul-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∘ 𝐵) = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ ∃𝑧(𝑥𝐵𝑧 ∧ 𝑧𝐴𝑦)} | ||
Definition | df-dm 5698* | Define the domain of a class. Definition 3 of [Suppes] p. 59. For example, 𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} → dom 𝐹 = {2, 3} (ex-dm 30467). Another example is the domain of the complex arctangent, (𝐴 ∈ dom arctan ↔ (𝐴 ∈ ℂ ∧ 𝐴 ≠ -i ∧ 𝐴 ≠ i)) (for proof see atandm 26933). Contrast with range (defined in df-rn 5699). For alternate definitions see dfdm2 6302, dfdm3 5900, and dfdm4 5908. The notation "dom " is used by Enderton; other authors sometimes use script D. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ dom 𝐴 = {𝑥 ∣ ∃𝑦 𝑥𝐴𝑦} | ||
Definition | df-rn 5699 | Define the range of a class. For example, 𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} → ran 𝐹 = {6, 9} (ex-rn 30468). Contrast with domain (defined in df-dm 5698). For alternate definitions, see dfrn2 5901, dfrn3 5902, and dfrn4 6223. The notation "ran " is used by Enderton. The range of a function is often also called "the image of the function" (see definition in [Lang] p. ix), which can be justified by imadmrn 6089. Not to be confused with "codomain" (see df-f 6566), which may be a superset/superclass of the range (see frn 6743). (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ ran 𝐴 = dom ◡𝐴 | ||
Definition | df-res 5700 | Define the restriction of a class. Definition 6.6(1) of [TakeutiZaring] p. 24. For example, the expression (exp ↾ ℝ) (used in reeff1 16152) means "the exponential function e to the x, but the exponent x must be in the reals" (df-ef 16099 defines the exponential function, which normally allows the exponent to be a complex number). Another example is (𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} ∧ 𝐵 = {1, 2}) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) = {〈2, 6〉} (ex-res 30469). We do not introduce a special syntax for the corestriction of a class: it will be expressed either as the intersection (𝐴 ∩ (V × 𝐵)) or as the converse of the restricted converse (see cnvrescnv 6216). (Contributed by NM, 2-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↾ 𝐵) = (𝐴 ∩ (𝐵 × V)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |