![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 366 of 489) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30950) |
![]() (30951-32473) |
![]() (32474-48899) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | knoppf 36501* | Knopp's function is a function. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 25-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥))) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶↑𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦))))) & ⊢ 𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹‘𝑤)‘𝑖)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊:ℝ⟶ℝ) | ||
Theorem | knoppcn2 36502* | Variant of knoppcn 36470 with different codomain. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 25-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥))) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ ((𝐶↑𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 𝑁)↑𝑛) · 𝑦))))) & ⊢ 𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹‘𝑤)‘𝑖)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ (-1(,)1)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑊 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ)) | ||
Theorem | cnndvlem1 36503* | Lemma for cnndv 36505. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 25-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥))) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ (((1 / 2)↑𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 3)↑𝑛) · 𝑦))))) & ⊢ 𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹‘𝑤)‘𝑖)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑊 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ) ∧ dom (ℝ D 𝑊) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | cnndvlem2 36504* | Lemma for cnndv 36505. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 26-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = (𝑥 ∈ ℝ ↦ (abs‘((⌊‘(𝑥 + (1 / 2))) − 𝑥))) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ ℝ ↦ (𝑛 ∈ ℕ0 ↦ (((1 / 2)↑𝑛) · (𝑇‘(((2 · 3)↑𝑛) · 𝑦))))) & ⊢ 𝑊 = (𝑤 ∈ ℝ ↦ Σ𝑖 ∈ ℕ0 ((𝐹‘𝑤)‘𝑖)) ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑓(𝑓 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ) ∧ dom (ℝ D 𝑓) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | cnndv 36505 | There exists a continuous nowhere differentiable function. The result follows directly from knoppcn 36470 and knoppndv 36500. (Contributed by Asger C. Ipsen, 26-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ ∃𝑓(𝑓 ∈ (ℝ–cn→ℝ) ∧ dom (ℝ D 𝑓) = ∅) | ||
In this mathbox, we try to respect the ordering of the sections of the main part. There are strengthenings of theorems of the main part, as well as work on reducing axiom dependencies. | ||
Miscellaneous utility theorems of propositional calculus. | ||
In this section, we prove a few rules of inference derived from modus ponens ax-mp 5, and which do not depend on any other axioms. | ||
Theorem | bj-mp2c 36506 | A double modus ponens inference. Inference associated with mpd 15. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜒 | ||
Theorem | bj-mp2d 36507 | A double modus ponens inference. Inference associated with mpcom 38. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜒 | ||
In this section, we prove a syntactic theorem (bj-0 36508) asserting that some formula is well-formed. Then, we use this syntactic theorem to shorten the proof of a "usual" theorem (bj-1 36509) and explain in the comment of that theorem why this phenomenon is unusual. | ||
Theorem | bj-0 36508 | A syntactic theorem. See the section comment and the comment of bj-1 36509. The full proof (that is, with the syntactic, non-essential steps) does not appear on this webpage. It has five steps and reads $= wph wps wi wch wi $. The only other syntactic theorems in the main part of set.mm are wel 2109 and weq 1962. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
wff ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | bj-1 36509 |
In this proof, the use of the syntactic theorem bj-0 36508
allows to reduce
the total length by one (non-essential) step. See also the section
comment and the comment of bj-0 36508. Since bj-0 36508
is used in a
non-essential step, this use does not appear on this webpage (but the
present theorem appears on the webpage for bj-0 36508
as a theorem referencing
it). The full proof reads $= wph wps wch bj-0 id $. (while, without
using bj-0 36508, it would read $= wph wps wi wch wi id $.).
Now we explain why syntactic theorems are not useful in set.mm. Suppose that the syntactic theorem thm-0 proves that PHI is a well-formed formula, and that thm-0 is used to shorten the proof of thm-1. Assume that PHI does have proper non-atomic subformulas (which is not the case of the formula proved by weq 1962 or wel 2109). Then, the proof of thm-1 does not construct all the proper non-atomic subformulas of PHI (if it did, then using thm-0 would not shorten it). Therefore, thm-1 is a special instance of a more general theorem with essentially the same proof. In the present case, bj-1 36509 is a special instance of id 22. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-a1k 36510 | Weakening of ax-1 6. As a consequence, its associated inference is an instance (where we allow extra hypotheses) of ax-1 6. Its commuted form is 2a1 28 (but bj-a1k 36510 does not require ax-2 7). This shortens the proofs of dfwe2 7809 (937>925), ordunisuc2 7881 (789>777), r111 9844 (558>545), smo11 8420 (1176>1164). (Contributed by BJ, 11-Aug-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-poni 36511 | Inference associated with "pon", pm2.27 42. Its associated inference is ax-mp 5. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-nnclav 36512 | When ⊥ is substituted for 𝜓, this formula is the Clavius law with a doubly negated consequent, which is therefore a minimalistic tautology. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from peirce 202 and pm2.27 42 chained using syl 17. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜑) → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-nnclavi 36513 | Inference associated with bj-nnclav 36512. Its associated inference is an instance of syl 17. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from bj-peircei 36531 and bj-poni 36511. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-nnclavc 36514 | Commuted form of bj-nnclav 36512. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from bj-peircei 36531 and imim1i 63. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.) A proof which is shorter when compressed uses embantd 59. (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜑) → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-nnclavci 36515 | Inference associated with bj-nnclavc 36514. Its associated inference is an instance of syl 17. Notice the non-intuitionistic proof from peirce 202 and syl 17. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜑) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-jarrii 36516 | Inference associated with jarri 107. Contrary to it, it does not require ax-2 7, but only ax-mp 5 and ax-1 6. (Contributed by BJ, 29-Mar-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜒 | ||
Theorem | bj-imim21 36517 | The propositional function (𝜒 → (. → 𝜃)) is decreasing. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | bj-imim21i 36518 | Inference associated with bj-imim21 36517. Its associated inference is syl5 34. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Jul-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜒 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) → (𝜒 → (𝜑 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | bj-peircestab 36519 | Over minimal implicational calculus, Peirce's law implies the double negation of the stability of any formula (that is the interpretation when ⊥ is substituted for 𝜓 and for 𝜒). Therefore, the double negation of the stability of any formula is provable in classical refutability calculus. It is also provable in intuitionistic calculus (see iset.mm/bj-nnst) but it is not provable in minimal calculus (see bj-stabpeirce 36520). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Nov-2023.) Axiom ax-3 8 is only used through Peirce's law peirce 202. (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → 𝜑) → 𝜒) → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | bj-stabpeirce 36520 | This minimal implicational calculus tautology is used in the following argument: When 𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒, 𝜃, 𝜏 are replaced respectively by (𝜑 → ⊥), ⊥, 𝜑, ⊥, ⊥, the antecedent becomes ¬ ¬ (¬ ¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑), that is, the double negation of the stability of 𝜑. If that statement were provable in minimal calculus, then, since ⊥ plays no particular role in minimal calculus, also the statement with 𝜓 in place of ⊥ would be provable. The corresponding consequent is (((𝜓 → 𝜑) → 𝜓) → 𝜓), that is, the non-intuitionistic Peirce law. Therefore, the double negation of the stability of any formula is not provable in minimal calculus. However, it is provable both in intuitionistic calculus (see iset.mm/bj-nnst) and in classical refutability calculus (see bj-peircestab 36519). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Nov-2023.) (Revised by BJ, 30-Jul-2024.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜒) → 𝜃) → 𝜏) → (((𝜓 → 𝜒) → 𝜃) → 𝜏)) | ||
Positive calculus is understood to be intuitionistic. | ||
Theorem | bj-syl66ib 36521 | A mixed syllogism inference derived from imbitrdi 251. In addition to bj-dvelimdv1 36818, it can also shorten alexsubALTlem4 24079 (4821>4812), supsrlem 11180 (2868>2863). (Contributed by BJ, 20-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜃 → 𝜏) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-orim2 36522 | Proof of orim2 968 from the axiomatic definition of disjunction (olc 867, orc 866, jao 961) and minimal implicational calculus. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Apr-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → ((𝜒 ∨ 𝜑) → (𝜒 ∨ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-currypeirce 36523 | Curry's axiom curryax 892 (a non-intuitionistic positive statement sometimes called a paradox of material implication) implies Peirce's axiom peirce 202 over minimal implicational calculus and the axiomatic definition of disjunction (actually, only the elimination axiom jao 961 via its inference form jaoi 856; the introduction axioms olc 867 and orc 866 are not needed). Note that this theorem shows that actually, the standard instance of curryax 892 implies the standard instance of peirce 202, which is not the case for the converse bj-peircecurry 36524. (Contributed by BJ, 15-Jun-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∨ (𝜑 → 𝜓)) → (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜑) → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | bj-peircecurry 36524 | Peirce's axiom peirce 202 implies Curry's axiom curryax 892 over minimal implicational calculus and the axiomatic definition of disjunction (actually, only the introduction axioms olc 867 and orc 866; the elimination axiom jao 961 is not needed). See bj-currypeirce 36523 for the converse. (Contributed by BJ, 15-Jun-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ∨ (𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-animbi 36525 | Conjunction in terms of implication and biconditional. Note that the proof is intuitionistic (use of ax-3 8 comes from the unusual definition of the biconditional in set.mm). (Contributed by BJ, 23-Sep-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-currypara 36526 | Curry's paradox. Note that the proof is intuitionistic (use of ax-3 8 comes from the unusual definition of the biconditional in set.mm). The paradox comes from the case where 𝜑 is the self-referential sentence "If this sentence is true, then 𝜓", so that one can prove everything. Therefore, a consistent system cannot allow the formation of such self-referential sentences. This has lead to the study of logics rejecting contraction pm2.43 56, such as affine logic and linear logic. (Contributed by BJ, 23-Sep-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ (𝜑 → 𝜓)) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-con2com 36527 | A commuted form of the contrapositive, true in minimal calculus. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑) → ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-con2comi 36528 | Inference associated with bj-con2com 36527. Its associated inference is mt2 200. TODO: when in the main part, add to mt2 200 that it is the inference associated with bj-con2comi 36528. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑) → ¬ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-nimn 36529 | If a formula is true, then it does not imply its negation. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.) A shorter proof is possible using id 22 and jc 161, however, the present proof uses theorems that are more basic than jc 161. (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | bj-nimni 36530 | Inference associated with bj-nimn 36529. (Contributed by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | bj-peircei 36531 | Inference associated with peirce 202. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | bj-looinvi 36532 | Inference associated with looinv 203. Its associated inference is bj-looinvii 36533. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝜑) → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | bj-looinvii 36533 | Inference associated with bj-looinvi 36532. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | bj-mt2bi 36534 | Version of mt2 200 where the major premise is a biconditional. Another proof is also possible via con2bii 357 and mpbi 230. The current mt2bi 363 should be relabeled, maybe to imfal. (Contributed by BJ, 5-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ ¬ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | bj-ntrufal 36535 | The negation of a theorem is equivalent to false. This can shorten dfnul2 4355. (Contributed by BJ, 5-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ ⊥) | ||
Theorem | bj-fal 36536 | Shortening of fal 1551 using bj-mt2bi 36534. (Contributed by Anthony Hart, 22-Oct-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mel L. O'Cat, 11-Mar-2012.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ¬ ⊥ | ||
A few lemmas about disjunction. The fundamental theorems in this family are the dual statements pm4.71 557 and pm4.72 950. See also biort 934 and biorf 935. | ||
Theorem | bj-jaoi1 36537 | Shortens orfa2 38046 (58>53), pm1.2 902 (20>18), pm1.2 902 (20>18), pm2.4 905 (31>25), pm2.41 906 (31>25), pm2.42 943 (38>32), pm3.2ni 879 (43>39), pm4.44 997 (55>51). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-jaoi2 36538 | Shortens consensus 1053 (110>106), elnn0z 12652 (336>329), pm1.2 902 (20>19), pm3.2ni 879 (43>39), pm4.44 997 (55>51). (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 ∨ 𝜑) → 𝜓) | ||
A few other characterizations of the biconditional. The inter-definability of logical connectives offers many ways to express a given statement. Some useful theorems in this regard are df-or 847, df-an 396, pm4.64 848, imor 852, pm4.62 855 through pm4.67 398, and, for the De Morgan laws, ianor 982 through pm4.57 991. | ||
Theorem | bj-dfbi4 36539 | Alternate definition of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Oct-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ∨ ¬ (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-dfbi5 36540 | Alternate definition of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Oct-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) → (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-dfbi6 36541 | Alternate definition of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 4-Oct-2019.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-bijust0ALT 36542 | Alternate proof of bijust0 204; shorter but using additional intermediate results. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1999.) (Proof shortened by Josh Purinton, 29-Dec-2000.) (Revised by BJ, 19-Mar-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ¬ ((𝜑 → 𝜑) → ¬ (𝜑 → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | bj-bijust00 36543 | A self-implication does not imply the negation of a self-implication. Most general theorem of which bijust 205 is an instance (bijust0 204 and bj-bijust0ALT 36542 are therefore also instances of it). (Contributed by BJ, 7-Sep-2022.) |
⊢ ¬ ((𝜑 → 𝜑) → ¬ (𝜓 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-consensus 36544 | Version of consensus 1053 expressed using the conditional operator. (Remark: it may be better to express it as consensus 1053, using only binary connectives, and hinting at the fact that it is a Boolean algebra identity, like the absorption identities.) (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ ((if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) ↔ if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-consensusALT 36545 | Alternate proof of bj-consensus 36544. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) ↔ if-(𝜑, 𝜓, 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-df-ifc 36546* | Candidate definition for the conditional operator for classes. This is in line with the definition of a class as the extension of a predicate in df-clab 2718. We reprove the current df-if 4549 from it in bj-dfif 36547. (Contributed by BJ, 20-Sep-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ if(𝜑, 𝐴, 𝐵) = {𝑥 ∣ if-(𝜑, 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵)} | ||
Theorem | bj-dfif 36547* | Alternate definition of the conditional operator for classes, which used to be the main definition. (Contributed by BJ, 26-Dec-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ if(𝜑, 𝐴, 𝐵) = {𝑥 ∣ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) ∨ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵))} | ||
Theorem | bj-ififc 36548 | A biconditional connecting the conditional operator for propositions and the conditional operator for classes. Note that there is no sethood hypothesis on 𝑋: it is implied by either side. (Contributed by BJ, 24-Sep-2019.) Generalize statement from setvar 𝑥 to class 𝑋. (Revised by BJ, 26-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ if(𝜑, 𝐴, 𝐵) ↔ if-(𝜑, 𝑋 ∈ 𝐴, 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Miscellaneous theorems of propositional calculus. | ||
Theorem | bj-imbi12 36549 | Uncurried (imported) form of imbi12 346. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) → ((𝜑 → 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | bj-falor 36550 | Dual of truan 1548 (which has biconditional reversed). (Contributed by BJ, 26-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (⊥ ∨ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | bj-falor2 36551 | Dual of truan 1548. (Contributed by BJ, 26-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((⊥ ∨ 𝜑) ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | bj-bibibi 36552 | A property of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 26-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-imn3ani 36553 | Duplication of bnj1224 34777. Three-fold version of imnani 400. (Contributed by Jonathan Ben-Naim, 3-Jun-2011.) (Revised by BJ, 22-Oct-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → ¬ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | bj-andnotim 36554 | Two ways of expressing a certain ternary connective. Note the respective positions of the three formulas on each side of the biconditional. (Contributed by BJ, 6-Oct-2018.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ ¬ 𝜓) → 𝜒) ↔ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ∨ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-bi3ant 36555 | This used to be in the main part. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 14-May-2013.) (Revised by BJ, 14-Jun-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜃 → 𝜏) → 𝜑) → (((𝜏 → 𝜃) → 𝜓) → ((𝜃 ↔ 𝜏) → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | bj-bisym 36556 | This used to be in the main part. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 14-May-2013.) (Revised by BJ, 14-Jun-2019.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) → (((𝜓 → 𝜑) → (𝜃 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | bj-bixor 36557 | Equivalence of two ternary operations. Note the identical order and parenthesizing of the three arguments in both expressions. (Contributed by BJ, 31-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ⊻ 𝜒)) ↔ (𝜑 ⊻ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
In this section, we prove some theorems related to modal logic. For modal logic, we refer to https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Kripke_semantics, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Modal_logic and https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-modal/. Monadic first-order logic (i.e., with quantification over only one variable) is bi-interpretable with modal logic, by mapping ∀𝑥 to "necessity" (generally denoted by a box) and ∃𝑥 to "possibility" (generally denoted by a diamond). Therefore, we use these quantifiers so as not to introduce new symbols. (To be strictly within modal logic, we should add disjoint variable conditions between 𝑥 and any other metavariables appearing in the statements.) For instance, ax-gen 1793 corresponds to the necessitation rule of modal logic, and ax-4 1807 corresponds to the distributivity axiom (K) of modal logic, also called the Kripke scheme. Modal logics satisfying these rule and axiom are called "normal modal logics", of which the most important modal logics are. The minimal normal modal logic is also denoted by (K). Here are a few normal modal logics with their axiomatizations (on top of (K)): (K) axiomatized by no supplementary axioms; (T) axiomatized by the axiom T; (K4) axiomatized by the axiom 4; (S4) axiomatized by the axioms T,4; (S5) axiomatized by the axioms T,5 or D,B,4; (GL) axiomatized by the axiom GL. The last one, called Gödel–Löb logic or provability logic, is important because it describes exactly the properties of provability in Peano arithmetic, as proved by Robert Solovay. See for instance https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-provability/ 1807. A basic result in this logic is bj-gl4 36561. | ||
Theorem | bj-axdd2 36558 | This implication, proved using only ax-gen 1793 and ax-4 1807 on top of propositional calculus (hence holding, up to the standard interpretation, in any normal modal logic), shows that the axiom scheme ⊢ ∃𝑥⊤ implies the axiom scheme ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑). These correspond to the modal axiom (D), and in predicate calculus, they assert that the universe of discourse is nonempty. For the converse, see bj-axd2d 36559. (Contributed by BJ, 16-May-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-axd2d 36559 | This implication, proved using only ax-gen 1793 on top of propositional calculus (hence holding, up to the standard interpretation, in any modal logic), shows that the axiom scheme ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) implies the axiom scheme ⊢ ∃𝑥⊤. These correspond to the modal axiom (D), and in predicate calculus, they assert that the universe of discourse is nonempty. For the converse, see bj-axdd2 36558. (Contributed by BJ, 16-May-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥⊤ → ∃𝑥⊤) → ∃𝑥⊤) | ||
Theorem | bj-axtd 36560 | This implication, proved from propositional calculus only (hence holding, up to the standard interpretation, in any modal logic), shows that the axiom scheme ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) (modal T) implies the axiom scheme ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑) (modal D). See also bj-axdd2 36558 and bj-axd2d 36559. (Contributed by BJ, 16-May-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑) → ((∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∃𝑥𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | bj-gl4 36561 | In a normal modal logic, the modal axiom GL implies the modal axiom (4). Translated to first-order logic, Axiom GL reads ⊢ (∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) → ∀𝑥𝜑). Note that the antecedent of bj-gl4 36561 is an instance of the axiom GL, with 𝜑 replaced by (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜑), which is a modality sometimes called the "strong necessity" of 𝜑. (Contributed by BJ, 12-Dec-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥(∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜑) → (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜑)) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜑)) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑥𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | bj-axc4 36562 | Over minimal calculus, the modal axiom (4) (hba1 2297) and the modal axiom (K) (ax-4 1807) together imply axc4 2325. (Contributed by BJ, 29-Nov-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑥𝜑) → ((∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) → (∀𝑥(∀𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)))) | ||
In this section, we assume that, on top of propositional calculus, there is given a provability predicate Prv satisfying the three axioms ax-prv1 36564 and ax-prv2 36565 and ax-prv3 36566. Note the similarity with ax-gen 1793, ax-4 1807 and hba1 2297 respectively. These three properties of Prv are often called the Hilbert–Bernays–Löb derivability conditions, or the Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions. This corresponds to the modal logic (K4) (see previous section for modal logic). The interpretation of provability logic is the following: we are given a background first-order theory T, the wff Prv 𝜑 means "𝜑 is provable in T", and the turnstile ⊢ indicates provability in T. Beware that "provability logic" often means (K) augmented with the Gödel–Löb axiom GL, which we do not assume here (at least for the moment). See for instance https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-provability/ 2297. Provability logic is worth studying because whenever T is a first-order theory containing Robinson arithmetic (a fragment of Peano arithmetic), one can prove (using Gödel numbering, and in the much weaker primitive recursive arithmetic) that there exists in T a provability predicate Prv satisfying the above three axioms. (We do not construct this predicate in this section; this is still a project.) The main theorems of this section are the "easy parts" of the proofs of Gödel's second incompleteness theorem (bj-babygodel 36569) and Löb's theorem (bj-babylob 36570). See the comments of these theorems for details. | ||
Syntax | cprvb 36563 | Syntax for the provability predicate. |
wff Prv 𝜑 | ||
Axiom | ax-prv1 36564 | First property of three of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Prv 𝜑 | ||
Axiom | ax-prv2 36565 | Second property of three of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (Prv (𝜑 → 𝜓) → (Prv 𝜑 → Prv 𝜓)) | ||
Axiom | ax-prv3 36566 | Third property of three of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (Prv 𝜑 → Prv Prv 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | prvlem1 36567 | An elementary property of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (Prv 𝜑 → Prv 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | prvlem2 36568 | An elementary property of the provability predicate. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (Prv 𝜑 → (Prv 𝜓 → Prv 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-babygodel 36569 |
See the section header comments for the context.
The first hypothesis reads "𝜑 is true if and only if it is not provable in T" (and having this first hypothesis means that we can prove this fact in T). The wff 𝜑 is a formal version of the sentence "This sentence is not provable". The hard part of the proof of Gödel's theorem is to construct such a 𝜑, called a "Gödel–Rosser sentence", for a first-order theory T which is effectively axiomatizable and contains Robinson arithmetic, through Gödel diagonalization (this can be done in primitive recursive arithmetic). The second hypothesis means that ⊥ is not provable in T, that is, that the theory T is consistent (and having this second hypothesis means that we can prove in T that the theory T is consistent). The conclusion is the falsity, so having the conclusion means that T can prove the falsity, that is, T is inconsistent. Therefore, taking the contrapositive, this theorem expresses that if a first-order theory is consistent (and one can prove in it that some formula is true if and only if it is not provable in it), then this theory does not prove its own consistency. This proof is due to George Boolos, Gödel's Second Incompleteness Theorem Explained in Words of One Syllable, Mind, New Series, Vol. 103, No. 409 (January 1994), pp. 1--3. (Contributed by BJ, 3-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ Prv 𝜑) & ⊢ ¬ Prv ⊥ ⇒ ⊢ ⊥ | ||
Theorem | bj-babylob 36570 |
See the section header comments for the context, as well as the comments
for bj-babygodel 36569.
Löb's theorem when the Löb sentence is given as a hypothesis (the hard part of the proof of Löb's theorem is to construct this Löb sentence; this can be done, using Gödel diagonalization, for any first-order effectively axiomatizable theory containing Robinson arithmetic). More precisely, the present theorem states that if a first-order theory proves that the provability of a given sentence entails its truth (and if one can construct in this theory a provability predicate and a Löb sentence, given here as the first hypothesis), then the theory actually proves that sentence. See for instance, Eliezer Yudkowsky, The Cartoon Guide to Löb's Theorem (available at http://yudkowsky.net/rational/lobs-theorem/ 36569). (Contributed by BJ, 20-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (Prv 𝜓 → 𝜑)) & ⊢ (Prv 𝜑 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | bj-godellob 36571 | Proof of Gödel's theorem from Löb's theorem (see comments at bj-babygodel 36569 and bj-babylob 36570 for details). (Contributed by BJ, 20-Apr-2019.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ Prv 𝜑) & ⊢ ¬ Prv ⊥ ⇒ ⊢ ⊥ | ||
Utility lemmas or strengthenings of theorems in the main part (biconditional or closed forms, or fewer disjoint variable conditions, or disjoint variable conditions replaced with nonfreeness hypotheses...). Sorted in the same order as in the main part. | ||
Theorem | bj-genr 36572 | Generalization rule on the right conjunct. See 19.28 2229. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-genl 36573 | Generalization rule on the left conjunct. See 19.27 2228. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-genan 36574 | Generalization rule on a conjunction. Forward inference associated with 19.26 1869. (Contributed by BJ, 7-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-mpgs 36575 | From a closed form theorem (the major premise) with an antecedent in the "strong necessity" modality (in the language of modal logic), deduce the inference ⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓. Strong necessity is stronger than necessity, and equivalent to it when sp 2184 (modal T) is available. Therefore, this theorem is stronger than mpg 1795 when sp 2184 is not available. (Contributed by BJ, 1-Nov-2023.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜑) → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | bj-2alim 36576 | Closed form of 2alimi 1810. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 → ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-2exim 36577 | Closed form of 2eximi 1834. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜑 → ∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-alanim 36578 | Closed form of alanimi 1814. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝜒) → ((∀𝑥𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥𝜓) → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-2albi 36579 | Closed form of 2albii 1818. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥∀𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-notalbii 36580 | Equivalence of universal quantification of negation of equivalent formulas. Shortens ab0 4402 (103>94), ballotlem2 34453 (2655>2648), bnj1143 34766 (522>519), hausdiag 23674 (2119>2104). (Contributed by BJ, 17-Jul-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-2exbi 36581 | Closed form of 2exbii 1847. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑥∃𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-3exbi 36582 | Closed form of 3exbii 1848. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → (∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑥∃𝑦∃𝑧𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-sylggt 36583 | Stronger form of sylgt 1820, closer to ax-2 7. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Jul-2025.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒)) → ((𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | bj-sylgt2 36584 | Uncurried (imported) form of sylgt 1820. (Contributed by BJ, 2-May-2019.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒) ∧ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-alrimg 36585 | The general form of the *alrim* family of theorems: if 𝜑 is substituted for 𝜓, then the antecedent expresses a form of nonfreeness of 𝑥 in 𝜑, so the theorem means that under a nonfreeness condition in an antecedent, one can deduce from the universally quantified implication an implication where the consequent is universally quantified. Dual of bj-exlimg 36589. (Contributed by BJ, 9-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒) → (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | bj-alrimd 36586 | A slightly more general alrimd 2216. A common usage will have 𝜑 substituted for 𝜓 and 𝜒 substituted for 𝜃, giving a form closer to alrimd 2216. (Contributed by BJ, 25-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜃 → 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | bj-sylget 36587 | Dual statement of sylgt 1820. Closed form of bj-sylge 36590. (Contributed by BJ, 2-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜒 → 𝜑) → ((∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∃𝑥𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-sylget2 36588 | Uncurried (imported) form of bj-sylget 36587. (Contributed by BJ, 2-May-2019.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓) ∧ (∃𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-exlimg 36589 | The general form of the *exlim* family of theorems: if 𝜑 is substituted for 𝜓, then the antecedent expresses a form of nonfreeness of 𝑥 in 𝜑, so the theorem means that under a nonfreeness condition in a consequent, one can deduce from the universally quantified implication an implication where the antecedent is existentially quantified. Dual of bj-alrimg 36585. (Contributed by BJ, 9-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ ((∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∀𝑥(𝜒 → 𝜑) → (∃𝑥𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-sylge 36590 | Dual statement of sylg 1821 (the final "e" in the label stands for "existential (version of sylg 1821)". Variant of exlimih 2293. (Contributed by BJ, 25-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥𝜒 → 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | bj-exlimd 36591 | A slightly more general exlimd 2219. A common usage will have 𝜑 substituted for 𝜓 and 𝜃 substituted for 𝜏, giving a form closer to exlimd 2219. (Contributed by BJ, 25-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜃 → 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜒 → 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | bj-nfimexal 36592 | A weak from of nonfreeness in either an antecedent or a consequent implies that a universally quantified implication is equivalent to the associated implication where the antecedent is existentially quantified and the consequent is universally quantified. The forward implication always holds (this is 19.38 1837) and the converse implication is the join of instances of bj-alrimg 36585 and bj-exlimg 36589 (see 19.38a 1838 and 19.38b 1839). TODO: prove a version where the antecedents use the nonfreeness quantifier. (Contributed by BJ, 9-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (((∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ∨ (∃𝑥𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓)) → ((∃𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ↔ ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-alexim 36593 | Closed form of aleximi 1830. Note: this proof is shorter, so aleximi 1830 could be deduced from it (exim 1832 would have to be proved first, see bj-eximALT 36607 but its proof is shorter (currently almost a subproof of aleximi 1830)). (Contributed by BJ, 8-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → (∃𝑥𝜓 → ∃𝑥𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | bj-nexdh 36594 | Closed form of nexdh 1864 (actually, its general instance). (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜑) → (𝜒 → ¬ ∃𝑥𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-nexdh2 36595 | Uncurried (imported) form of bj-nexdh 36594. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥(𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ∧ (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜑)) → (𝜒 → ¬ ∃𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bj-hbxfrbi 36596 | Closed form of hbxfrbi 1823. Note: it is less important than nfbiit 1849. The antecedent is in the "strong necessity" modality of modal logic (see also bj-nnftht 36707) in order not to require sp 2184 (modal T). See bj-hbyfrbi 36597 for its version with existential quantifiers. (Contributed by BJ, 6-May-2019.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) → ((𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜑) ↔ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-hbyfrbi 36597 | Version of bj-hbxfrbi 36596 with existential quantifiers. (Contributed by BJ, 23-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) → ((∃𝑥𝜑 → 𝜑) ↔ (∃𝑥𝜓 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bj-exalim 36598 |
Distribute quantifiers over a nested implication.
This and the following theorems are the general instances of already proved theorems. They could be moved to the main part, before ax-5 1909. I propose to move to the main part: bj-exalim 36598, bj-exalimi 36599, bj-exalims 36600, bj-exalimsi 36601, bj-ax12i 36603, bj-ax12wlem 36610, bj-ax12w 36643. A new label is needed for bj-ax12i 36603 and label suggestions are welcome for the others. I also propose to change ¬ ∀𝑥¬ to ∃𝑥 in speimfw 1963 and spimfw 1965 (other spim* theorems use ∃𝑥 and very few theorems in set.mm use ¬ ∀𝑥¬). (Contributed by BJ, 8-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (∃𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∃𝑥𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | bj-exalimi 36599 | An inference for distributing quantifiers over a nested implication. The canonical derivation from its closed form bj-exalim 36598 (using mpg 1795) has fewer essential steps, but more steps in total (yielding a longer compressed proof). (Almost) the general statement that speimfw 1963 proves. (Contributed by BJ, 29-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → ∃𝑥𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bj-exalims 36600 | Distributing quantifiers over a nested implication. (Almost) the general statement that spimfw 1965 proves. (Contributed by BJ, 29-Sep-2019.) |
⊢ (∃𝑥𝜑 → (¬ 𝜒 → ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) → (∃𝑥𝜑 → (∀𝑥𝜓 → 𝜒))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |