Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 4 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29181) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29182-30704) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30705-46395) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | 3bitr3ri 301 | A chained inference from transitive law for logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr4i 302 | A chained inference from transitive law for logical equivalence. This inference is frequently used to apply a definition to both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr4ri 303 | A chained inference from transitive law for logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 2-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | 3bitrd 304 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 13-Aug-1999.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitrrd 305 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 4-Aug-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr2d 306 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 4-Aug-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr2rd 307 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 4-Aug-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr3d 308 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. Useful for converting conditional definitions in a formula. (Contributed by NM, 24-Apr-1996.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr3rd 309 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 4-Aug-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr4d 310 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. Useful for converting conditional definitions in a formula. (Contributed by NM, 18-Oct-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr4rd 311 | Deduction from transitivity of biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 4-Aug-2006.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr3g 312 | More general version of 3bitr3i 300. Useful for converting definitions in a formula. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jun-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜏) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | 3bitr4g 313 | More general version of 3bitr4i 302. Useful for converting definitions in a formula. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜏 ↔ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | notnotb 314 | Double negation. Theorem *4.13 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 117. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | con34b 315 | A biconditional form of contraposition. Theorem *4.1 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 116. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (¬ 𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | con4bid 316 | A contraposition deduction. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | notbid 317 | Deduction negating both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | notbi 318 | Contraposition. Theorem *4.11 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 117. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | notbii 319 | Negate both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | con4bii 320 | A contraposition inference. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-1994.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | mtbi 321 | An inference from a biconditional, related to modus tollens. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 25-Oct-2012.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ¬ 𝜓 | ||
Theorem | mtbir 322 | An inference from a biconditional, related to modus tollens. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 14-Oct-2012.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ¬ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | mtbid 323 | A deduction from a biconditional, similar to modus tollens. (Contributed by NM, 26-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | mtbird 324 | A deduction from a biconditional, similar to modus tollens. (Contributed by NM, 10-May-1994.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | mtbii 325 | An inference from a biconditional, similar to modus tollens. (Contributed by NM, 27-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜓 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | mtbiri 326 | An inference from a biconditional, similar to modus tollens. (Contributed by NM, 24-Aug-1995.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜒 & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | sylnib 327 | A mixed syllogism inference from an implication and a biconditional. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | sylnibr 328 | A mixed syllogism inference from an implication and a biconditional. Useful for substituting a consequent with a definition. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | sylnbi 329 | A mixed syllogism inference from a biconditional and an implication. Useful for substituting an antecedent with a definition. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | sylnbir 330 | A mixed syllogism inference from a biconditional and an implication. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 16-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜑) & ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | xchnxbi 331 | Replacement of a subexpression by an equivalent one. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 27-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | xchnxbir 332 | Replacement of a subexpression by an equivalent one. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 27-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | xchbinx 333 | Replacement of a subexpression by an equivalent one. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 27-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | xchbinxr 334 | Replacement of a subexpression by an equivalent one. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 27-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | imbi2i 335 | Introduce an antecedent to both sides of a logical equivalence. This and the next three rules are useful for building up wff's around a definition, in order to make use of the definition. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜒 → 𝜑) ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | jcndOLD 336 | Obsolete version of jcnd 163 as of 10-Apr-2024. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 11-Dec-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bibi2i 337 | Inference adding a biconditional to the left in an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 7-May-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 16-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜒 ↔ 𝜑) ↔ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | bibi1i 338 | Inference adding a biconditional to the right in an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | bibi12i 339 | The equivalence of two equivalences. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | imbi2d 340 | Deduction adding an antecedent to both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜃 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜃 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | imbi1d 341 | Deduction adding a consequent to both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 17-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜃) ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | bibi2d 342 | Deduction adding a biconditional to the left in an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜃 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜃 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | bibi1d 343 | Deduction adding a biconditional to the right in an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ↔ 𝜃) ↔ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | imbi12d 344 | Deduction joining two equivalences to form equivalence of implications. (Contributed by NM, 16-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 → 𝜃) ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | bibi12d 345 | Deduction joining two equivalences to form equivalence of biconditionals. (Contributed by NM, 26-May-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜓 ↔ 𝜃) ↔ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜏))) | ||
Theorem | imbi12 346 | Closed form of imbi12i 350. Was automatically derived from its "Virtual Deduction" version and the Metamath program "MM-PA> MINIMIZE_WITH *" command. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 18-Mar-2012.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ((𝜒 ↔ 𝜃) → ((𝜑 → 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 → 𝜃)))) | ||
Theorem | imbi1 347 | Theorem *4.84 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 122. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ((𝜑 → 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | imbi2 348 | Theorem *4.85 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 122. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-May-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ((𝜒 → 𝜑) ↔ (𝜒 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | imbi1i 349 | Introduce a consequent to both sides of a logical equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 17-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | imbi12i 350 | Join two logical equivalences to form equivalence of implications. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | bibi1 351 | Theorem *4.86 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 122. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) ↔ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | bitr3 352 | Closed nested implication form of bitr3i 276. Derived automatically from bitr3VD 42358. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 31-Dec-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | con2bi 353 | Contraposition. Theorem *4.12 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 117. (Contributed by NM, 15-Apr-1995.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 3-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | con2bid 354 | A contraposition deduction. (Contributed by NM, 15-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | con1bid 355 | A contraposition deduction. (Contributed by NM, 9-Oct-1999.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (¬ 𝜒 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | con1bii 356 | A contraposition inference. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 13-Oct-2012.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | con2bii 357 | A contraposition inference. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | con1b 358 | Contraposition. Bidirectional version of con1 146. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | con2b 359 | Contraposition. Bidirectional version of con2 135. (Contributed by NM, 12-Mar-1993.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | biimt 360 | A wff is equivalent to itself with true antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 28-Jan-1996.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ (𝜑 → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | pm5.5 361 | Theorem *5.5 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 125. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | a1bi 362 | Inference introducing a theorem as an antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Nov-2012.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | mt2bi 363 | A false consequent falsifies an antecedent. (Contributed by NM, 19-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-Nov-2012.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 ↔ (𝜓 → ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | mtt 364 | Modus-tollens-like theorem. (Contributed by NM, 7-Apr-2001.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-Nov-2012.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 ↔ (𝜓 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | imnot 365 | If a proposition is false, then implying it is equivalent to being false. One of four theorems that can be used to simplify an implication (𝜑 → 𝜓), the other ones being ax-1 6 (true consequent), pm2.21 123 (false antecedent), pm5.5 361 (true antecedent). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2019.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 26-May-2019.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | pm5.501 366 | Theorem *5.501 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 125. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | ibib 367 | Implication in terms of implication and biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 31-Mar-1994.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 24-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | ibibr 368 | Implication in terms of implication and biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 29-Apr-2005.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | tbt 369 | A wff is equivalent to its equivalence with a truth. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 13-May-2011.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | nbn2 370 | The negation of a wff is equivalent to the wff's equivalence to falsehood. (Contributed by Juha Arpiainen, 19-Jan-2006.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 ↔ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | bibif 371 | Transfer negation via an equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 3-Oct-2007.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 28-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | nbn 372 | The negation of a wff is equivalent to the wff's equivalence to falsehood. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1993.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 3-Oct-2013.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 ↔ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | nbn3 373 | Transfer falsehood via equivalence. (Contributed by NM, 11-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 ↔ (𝜓 ↔ ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | pm5.21im 374 | Two propositions are equivalent if they are both false. Closed form of 2false 375. Equivalent to a biimpr 219-like version of the xor-connective. (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2013.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | 2false 375 | Two falsehoods are equivalent. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2005.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-May-2013.) |
⊢ ¬ 𝜑 & ⊢ ¬ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | 2falsed 376 | Two falsehoods are equivalent (deduction form). (Contributed by NM, 11-Oct-2013.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 11-Apr-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | 2falsedOLD 377 | Obsolete version of 2falsed 376 as of 11-Apr-2024. (Contributed by NM, 11-Oct-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | pm5.21ni 378 | Two propositions implying a false one are equivalent. (Contributed by NM, 16-Feb-1996.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 19-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | pm5.21nii 379 | Eliminate an antecedent implied by each side of a biconditional. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-1999.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜓 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | pm5.21ndd 380 | Eliminate an antecedent implied by each side of a biconditional, deduction version. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 21-Nov-2012.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 6-Oct-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 → 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜃 → 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | bija 381 | Combine antecedents into a single biconditional. This inference, reminiscent of ja 186, is reversible: The hypotheses can be deduced from the conclusion alone (see pm5.1im 262 and pm5.21im 374). (Contributed by Wolf Lammen, 13-May-2013.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) & ⊢ (¬ 𝜑 → (¬ 𝜓 → 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) → 𝜒) | ||
Theorem | pm5.18 382 | Theorem *5.18 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. This theorem says that logical equivalence is the same as negated "exclusive or". (Contributed by NM, 28-Jun-2002.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 20-Jun-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 15-Oct-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | xor3 383 | Two ways to express "exclusive or". (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2006.) |
⊢ (¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nbbn 384 | Move negation outside of biconditional. Compare Theorem *5.18 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by NM, 27-Jun-2002.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 20-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | biass 385 | Associative law for the biconditional. An axiom of system DS in Vladimir Lifschitz, "On calculational proofs", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 113:207-224, 2002, http://www.cs.utexas.edu/users/ai-lab/pub-view.php?PubID=26805. Interestingly, this law was not included in Principia Mathematica but was apparently first noted by Jan Lukasiewicz circa 1923. (Contributed by NM, 8-Jan-2005.) (Proof shortened by Juha Arpiainen, 19-Jan-2006.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 21-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ 𝜒) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | biluk 386 | Lukasiewicz's shortest axiom for equivalential calculus. Storrs McCall, ed., Polish Logic 1920-1939 (Oxford, 1967), p. 96. (Contributed by NM, 10-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ ((𝜒 ↔ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | pm5.19 387 | Theorem *5.19 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 124. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ ¬ (𝜑 ↔ ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | bi2.04 388 | Logical equivalence of commuted antecedents. Part of Theorem *4.87 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 122. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1993.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ↔ (𝜓 → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | pm5.4 389 | Antecedent absorption implication. Theorem *5.4 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 125. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ↔ (𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | imdi 390 | Distributive law for implication. Compare Theorem *5.41 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 125. (Contributed by NM, 5-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒)) ↔ ((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | pm5.41 391 | Theorem *5.41 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 125. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 12-Oct-2012.) |
⊢ (((𝜑 → 𝜓) → (𝜑 → 𝜒)) ↔ (𝜑 → (𝜓 → 𝜒))) | ||
Theorem | pm4.8 392 | Theorem *4.8 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 122. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ¬ 𝜑) ↔ ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | pm4.81 393 | A formula is equivalent to its negation implying it. Theorem *4.81 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 122. Note that the second step, using pm2.24 124, could also use ax-1 6. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ ((¬ 𝜑 → 𝜑) ↔ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | imim21b 394 | Simplify an implication between two implications when the antecedent of the first is a consequence of the antecedent of the second. The reverse form is useful in producing the successor step in induction proofs. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 22-Jun-2011.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 14-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝜑) → (((𝜑 → 𝜒) → (𝜓 → 𝜃)) ↔ (𝜓 → (𝜒 → 𝜃)))) | ||
This section defines conjunction of two formulas, denoted by infix "∧ " and read "and". It is defined in terms of implication and negation, which is possible in classical logic (but not in intuitionistic logic: see iset.mm). After the definition, we briefly introduce conversion of simple expressions to and from conjunction. Two simple operations called importation (imp 406) and exportation (ex 412) follow. In the propositions-as-types interpretation, they correspond to uncurrying and currying respectively. They are foundational for this section. Most of the theorems proved here trace back to them, mostly indirectly, in a layered fashion, where more complex expressions are built from simpler ones. Here are some of these successive layers: importation and exportation, commutativity and associativity laws, adding antecedents and simplifying, conjunction of consequents, syllogisms, etc. As indicated in the "note on definitions" in the section comment for logical equivalence, some theorems containing only implication, negation and conjunction are placed in the section after disjunction since theirs proofs use disjunction (although this is not required since definitions are conservative, see said section comment). | ||
Syntax | wa 395 | Extend wff definition to include conjunction ("and"). |
wff (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) | ||
Definition | df-an 396 |
Define conjunction (logical "and"). Definition of [Margaris] p. 49. When
both the left and right operand are true, the result is true; when either
is false, the result is false. For example, it is true that
(2 = 2 ∧ 3 = 3). After we define the constant
true ⊤
(df-tru 1542) and the constant false ⊥ (df-fal 1552), we will be able
to prove these truth table values: ((⊤ ∧
⊤) ↔ ⊤)
(truantru 1572), ((⊤ ∧ ⊥)
↔ ⊥) (truanfal 1573),
((⊥ ∧ ⊤) ↔ ⊥) (falantru 1574), and
((⊥ ∧ ⊥) ↔ ⊥) (falanfal 1575).
This is our first use of the biconditional connective in a definition; we use the biconditional connective in place of the traditional "<=def=>", which means the same thing, except that we can manipulate the biconditional connective directly in proofs rather than having to rely on an informal definition substitution rule. Note that if we mechanically substitute ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) for (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓), we end up with an instance of previously proved theorem biid 260. This is the justification for the definition, along with the fact that it introduces a new symbol ∧. Contrast with ∨ (df-or 844), → (wi 4), ⊼ (df-nan 1484), and ⊻ (df-xor 1504). (Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-1993.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | pm4.63 397 | Theorem *4.63 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 120. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ (¬ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ↔ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | pm4.67 398 | Theorem *4.67 of [WhiteheadRussell] p. 120. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2005.) |
⊢ (¬ (¬ 𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ↔ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | imnan 399 | Express an implication in terms of a negated conjunction. (Contributed by NM, 9-Apr-1994.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) ↔ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | imnani 400 | Infer an implication from a negated conjunction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 28-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝜓) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |