Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 289 of 466) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29289) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29290-30812) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30813-46532) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | ex-pss 28801 | Example for df-pss 3907. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ {1, 2} ⊊ {1, 2, 3} | ||
Theorem | ex-pw 28802 | Example for df-pw 4536. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jul-2016.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = {3, 5, 7} → 𝒫 𝐴 = (({∅} ∪ {{3}, {5}, {7}}) ∪ ({{3, 5}, {3, 7}, {5, 7}} ∪ {{3, 5, 7}}))) | ||
Theorem | ex-pr 28803 | Example for df-pr 4565. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {1, -1} → (𝐴↑2) = 1) | ||
Theorem | ex-br 28804 | Example for df-br 5076. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} → 3𝑅9) | ||
Theorem | ex-opab 28805* | Example for df-opab 5138. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ℂ ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℂ ∧ (𝑥 + 1) = 𝑦)} → 3𝑅4) | ||
Theorem | ex-eprel 28806 | Example for df-eprel 5496. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 5 E {1, 5} | ||
Theorem | ex-id 28807 | Example for df-id 5490. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (5 I 5 ∧ ¬ 4 I 5) | ||
Theorem | ex-po 28808 | Example for df-po 5504. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ( < Po ℝ ∧ ¬ ≤ Po ℝ) | ||
Theorem | ex-xp 28809 | Example for df-xp 5596. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ ({1, 5} × {2, 7}) = ({〈1, 2〉, 〈1, 7〉} ∪ {〈5, 2〉, 〈5, 7〉}) | ||
Theorem | ex-cnv 28810 | Example for df-cnv 5598. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ ◡{〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} = {〈6, 2〉, 〈9, 3〉} | ||
Theorem | ex-co 28811 | Example for df-co 5599. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((exp ∘ cos)‘0) = e | ||
Theorem | ex-dm 28812 | Example for df-dm 5600. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} → dom 𝐹 = {2, 3}) | ||
Theorem | ex-rn 28813 | Example for df-rn 5601. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} → ran 𝐹 = {6, 9}) | ||
Theorem | ex-res 28814 | Example for df-res 5602. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} ∧ 𝐵 = {1, 2}) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) = {〈2, 6〉}) | ||
Theorem | ex-ima 28815 | Example for df-ima 5603. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} ∧ 𝐵 = {1, 2}) → (𝐹 “ 𝐵) = {6}) | ||
Theorem | ex-fv 28816 | Example for df-fv 6445. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐹 = {〈2, 6〉, 〈3, 9〉} → (𝐹‘3) = 9) | ||
Theorem | ex-1st 28817 | Example for df-1st 7840. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (1st ‘〈3, 4〉) = 3 | ||
Theorem | ex-2nd 28818 | Example for df-2nd 7841. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (2nd ‘〈3, 4〉) = 4 | ||
Theorem | 1kp2ke3k 28819 |
Example for df-dec 12447, 1000 + 2000 = 3000.
This proof disproves (by counterexample) the assertion of Hao Wang, who stated, "There is a theorem in the primitive notation of set theory that corresponds to the arithmetic theorem 1000 + 2000 = 3000. The formula would be forbiddingly long... even if (one) knows the definitions and is asked to simplify the long formula according to them, chances are he will make errors and arrive at some incorrect result." (Hao Wang, "Theory and practice in mathematics" , In Thomas Tymoczko, editor, New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics, pp 129-152, Birkauser Boston, Inc., Boston, 1986. (QA8.6.N48). The quote itself is on page 140.) This is noted in Metamath: A Computer Language for Pure Mathematics by Norman Megill (2007) section 1.1.3. Megill then states, "A number of writers have conveyed the impression that the kind of absolute rigor provided by Metamath is an impossible dream, suggesting that a complete, formal verification of a typical theorem would take millions of steps in untold volumes of books... These writers assume, however, that in order to achieve the kind of complete formal verification they desire one must break down a proof into individual primitive steps that make direct reference to the axioms. This is not necessary. There is no reason not to make use of previously proved theorems rather than proving them over and over... A hierarchy of theorems and definitions permits an exponential growth in the formula sizes and primitive proof steps to be described with only a linear growth in the number of symbols used. Of course, this is how ordinary informal mathematics is normally done anyway, but with Metamath it can be done with absolute rigor and precision." The proof here starts with (2 + 1) = 3, commutes it, and repeatedly multiplies both sides by ten. This is certainly longer than traditional mathematical proofs, e.g., there are a number of steps explicitly shown here to show that we're allowed to do operations such as multiplication. However, while longer, the proof is clearly a manageable size - even though every step is rigorously derived all the way back to the primitive notions of set theory and logic. And while there's a risk of making errors, the many independent verifiers make it much less likely that an incorrect result will be accepted. This proof heavily relies on the decimal constructor df-dec 12447 developed by Mario Carneiro in 2015. The underlying Metamath language has an intentionally very small set of primitives; it doesn't even have a built-in construct for numbers. Instead, the digits are defined using these primitives, and the decimal constructor is used to make it easy to express larger numbers as combinations of digits. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 29-Jun-2016.) (Shortened by Mario Carneiro using the arithmetic algorithm in mmj2, 30-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (;;;1000 + ;;;2000) = ;;;3000 | ||
Theorem | ex-fl 28820 | Example for df-fl 13521. Example by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((⌊‘(3 / 2)) = 1 ∧ (⌊‘-(3 / 2)) = -2) | ||
Theorem | ex-ceil 28821 | Example for df-ceil 13522. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ ((⌈‘(3 / 2)) = 2 ∧ (⌈‘-(3 / 2)) = -1) | ||
Theorem | ex-mod 28822 | Example for df-mod 13599. (Contributed by AV, 3-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ ((5 mod 3) = 2 ∧ (-7 mod 2) = 1) | ||
Theorem | ex-exp 28823 | Example for df-exp 13792. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ ((5↑2) = ;25 ∧ (-3↑-2) = (1 / 9)) | ||
Theorem | ex-fac 28824 | Example for df-fac 13997. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (!‘5) = ;;120 | ||
Theorem | ex-bc 28825 | Example for df-bc 14026. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (5C3) = ;10 | ||
Theorem | ex-hash 28826 | Example for df-hash 14054. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (♯‘{0, 1, 2}) = 3 | ||
Theorem | ex-sqrt 28827 | Example for df-sqrt 14955. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (√‘;25) = 5 | ||
Theorem | ex-abs 28828 | Example for df-abs 14956. (Contributed by AV, 4-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (abs‘-2) = 2 | ||
Theorem | ex-dvds 28829 | Example for df-dvds 15973: 3 divides into 6. (Contributed by David A. Wheeler, 19-May-2015.) |
⊢ 3 ∥ 6 | ||
Theorem | ex-gcd 28830 | Example for df-gcd 16211. (Contributed by AV, 5-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (-6 gcd 9) = 3 | ||
Theorem | ex-lcm 28831 | Example for df-lcm 16304. (Contributed by AV, 5-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (6 lcm 9) = ;18 | ||
Theorem | ex-prmo 28832 | Example for df-prmo 16742: (#p‘10) = 2 · 3 · 5 · 7. (Contributed by AV, 6-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (#p‘;10) = ;;210 | ||
Theorem | aevdemo 28833* | Proof illustrating the comment of aev2 2062. (Contributed by BJ, 30-Mar-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ((∃𝑎∀𝑏 𝑐 = 𝑑 ∨ ∃𝑒 𝑓 = 𝑔) ∧ ∀ℎ(𝑖 = 𝑗 → 𝑘 = 𝑙))) | ||
Theorem | ex-ind-dvds 28834 | Example of a proof by induction (divisibility result). (Contributed by Stanislas Polu, 9-Mar-2020.) (Revised by BJ, 24-Mar-2020.) |
⊢ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 → 3 ∥ ((4↑𝑁) + 2)) | ||
Theorem | ex-fpar 28835 | Formalized example provided in the comment for fpar 7965. (Contributed by AV, 3-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = ((◡(1st ↾ (V × V)) ∘ (𝐹 ∘ (1st ↾ (V × V)))) ∩ (◡(2nd ↾ (V × V)) ∘ (𝐺 ∘ (2nd ↾ (V × V))))) & ⊢ 𝐴 = (0[,)+∞) & ⊢ 𝐵 = ℝ & ⊢ 𝐹 = (√ ↾ 𝐴) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (sin ↾ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝑋( + ∘ 𝐻)𝑌) = ((√‘𝑋) + (sin‘𝑌))) | ||
Theorem | avril1 28836 |
Poisson d'Avril's Theorem. This theorem is noted for its
Selbstdokumentieren property, which means, literally,
"self-documenting" and recalls the principle of quidquid
german dictum
sit, altum viditur, often used in set theory. Starting with the
seemingly simple yet profound fact that any object 𝑥 equals
itself
(proved by Tarski in 1965; see Lemma 6 of [Tarski] p. 68), we
demonstrate that the power set of the real numbers, as a relation on the
value of the imaginary unit, does not conjoin with an empty relation on
the product of the additive and multiplicative identity elements,
leading to this startling conclusion that has left even seasoned
professional mathematicians scratching their heads. (Contributed by
Prof. Loof Lirpa, 1-Apr-2005.) (Proof modification is discouraged.)
(New usage is discouraged.)
A reply to skeptics can be found at mmnotes.txt, under the 1-Apr-2006 entry. |
⊢ ¬ (𝐴𝒫 ℝ(i‘1) ∧ 𝐹∅(0 · 1)) | ||
Theorem | 2bornot2b 28837 | The law of excluded middle. Act III, Theorem 1 of Shakespeare, Hamlet, Prince of Denmark (1602). Its author leaves its proof as an exercise for the reader - "To be, or not to be: that is the question" - starting a trend that has become standard in modern-day textbooks, serving to make the frustrated reader feel inferior, or in some cases to mask the fact that the author does not know its solution. (Contributed by Prof. Loof Lirpa, 1-Apr-2006.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (2 · 𝐵 ∨ ¬ 2 · 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | helloworld 28838 | The classic "Hello world" benchmark has been translated into 314 computer programming languages - see http://helloworldcollection.de. However, for many years it eluded a proof that it is more than just a conjecture, even though a wily mathematician once claimed, "I have discovered a truly marvelous proof of this, which this margin is too narrow to contain." Using an IBM 709 mainframe, a team of mathematicians led by Prof. Loof Lirpa, at the New College of Tahiti, were finally able to put it to rest with a remarkably short proof only four lines long. (Contributed by Prof. Loof Lirpa, 1-Apr-2007.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ¬ (ℎ ∈ (𝐿𝐿0) ∧ 𝑊∅(R1𝑑)) | ||
Theorem | 1p1e2apr1 28839 | One plus one equals two. Using proof-shortening techniques pioneered by Mr. Mel L. O'Cat, along with the latest supercomputer technology, Prof. Loof Lirpa and colleagues were able to shorten Whitehead and Russell's 360-page proof that 1+1=2 in Principia Mathematica to this remarkable proof only two steps long, thus establishing a new world's record for this famous theorem. (Contributed by Prof. Loof Lirpa, 1-Apr-2008.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (1 + 1) = 2 | ||
Theorem | eqid1 28840 |
Law of identity (reflexivity of class equality). Theorem 6.4 of [Quine]
p. 41.
This law is thought to have originated with Aristotle (Metaphysics, Book VII, Part 17). It is one of the three axioms of Ayn Rand's philosophy (Atlas Shrugged, Part Three, Chapter VII). While some have proposed extending Rand's axiomatization to include Compassion and Kindness, others fear that such an extension may flirt with logical inconsistency. (Contributed by Stefan Allan, 1-Apr-2009.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | 1div0apr 28841 | Division by zero is forbidden! If we try, we encounter the DO NOT ENTER sign, which in mathematics means it is foolhardy to venture any further, possibly putting the underlying fabric of reality at risk. Based on a dare by David A. Wheeler. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Apr-2014.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (1 / 0) = ∅ | ||
Theorem | topnfbey 28842 | Nothing seems to be impossible to Prof. Lirpa. After years of intensive research, he managed to find a proof that when given a chance to reach infinity, one could indeed go beyond, thus giving formal soundness to Buzz Lightyear's motto "To infinity... and beyond!" (Contributed by Prof. Loof Lirpa, 1-Apr-2020.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 2-Aug-2020.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ (0...+∞) → +∞ < 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | 9p10ne21 28843 | 9 + 10 is not equal to 21. This disproves a popular meme which asserts that 9 + 10 does equal 21. See https://www.quora.com/Can-someone-try-to-prove-to-me-that-9+10-21 for attempts to prove that 9 + 10 = 21, and see https://tinyurl.com/9p10e21 for the history of the 9 + 10 = 21 meme. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 25-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ (9 + ;10) ≠ ;21 | ||
Theorem | 9p10ne21fool 28844 | 9 + 10 equals 21. This astonishing thesis lives as a meme on the internet, and may be believed by quite some people. At least repeated requests to falsify it are a permanent part of the story. Prof. Loof Lirpa did not rest until he finally came up with a computer verifiable mathematical proof, that only a fool can think so. (Contributed by Prof. Loof Lirpa, 26-Aug-2023.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((9 + ;10) = ;21 → 𝐹∅(0 · 1)) | ||
Syntax | cplig 28845 | Extend class notation with the class of all planar incidence geometries. |
class Plig | ||
Definition | df-plig 28846* |
Define the class of planar incidence geometries. We use Hilbert's
axioms and adapt them to planar geometry. We use ∈ for the
incidence relation. We could have used a generic binary relation, but
using ∈ allows us to reuse previous
results. Much of what follows
is directly borrowed from Aitken, Incidence-Betweenness Geometry,
2008, http://public.csusm.edu/aitken_html/m410/betweenness.08.pdf.
The class Plig is the class of planar incidence geometries, where a planar incidence geometry is defined as a set of lines satisfying three axioms. In the definition below, 𝑥 denotes a planar incidence geometry, so ∪ 𝑥 denotes the union of its lines, that is, the set of points in the plane, 𝑙 denotes a line, and 𝑎, 𝑏, 𝑐 denote points. Therefore, the axioms are: 1) for all pairs of (distinct) points, there exists a unique line containing them; 2) all lines contain at least two points; 3) there exist three non-collinear points. (Contributed by FL, 2-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ Plig = {𝑥 ∣ (∀𝑎 ∈ ∪ 𝑥∀𝑏 ∈ ∪ 𝑥(𝑎 ≠ 𝑏 → ∃!𝑙 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙)) ∧ ∀𝑙 ∈ 𝑥 ∃𝑎 ∈ ∪ 𝑥∃𝑏 ∈ ∪ 𝑥(𝑎 ≠ 𝑏 ∧ 𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙) ∧ ∃𝑎 ∈ ∪ 𝑥∃𝑏 ∈ ∪ 𝑥∃𝑐 ∈ ∪ 𝑥∀𝑙 ∈ 𝑥 ¬ (𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑐 ∈ 𝑙))} | ||
Theorem | isplig 28847* | The predicate "is a planar incidence geometry" for sets. (Contributed by FL, 2-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ 𝑃 = ∪ 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝐺 ∈ Plig ↔ (∀𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∀𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 (𝑎 ≠ 𝑏 → ∃!𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 (𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙)) ∧ ∀𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 (𝑎 ≠ 𝑏 ∧ 𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙) ∧ ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝑃 ∀𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 ¬ (𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑐 ∈ 𝑙)))) | ||
Theorem | ispligb 28848* | The predicate "is a planar incidence geometry". (Contributed by BJ, 2-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑃 = ∪ 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ Plig ↔ (𝐺 ∈ V ∧ (∀𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∀𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 (𝑎 ≠ 𝑏 → ∃!𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 (𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙)) ∧ ∀𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 (𝑎 ≠ 𝑏 ∧ 𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙) ∧ ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝑃 ∀𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 ¬ (𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑐 ∈ 𝑙)))) | ||
Theorem | tncp 28849* | In any planar incidence geometry, there exist three non-collinear points. (Contributed by FL, 3-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ 𝑃 = ∪ 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ Plig → ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝑃 ∀𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 ¬ (𝑎 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝑐 ∈ 𝑙)) | ||
Theorem | l2p 28850* | For any line in a planar incidence geometry, there exist two different points on the line. (Contributed by AV, 28-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑃 = ∪ 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ Plig ∧ 𝐿 ∈ 𝐺) → ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 (𝑎 ≠ 𝑏 ∧ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐿 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝐿)) | ||
Theorem | lpni 28851* | For any line in a planar incidence geometry, there exists a point not on the line. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 15-Aug-2009.) |
⊢ 𝑃 = ∪ 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ Plig ∧ 𝐿 ∈ 𝐺) → ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 𝑎 ∉ 𝐿) | ||
Theorem | nsnlplig 28852 | There is no "one-point line" in a planar incidence geometry. (Contributed by BJ, 2-Dec-2021.) (Proof shortened by AV, 5-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐺 ∈ Plig → ¬ {𝐴} ∈ 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | nsnlpligALT 28853 | Alternate version of nsnlplig 28852 using the predicate ∉ instead of ¬ ∈ and whose proof is shorter. (Contributed by AV, 5-Dec-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐺 ∈ Plig → {𝐴} ∉ 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | n0lplig 28854 | There is no "empty line" in a planar incidence geometry. (Contributed by AV, 28-Nov-2021.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 2-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐺 ∈ Plig → ¬ ∅ ∈ 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | n0lpligALT 28855 | Alternate version of n0lplig 28854 using the predicate ∉ instead of ¬ ∈ and whose proof bypasses nsnlplig 28852. (Contributed by AV, 28-Nov-2021.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐺 ∈ Plig → ∅ ∉ 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | eulplig 28856* | Through two distinct points of a planar incidence geometry, there is a unique line. (Contributed by BJ, 2-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑃 = ∪ 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ Plig ∧ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑃 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑃) ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵)) → ∃!𝑙 ∈ 𝐺 (𝐴 ∈ 𝑙 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑙)) | ||
Theorem | pliguhgr 28857 | Any planar incidence geometry 𝐺 can be regarded as a hypergraph with its points as vertices and its lines as edges. See incistruhgr 27458 for a generalization of this case for arbitrary incidence structures (planar incidence geometries are such incidence structures). (Proposed by Gerard Lang, 24-Nov-2021.) (Contributed by AV, 28-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐺 ∈ Plig → 〈∪ 𝐺, ( I ↾ 𝐺)〉 ∈ UHGraph) | ||
This section contains a few aliases that we temporarily keep to prevent broken links. If you land on any of these, please let the originating site and/or us know that the link that made you land here should be changed. | ||
Theorem | dummylink 28858 |
Alias for a1ii 2 that may be referenced in some older works, and
kept
here to prevent broken links.
If you landed here, please let the originating site and/or us know that the link that made you land here should be changed to a link to a1ii 2. (Contributed by NM, 7-Feb-2006.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝜑 & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | id1 28859 |
Alias for idALT 23 that may be referenced in some older works, and
kept
here to prevent broken links.
If you landed here, please let the originating site and/or us know that the link that made you land here should be changed to a link to idALT 23. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-1992.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜑) | ||
The intent is for this deprecated section to be deleted once its theorems have extensible structure versions (or are not useful). You can make a list of "terminal" theorems (i.e., theorems not referenced by anything else) and for each theorem see if there exists an extensible structure version (or decide it is not useful), and if so, delete it. Then, repeat this recursively. One way to search for terminal theorems is to log the output ("MM> OPEN LOG xxx.txt") of "MM> SHOW USAGE <label-match>" in the Metamath program and search for "(None)". | ||
This section contains an earlier development of groups that was defined before extensible structures were introduced. The intent is for this deprecated section to be deleted once the corresponding definitions and theorems for complex topological vector spaces, which are using them, are revised accordingly. | ||
Syntax | cgr 28860 | Extend class notation with the class of all group operations. |
class GrpOp | ||
Syntax | cgi 28861 | Extend class notation with a function mapping a group operation to the group's identity element. |
class GId | ||
Syntax | cgn 28862 | Extend class notation with a function mapping a group operation to the inverse function for the group. |
class inv | ||
Syntax | cgs 28863 | Extend class notation with a function mapping a group operation to the division (or subtraction) operation for the group. |
class /𝑔 | ||
Definition | df-grpo 28864* | Define the class of all group operations. The base set for a group can be determined from its group operation. Based on the definition in Exercise 28 of [Herstein] p. 54. (Contributed by NM, 10-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ GrpOp = {𝑔 ∣ ∃𝑡(𝑔:(𝑡 × 𝑡)⟶𝑡 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑡 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑡 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑡 ((𝑥𝑔𝑦)𝑔𝑧) = (𝑥𝑔(𝑦𝑔𝑧)) ∧ ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑡 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑡 ((𝑢𝑔𝑥) = 𝑥 ∧ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑡 (𝑦𝑔𝑥) = 𝑢))} | ||
Definition | df-gid 28865* | Define a function that maps a group operation to the group's identity element. (Contributed by FL, 5-Feb-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ GId = (𝑔 ∈ V ↦ (℩𝑢 ∈ ran 𝑔∀𝑥 ∈ ran 𝑔((𝑢𝑔𝑥) = 𝑥 ∧ (𝑥𝑔𝑢) = 𝑥))) | ||
Definition | df-ginv 28866* | Define a function that maps a group operation to the group's inverse function. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ inv = (𝑔 ∈ GrpOp ↦ (𝑥 ∈ ran 𝑔 ↦ (℩𝑧 ∈ ran 𝑔(𝑧𝑔𝑥) = (GId‘𝑔)))) | ||
Definition | df-gdiv 28867* | Define a function that maps a group operation to the group's division (or subtraction) operation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ /𝑔 = (𝑔 ∈ GrpOp ↦ (𝑥 ∈ ran 𝑔, 𝑦 ∈ ran 𝑔 ↦ (𝑥𝑔((inv‘𝑔)‘𝑦)))) | ||
Theorem | isgrpo 28868* | The predicate "is a group operation." Note that 𝑋 is the base set of the group. (Contributed by NM, 10-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ↔ (𝐺:(𝑋 × 𝑋)⟶𝑋 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑥𝐺𝑦)𝐺𝑧) = (𝑥𝐺(𝑦𝐺𝑧)) ∧ ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑢𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥 ∧ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑦𝐺𝑥) = 𝑢)))) | ||
Theorem | isgrpoi 28869* | Properties that determine a group operation. Read 𝑁 as 𝑁(𝑥). (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐺:(𝑋 × 𝑋)⟶𝑋 & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑋) → ((𝑥𝐺𝑦)𝐺𝑧) = (𝑥𝐺(𝑦𝐺𝑧))) & ⊢ 𝑈 ∈ 𝑋 & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 → (𝑈𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥) & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 → 𝑁 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 → (𝑁𝐺𝑥) = 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐺 ∈ GrpOp | ||
Theorem | grpofo 28870 | A group operation maps onto the group's underlying set. (Contributed by NM, 30-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → 𝐺:(𝑋 × 𝑋)–onto→𝑋) | ||
Theorem | grpocl 28871 | Closure law for a group operation. (Contributed by NM, 10-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴𝐺𝐵) ∈ 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | grpolidinv 28872* | A group has a left identity element, and every member has a left inverse. (Contributed by NM, 2-Nov-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑢𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥 ∧ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑦𝐺𝑥) = 𝑢)) | ||
Theorem | grpon0 28873 | The base set of a group is not empty. (Contributed by Szymon Jaroszewicz, 3-Apr-2007.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → 𝑋 ≠ ∅) | ||
Theorem | grpoass 28874 | A group operation is associative. (Contributed by NM, 10-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋)) → ((𝐴𝐺𝐵)𝐺𝐶) = (𝐴𝐺(𝐵𝐺𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | grpoidinvlem1 28875 | Lemma for grpoidinv 28879. (Contributed by NM, 10-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ (𝑌 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋)) ∧ ((𝑌𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈 ∧ (𝐴𝐺𝐴) = 𝐴)) → (𝑈𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grpoidinvlem2 28876 | Lemma for grpoidinv 28879. (Contributed by NM, 10-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ (𝑌 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋)) ∧ ((𝑈𝐺𝑌) = 𝑌 ∧ (𝑌𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈)) → ((𝐴𝐺𝑌)𝐺(𝐴𝐺𝑌)) = (𝐴𝐺𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | grpoidinvlem3 28877* | Lemma for grpoidinv 28879. (Contributed by NM, 11-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑈𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑧𝐺𝑥) = 𝑈) ⇒ ⊢ ((((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝑈 ∈ 𝑋) ∧ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑦𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈 ∧ (𝐴𝐺𝑦) = 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | grpoidinvlem4 28878* | Lemma for grpoidinv 28879. (Contributed by NM, 14-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) ∧ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑦𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈 ∧ (𝐴𝐺𝑦) = 𝑈)) → (𝐴𝐺𝑈) = (𝑈𝐺𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | grpoidinv 28879* | A group has a left and right identity element, and every member has a left and right inverse. (Contributed by NM, 14-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 (((𝑢𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥 ∧ (𝑥𝐺𝑢) = 𝑥) ∧ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑦𝐺𝑥) = 𝑢 ∧ (𝑥𝐺𝑦) = 𝑢))) | ||
Theorem | grpoideu 28880* | The left identity element of a group is unique. Lemma 2.2.1(a) of [Herstein] p. 55. (Contributed by NM, 14-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → ∃!𝑢 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑢𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | grporndm 28881 | A group's range in terms of its domain. (Contributed by NM, 6-Apr-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → ran 𝐺 = dom dom 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | 0ngrp 28882 | The empty set is not a group. (Contributed by NM, 25-Apr-2007.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ¬ ∅ ∈ GrpOp | ||
Theorem | gidval 28883* | The value of the identity element of a group. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ 𝑉 → (GId‘𝐺) = (℩𝑢 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑢𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥 ∧ (𝑥𝐺𝑢) = 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | grpoidval 28884* | Lemma for grpoidcl 28885 and others. (Contributed by NM, 5-Feb-2010.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → 𝑈 = (℩𝑢 ∈ 𝑋 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑢𝐺𝑥) = 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | grpoidcl 28885 | The identity element of a group belongs to the group. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → 𝑈 ∈ 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | grpoidinv2 28886* | A group's properties using the explicit identity element. (Contributed by NM, 5-Feb-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (((𝑈𝐺𝐴) = 𝐴 ∧ (𝐴𝐺𝑈) = 𝐴) ∧ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 ((𝑦𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈 ∧ (𝐴𝐺𝑦) = 𝑈))) | ||
Theorem | grpolid 28887 | The identity element of a group is a left identity. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝑈𝐺𝐴) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | grporid 28888 | The identity element of a group is a right identity. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴𝐺𝑈) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | grporcan 28889 | Right cancellation law for groups. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋)) → ((𝐴𝐺𝐶) = (𝐵𝐺𝐶) ↔ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | grpoinveu 28890* | The left inverse element of a group is unique. Lemma 2.2.1(b) of [Herstein] p. 55. (Contributed by NM, 27-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑦𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grpoid 28891 | Two ways of saying that an element of a group is the identity element. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 25-Feb-2008.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴 = 𝑈 ↔ (𝐴𝐺𝐴) = 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | grporn 28892 | The range of a group operation. Useful for satisfying group base set hypotheses of the form 𝑋 = ran 𝐺. (Contributed by NM, 5-Nov-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐺 ∈ GrpOp & ⊢ dom 𝐺 = (𝑋 × 𝑋) ⇒ ⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 | ||
Theorem | grpoinvfval 28893* | The inverse function of a group. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ GrpOp → 𝑁 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 ↦ (℩𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑦𝐺𝑥) = 𝑈))) | ||
Theorem | grpoinvval 28894* | The inverse of a group element. (Contributed by NM, 26-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝑁‘𝐴) = (℩𝑦 ∈ 𝑋 (𝑦𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | grpoinvcl 28895 | A group element's inverse is a group element. (Contributed by NM, 27-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝑁‘𝐴) ∈ 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | grpoinv 28896 | The properties of a group element's inverse. (Contributed by NM, 27-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Dec-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (((𝑁‘𝐴)𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈 ∧ (𝐴𝐺(𝑁‘𝐴)) = 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | grpolinv 28897 | The left inverse of a group element. (Contributed by NM, 27-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → ((𝑁‘𝐴)𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grporinv 28898 | The right inverse of a group element. (Contributed by NM, 27-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴𝐺(𝑁‘𝐴)) = 𝑈) | ||
Theorem | grpoinvid1 28899 | The inverse of a group element expressed in terms of the identity element. (Contributed by NM, 27-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋) → ((𝑁‘𝐴) = 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴𝐺𝐵) = 𝑈)) | ||
Theorem | grpoinvid2 28900 | The inverse of a group element expressed in terms of the identity element. (Contributed by NM, 27-Oct-2006.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝑋 = ran 𝐺 & ⊢ 𝑈 = (GId‘𝐺) & ⊢ 𝑁 = (inv‘𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ GrpOp ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑋 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑋) → ((𝑁‘𝐴) = 𝐵 ↔ (𝐵𝐺𝐴) = 𝑈)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |