![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 89 of 479) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30159) |
![]() (30160-31682) |
![]() (31683-47806) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | brecop 8801* | Binary relation on a quotient set. Lemma for real number construction. (Contributed by NM, 29-Jan-1996.) |
⊢ ∼ ∈ V & ⊢ ∼ Er (𝐺 × 𝐺) & ⊢ 𝐻 = ((𝐺 × 𝐺) / ∼ ) & ⊢ ≤ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐻 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐻) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) ∧ 𝜑))} & ⊢ ((((𝑧 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝐺) ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐺)) ∧ ((𝑣 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐺) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐺))) → (([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ = [⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ ∧ [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ = [⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐺) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐺)) → ([⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ ≤ [⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | brecop2 8802 | Binary relation on a quotient set. Lemma for real number construction. Eliminates antecedent from last hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 13-Feb-1996.) (Revised by AV, 12-Jul-2022.) |
⊢ dom ∼ = (𝐺 × 𝐺) & ⊢ 𝐻 = ((𝐺 × 𝐺) / ∼ ) & ⊢ 𝑅 ⊆ (𝐻 × 𝐻) & ⊢ ≤ ⊆ (𝐺 × 𝐺) & ⊢ ¬ ∅ ∈ 𝐺 & ⊢ dom + = (𝐺 × 𝐺) & ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐺) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝐺 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝐺)) → ([⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ 𝑅[⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ↔ (𝐴 + 𝐷) ≤ (𝐵 + 𝐶))) ⇒ ⊢ ([⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ 𝑅[⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ↔ (𝐴 + 𝐷) ≤ (𝐵 + 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | eroveu 8803* | Lemma for erov 8805 and eroprf 8806. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Jul-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / 𝑅) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐵 / 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑍) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Er 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Er 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐵))) → ((𝑟𝑅𝑠 ∧ 𝑡𝑆𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡)𝑇(𝑠 + 𝑢))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐽 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐾)) → ∃!𝑧∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑋 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑌 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)) | ||
Theorem | erovlem 8804* | Lemma for erov 8805 and eroprf 8806. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / 𝑅) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐵 / 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑍) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Er 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Er 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐵))) → ((𝑟𝑅𝑠 ∧ 𝑡𝑆𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡)𝑇(𝑠 + 𝑢))) & ⊢ ⨣ = {⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑥 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ⨣ = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐽, 𝑦 ∈ 𝐾 ↦ (℩𝑧∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑥 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)))) | ||
Theorem | erov 8805* | The value of an operation defined on equivalence classes. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / 𝑅) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐵 / 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑍) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Er 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Er 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐵))) → ((𝑟𝑅𝑠 ∧ 𝑡𝑆𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡)𝑇(𝑠 + 𝑢))) & ⊢ ⨣ = {⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑥 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑌) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑃 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝐵) → ([𝑃]𝑅 ⨣ [𝑄]𝑆) = [(𝑃 + 𝑄)]𝑇) | ||
Theorem | eroprf 8806* | Functionality of an operation defined on equivalence classes. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / 𝑅) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐵 / 𝑆) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑍) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Er 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Er 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Er 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐵)⟶𝐶) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐵))) → ((𝑟𝑅𝑠 ∧ 𝑡𝑆𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡)𝑇(𝑠 + 𝑢))) & ⊢ ⨣ = {⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐵 ((𝑥 = [𝑝]𝑅 ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞]𝑆) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)]𝑇)} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 ∈ 𝑌) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝐶 / 𝑇) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ⨣ :(𝐽 × 𝐾)⟶𝐿) | ||
Theorem | erov2 8807* | The value of an operation defined on equivalence classes. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / ∼ ) & ⊢ ⨣ = {⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝑥 = [𝑝] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)] ∼ )} & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∼ ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∼ Er 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐴)⟶𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐴))) → ((𝑟 ∼ 𝑠 ∧ 𝑡 ∼ 𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡) ∼ (𝑠 + 𝑢))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑃 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝐴) → ([𝑃] ∼ ⨣ [𝑄] ∼ ) = [(𝑃 + 𝑄)] ∼ ) | ||
Theorem | eroprf2 8808* | Functionality of an operation defined on equivalence classes. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) |
⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐴 / ∼ ) & ⊢ ⨣ = {⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩ ∣ ∃𝑝 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑞 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝑥 = [𝑝] ∼ ∧ 𝑦 = [𝑞] ∼ ) ∧ 𝑧 = [(𝑝 + 𝑞)] ∼ )} & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∼ ∈ 𝑋) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∼ Er 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈) & ⊢ (𝜑 → + :(𝐴 × 𝐴)⟶𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ ((𝑟 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝐴))) → ((𝑟 ∼ 𝑠 ∧ 𝑡 ∼ 𝑢) → (𝑟 + 𝑡) ∼ (𝑠 + 𝑢))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ⨣ :(𝐽 × 𝐽)⟶𝐽) | ||
Theorem | ecopoveq 8809* | This is the first of several theorems about equivalence relations of the kind used in construction of fractions and signed reals, involving operations on equivalent classes of ordered pairs. This theorem expresses the relation ∼ (specified by the hypothesis) in terms of its operation 𝐹. (Contributed by NM, 16-Aug-1995.) |
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∼ ⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩ ↔ (𝐴 + 𝐷) = (𝐵 + 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | ecopovsym 8810* | Assuming the operation 𝐹 is commutative, show that the relation ∼, specified by the first hypothesis, is symmetric. (Contributed by NM, 27-Aug-1995.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∼ 𝐵 → 𝐵 ∼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ecopovtrn 8811* | Assuming that operation 𝐹 is commutative (second hypothesis), closed (third hypothesis), associative (fourth hypothesis), and has the cancellation property (fifth hypothesis), show that the relation ∼, specified by the first hypothesis, is transitive. (Contributed by NM, 11-Feb-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆) & ⊢ ((𝑥 + 𝑦) + 𝑧) = (𝑥 + (𝑦 + 𝑧)) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑥 + 𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∼ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∼ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ecopover 8812* | Assuming that operation 𝐹 is commutative (second hypothesis), closed (third hypothesis), associative (fourth hypothesis), and has the cancellation property (fifth hypothesis), show that the relation ∼, specified by the first hypothesis, is an equivalence relation. (Contributed by NM, 16-Feb-1996.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2015.) (Proof shortened by AV, 1-May-2021.) |
⊢ ∼ = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ ((𝑥 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝑆 × 𝑆)) ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∃𝑣∃𝑢((𝑥 = ⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∧ 𝑦 = ⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩) ∧ (𝑧 + 𝑢) = (𝑤 + 𝑣)))} & ⊢ (𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑦 + 𝑥) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆) & ⊢ ((𝑥 + 𝑦) + 𝑧) = (𝑥 + (𝑦 + 𝑧)) & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → ((𝑥 + 𝑦) = (𝑥 + 𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧)) ⇒ ⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆) | ||
Theorem | eceqoveq 8813* | Equality of equivalence relation in terms of an operation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Feb-1996.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ∼ Er (𝑆 × 𝑆) & ⊢ dom + = (𝑆 × 𝑆) & ⊢ ¬ ∅ ∈ 𝑆 & ⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) → (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ 𝑆) & ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑆)) → (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∼ ⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩ ↔ (𝐴 + 𝐷) = (𝐵 + 𝐶))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑆) → ([⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩] ∼ = [⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩] ∼ ↔ (𝐴 + 𝐷) = (𝐵 + 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | ecovcom 8814* | Lemma used to transfer a commutative law via an equivalence relation. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-1995.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐶 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐷, 𝐺⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐻, 𝐽⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ 𝐷 = 𝐻 & ⊢ 𝐺 = 𝐽 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → (𝐴 + 𝐵) = (𝐵 + 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ecovass 8815* | Lemma used to transfer an associative law via an equivalence relation. (Contributed by NM, 31-Aug-1995.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐷 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐺, 𝐻⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑁, 𝑄⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝐺 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐻 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝐺, 𝐻⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐽, 𝐾⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑁 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑁, 𝑄⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐿, 𝑀⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝐺 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐻 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑁 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑄 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ 𝐽 = 𝐿 & ⊢ 𝐾 = 𝑀 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷) → ((𝐴 + 𝐵) + 𝐶) = (𝐴 + (𝐵 + 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | ecovdi 8816* | Lemma used to transfer a distributive law via an equivalence relation. (Contributed by NM, 2-Sep-1995.) (Revised by David Abernethy, 4-Jun-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐷 = ((𝑆 × 𝑆) / ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑀, 𝑁⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑀 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑀, 𝑁⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐻, 𝐽⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑊, 𝑋⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩] ∼ · [⟨𝑣, 𝑢⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝑌, 𝑍⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑊 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑌 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑆)) → ([⟨𝑊, 𝑋⟩] ∼ + [⟨𝑌, 𝑍⟩] ∼ ) = [⟨𝐾, 𝐿⟩] ∼ ) & ⊢ (((𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑀 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑊 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ (((𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆) ∧ (𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑆)) → (𝑌 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝑆)) & ⊢ 𝐻 = 𝐾 & ⊢ 𝐽 = 𝐿 ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 · (𝐵 + 𝐶)) = ((𝐴 · 𝐵) + (𝐴 · 𝐶))) | ||
Syntax | cmap 8817 | Extend the definition of a class to include the mapping operation. (Read for 𝐴 ↑m 𝐵, "the set of all functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴.) |
class ↑m | ||
Syntax | cpm 8818 | Extend the definition of a class to include the partial mapping operation. (Read for 𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵, "the set of all partial functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴.) |
class ↑pm | ||
Definition | df-map 8819* | Define the mapping operation or set exponentiation. The set of all functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴 is written (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) (see mapval 8829). Many authors write 𝐴 followed by 𝐵 as a superscript for this operation and rely on context to avoid confusion other exponentiation operations (e.g., Definition 10.42 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 95). Other authors show 𝐵 as a prefixed superscript, which is read "𝐴 pre 𝐵 " (e.g., definition of [Enderton] p. 52). Definition 8.21 of [Eisenberg] p. 125 uses the notation Map(𝐵, 𝐴) for our (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵). The up-arrow is used by Donald Knuth for iterated exponentiation (Science 194, 1235-1242, 1976). We adopt the first case of his notation (simple exponentiation) and subscript it with m to distinguish it from other kinds of exponentiation. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ ↑m = (𝑥 ∈ V, 𝑦 ∈ V ↦ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝑦⟶𝑥}) | ||
Definition | df-pm 8820* | Define the partial mapping operation. A partial function from 𝐵 to 𝐴 is a function from a subset of 𝐵 to 𝐴. The set of all partial functions from 𝐵 to 𝐴 is written (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) (see pmvalg 8828). A notation for this operation apparently does not appear in the literature. We use ↑pm to distinguish it from the less general set exponentiation operation ↑m (df-map 8819). See mapsspm 8867 for its relationship to set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) |
⊢ ↑pm = (𝑥 ∈ V, 𝑦 ∈ V ↦ {𝑓 ∈ 𝒫 (𝑦 × 𝑥) ∣ Fun 𝑓}) | ||
Theorem | mapprc 8821* | When 𝐴 is a proper class, the class of all functions mapping 𝐴 to 𝐵 is empty. Exercise 4.41 of [Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ V → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} = ∅) | ||
Theorem | pmex 8822* | The class of all partial functions from one set to another is a set. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → {𝑓 ∣ (Fun 𝑓 ∧ 𝑓 ⊆ (𝐴 × 𝐵))} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | mapex 8823* | The class of all functions mapping one set to another is a set. Remark after Definition 10.24 of [Kunen] p. 31. (Contributed by Raph Levien, 4-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | fnmap 8824 | Set exponentiation has a universal domain. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ↑m Fn (V × V) | ||
Theorem | fnpm 8825 | Partial function exponentiation has a universal domain. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ ↑pm Fn (V × V) | ||
Theorem | reldmmap 8826 | Set exponentiation is a well-behaved binary operator. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 27-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ Rel dom ↑m | ||
Theorem | mapvalg 8827* | The value of set exponentiation. (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) is the set of all functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴. Definition 10.24 of [Kunen] p. 24. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐵⟶𝐴}) | ||
Theorem | pmvalg 8828* | The value of the partial mapping operation. (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) is the set of all partial functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 8-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) = {𝑓 ∈ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) ∣ Fun 𝑓}) | ||
Theorem | mapval 8829* | The value of set exponentiation (inference version). (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) is the set of all functions that map from 𝐵 to 𝐴. Definition 10.24 of [Kunen] p. 24. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐵⟶𝐴} | ||
Theorem | elmapg 8830 | Membership relation for set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM, 17-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ↔ 𝐶:𝐵⟶𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | elmapd 8831 | Deduction form of elmapg 8830. (Contributed by BJ, 11-Apr-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ↔ 𝐶:𝐵⟶𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | elmapdd 8832 | Deduction associated with elmapd 8831. (Contributed by SN, 29-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶:𝐵⟶𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | mapdm0 8833 | The empty set is the only map with empty domain. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 11-Oct-2020.) (Proof shortened by Thierry Arnoux, 3-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐵 ↑m ∅) = {∅}) | ||
Theorem | elpmg 8834 | The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐶 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (Fun 𝐶 ∧ 𝐶 ⊆ (𝐵 × 𝐴)))) | ||
Theorem | elpm2g 8835 | The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | elpm2r 8836 | Sufficient condition for being a partial function. (Contributed by NM, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ∧ (𝐹:𝐶⟶𝐴 ∧ 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐵)) → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elpmi 8837 | A partial function is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) → (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | pmfun 8838 | A partial function is a function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Jan-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) → Fun 𝐹) | ||
Theorem | elmapex 8839 | Eliminate antecedent for mapping theorems: domain can be taken to be a set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) → (𝐵 ∈ V ∧ 𝐶 ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | elmapi 8840 | A mapping is a function, forward direction only with superfluous antecedent removed. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) → 𝐴:𝐶⟶𝐵) | ||
Theorem | mapfset 8841* | If 𝐵 is a set, the value of the set exponentiation (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) is the class of all functions from 𝐴 to 𝐵. Generalisation of mapvalg 8827 (which does not require ax-rep 5285) to arbitrary domains. Note that the class {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} can only contain set-functions, as opposed to arbitrary class-functions. When 𝐴 is a proper class, there can be no set-functions on it, so the above class is empty (see also fsetdmprc0 8846), hence a set. In this case, both sides of the equality in this theorem are the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 8-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} = (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | mapssfset 8842* | The value of the set exponentiation (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) is a subset of the class of functions from 𝐴 to 𝐵. (Contributed by AV, 10-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) ⊆ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} | ||
Theorem | mapfoss 8843* | The value of the set exponentiation (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) is a superset of the set of all functions from 𝐴 onto 𝐵. (Contributed by AV, 7-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴–onto→𝐵} ⊆ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | fsetsspwxp 8844* | The class of all functions from 𝐴 into 𝐵 is a subclass of the power class of the cartesion product of 𝐴 and 𝐵. (Contributed by AV, 13-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ⊆ 𝒫 (𝐴 × 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | fset0 8845 | The set of functions from the empty set is the singleton containing the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 13-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:∅⟶𝐵} = {∅} | ||
Theorem | fsetdmprc0 8846* | The set of functions with a proper class as domain is empty. (Contributed by AV, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∉ V → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓 Fn 𝐴} = ∅) | ||
Theorem | fsetex 8847* | The set of functions between two classes exists if the codomain exists. Generalization of mapex 8823 to arbitrary domains. (Contributed by AV, 14-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | f1setex 8848* | The set of injections between two classes exists if the codomain exists. (Contributed by AV, 14-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴–1-1→𝐵} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | fosetex 8849* | The set of surjections between two classes exists (without any precondition). (Contributed by AV, 8-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴–onto→𝐵} ∈ V | ||
Theorem | f1osetex 8850* | The set of bijections between two classes exists. (Contributed by AV, 30-Mar-2024.) (Revised by AV, 8-Aug-2024.) (Proof shortened by SN, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴–1-1-onto→𝐵} ∈ V | ||
Theorem | fsetfcdm 8851* | The class of functions with a given domain and a given codomain is mapped, through evaluation at a point of the domain, into the codomain. (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} & ⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑔 ∈ 𝐹 ↦ (𝑔‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝑆:𝐹⟶𝐵) | ||
Theorem | fsetfocdm 8852* | The class of functions with a given domain that is a set and a given codomain is mapped, through evaluation at a point of the domain, onto the codomain. (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} & ⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑔 ∈ 𝐹 ↦ (𝑔‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑆:𝐹–onto→𝐵) | ||
Theorem | fsetprcnex 8853* | The class of all functions from a nonempty set 𝐴 into a proper class 𝐵 is not a set. If one of the preconditions is not fufilled, then {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} is a set, see fsetdmprc0 8846 for 𝐴 ∉ V, fset0 8845 for 𝐴 = ∅, and fsetex 8847 for 𝐵 ∈ V, see also fsetexb 8855. (Contributed by AV, 14-Sep-2024.) (Proof shortened by BJ, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) ∧ 𝐵 ∉ V) → {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∉ V) | ||
Theorem | fsetcdmex 8854* | The class of all functions from a nonempty set 𝐴 into a class 𝐵 is a set iff 𝐵 is a set . (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → (𝐵 ∈ V ↔ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | fsetexb 8855* | The class of all functions from a class 𝐴 into a class 𝐵 is a set iff 𝐵 is a set or 𝐴 is not a set or 𝐴 is empty. (Contributed by AV, 15-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ({𝑓 ∣ 𝑓:𝐴⟶𝐵} ∈ V ↔ (𝐴 ∉ V ∨ 𝐴 = ∅ ∨ 𝐵 ∈ V)) | ||
Theorem | elmapfn 8856 | A mapping is a function with the appropriate domain. (Contributed by AV, 6-Apr-2019.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) → 𝐴 Fn 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | elmapfun 8857 | A mapping is always a function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) → Fun 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | elmapssres 8858 | A restricted mapping is a mapping. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶) ∧ 𝐷 ⊆ 𝐶) → (𝐴 ↾ 𝐷) ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | fpmg 8859 | A total function is a partial function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵) → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑pm 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | pmss12g 8860 | Subset relation for the set of partial functions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐷) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑊)) → (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ⊆ (𝐶 ↑pm 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pmresg 8861 | Elementhood of a restricted function in the set of partial functions. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐶)) → (𝐹 ↾ 𝐵) ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elmap 8862 | Membership relation for set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ↔ 𝐹:𝐵⟶𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapval2 8863* | Alternate expression for the value of set exponentiation. (Contributed by NM, 3-Nov-2007.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = (𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) ∩ {𝑓 ∣ 𝑓 Fn 𝐵}) | ||
Theorem | elpm 8864 | The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐹 ⊆ (𝐵 × 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | elpm2 8865 | The predicate "is a partial function". (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ↔ (𝐹:dom 𝐹⟶𝐴 ∧ dom 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | fpm 8866 | A total function is a partial function. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-Dec-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵 → 𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑pm 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | mapsspm 8867 | Set exponentiation is a subset of partial maps. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 27-Feb-2016.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ⊆ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | pmsspw 8868 | Partial maps are a subset of the power set of the Cartesian product of its arguments. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↑pm 𝐵) ⊆ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapsspw 8869 | Set exponentiation is a subset of the power set of the Cartesian product of its arguments. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ⊆ 𝒫 (𝐵 × 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mapfvd 8870 | The value of a function that maps from 𝐵 to 𝐴. (Contributed by AV, 2-Feb-2023.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ 𝑀) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐹‘𝑋) ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | elmapresaun 8871 | fresaun 6760 transposed to mappings. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ (𝐶 ↑m 𝐴) ∧ 𝐺 ∈ (𝐶 ↑m 𝐵) ∧ (𝐹 ↾ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵)) = (𝐺 ↾ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵))) → (𝐹 ∪ 𝐺) ∈ (𝐶 ↑m (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | fvmptmap 8872* | Special case of fvmpt 6996 for operator theorems. (Contributed by NM, 27-Nov-2007.) |
⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐷 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑅 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝑅 ↑m 𝐷) ↦ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴:𝐷⟶𝑅 → (𝐹‘𝐴) = 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | map0e 8873 | Set exponentiation with an empty exponent (ordinal number 0) is ordinal number 1. Exercise 4.42(a) of [Mendelson] p. 255. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) (Proof shortened by AV, 14-Jul-2022.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ↑m ∅) = 1o) | ||
Theorem | map0b 8874 | Set exponentiation with an empty base is the empty set, provided the exponent is nonempty. Theorem 96 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≠ ∅ → (∅ ↑m 𝐴) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | map0g 8875 | Set exponentiation is empty iff the base is empty and the exponent is not empty. Theorem 97 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → ((𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = ∅ ↔ (𝐴 = ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅))) | ||
Theorem | 0map0sn0 8876 | The set of mappings of the empty set to the empty set is the singleton containing the empty set. (Contributed by AV, 31-Mar-2024.) |
⊢ (∅ ↑m ∅) = {∅} | ||
Theorem | mapsnd 8877* | The value of set exponentiation with a singleton exponent. Theorem 98 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Glauco Siliprandi, 24-Dec-2020.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ↑m {𝐵}) = {𝑓 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝑓 = {⟨𝐵, 𝑦⟩}}) | ||
Theorem | map0 8878 | Set exponentiation is empty iff the base is empty and the exponent is not empty. Theorem 97 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) = ∅ ↔ (𝐴 = ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ≠ ∅)) | ||
Theorem | mapsn 8879* | The value of set exponentiation with a singleton exponent. Theorem 98 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Proof shortened by AV, 17-Jul-2022.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ↑m {𝐵}) = {𝑓 ∣ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝑓 = {⟨𝐵, 𝑦⟩}} | ||
Theorem | mapss 8880 | Subset inheritance for set exponentiation. Theorem 99 of [Suppes] p. 89. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐶) ⊆ (𝐵 ↑m 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | fdiagfn 8881* | Functionality of the diagonal map. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝐼 × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐼 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐹:𝐵⟶(𝐵 ↑m 𝐼)) | ||
Theorem | fvdiagfn 8882* | Functionality of the diagonal map. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝐼 × {𝑥})) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐼 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝑋 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝐹‘𝑋) = (𝐼 × {𝑋})) | ||
Theorem | mapsnconst 8883 | Every singleton map is a constant function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 25-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) → 𝐹 = (𝑆 × {(𝐹‘𝑋)})) | ||
Theorem | mapsncnv 8884* | Expression for the inverse of the canonical map between a set and its set of singleton functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) ↦ (𝑥‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ ◡𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝑆 × {𝑦})) | ||
Theorem | mapsnf1o2 8885* | Explicit bijection between a set and its singleton functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ (𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) ↦ (𝑥‘𝑋)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:(𝐵 ↑m 𝑆)–1-1-onto→𝐵 | ||
Theorem | mapsnf1o3 8886* | Explicit bijection in the reverse of mapsnf1o2 8885. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Mar-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑋} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ↦ (𝑆 × {𝑦})) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹:𝐵–1-1-onto→(𝐵 ↑m 𝑆) | ||
Theorem | ralxpmap 8887* | Quantification over functions in terms of quantification over values and punctured functions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 27-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 5-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑓 = (𝑔 ∪ {⟨𝐽, 𝑦⟩}) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐽 ∈ 𝑇 → (∀𝑓 ∈ (𝑆 ↑m 𝑇)𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∀𝑔 ∈ (𝑆 ↑m (𝑇 ∖ {𝐽}))𝜓)) | ||
Syntax | cixp 8888 | Extend class notation to include infinite Cartesian products. |
class X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Definition | df-ixp 8889* | Definition of infinite Cartesian product of [Enderton] p. 54. Enderton uses a bold "X" with 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 written underneath or as a subscript, as does Stoll p. 47. Some books use a capital pi, but we will reserve that notation for products of numbers. Usually 𝐵 represents a class expression containing 𝑥 free and thus can be thought of as 𝐵(𝑥). Normally, 𝑥 is not free in 𝐴, although this is not a requirement of the definition. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = {𝑓 ∣ (𝑓 Fn {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴} ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)} | ||
Theorem | dfixp 8890* | Eliminate the expression {𝑥 ∣ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴} in df-ixp 8889, under the assumption that 𝐴 and 𝑥 are disjoint. This way, we can say that 𝑥 is bound in X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴𝐵 even if it appears free in 𝐴. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 12-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = {𝑓 ∣ (𝑓 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑓‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)} | ||
Theorem | ixpsnval 8891* | The value of an infinite Cartesian product with a singleton. (Contributed by AV, 3-Dec-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 → X𝑥 ∈ {𝑋}𝐵 = {𝑓 ∣ (𝑓 Fn {𝑋} ∧ (𝑓‘𝑋) ∈ ⦋𝑋 / 𝑥⦌𝐵)}) | ||
Theorem | elixp2 8892* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product. See df-ixp 8889 for discussion of the notation. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ (𝐹 ∈ V ∧ 𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | fvixp 8893* | Projection of a factor of an indexed Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐶 → 𝐵 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐹‘𝐶) ∈ 𝐷) | ||
Theorem | ixpfn 8894* | A nuple is a function. (Contributed by FL, 6-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 31-May-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 → 𝐹 Fn 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | elixp 8895* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elixpconst 8896* | Membership in an infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2008.) |
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 ∈ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ↔ 𝐹:𝐴⟶𝐵) | ||
Theorem | ixpconstg 8897* | Infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ixpconst 8898* | Infinite Cartesian product of a constant 𝐵. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 = (𝐵 ↑m 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq1 8899* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | ixpeq1d 8900* | Equality theorem for infinite Cartesian product. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Jun-2016.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → X𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 = X𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐶) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |