Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 99 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29181) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29182-30704) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30705-46395) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | iunfictbso 9801 | Countability of a countable union of finite sets with a strict (not globally well) order fulfilling the choice role. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ Fin ∧ 𝐵 Or ∪ 𝐴) → ∪ 𝐴 ≼ ω) | ||
Syntax | wac 9802 | Wff for an abbreviation of the axiom of choice. |
wff CHOICE | ||
Definition | df-ac 9803* |
The expression CHOICE will be used as a
readable shorthand for any
form of the axiom of choice; all concrete forms are long, cryptic, have
dummy variables, or all three, making it useful to have a short name.
Similar to the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49.
There is a slight problem with taking the exact form of ax-ac 10146 as our definition, because the equivalence to more standard forms (dfac2 9818) requires the Axiom of Regularity, which we often try to avoid. Thus, we take the first of the "textbook forms" as the definition and derive the form of ax-ac 10146 itself as dfac0 9820. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑓(𝑓 ⊆ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑓 Fn dom 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | aceq1 9804* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10146. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side expresses our AC with the fewest number of different variables. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑥∀𝑧(∃𝑥((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑧 = 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | aceq0 9805* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side is our original ax-ac 10146. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑣∀𝑢(∃𝑡((𝑢 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑡) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑡 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑢 = 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | aceq2 9806* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | aceq3lem 9807* | Lemma for dfac3 9808. (Contributed by NM, 2-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑤 ∈ dom 𝑦 ↦ (𝑓‘{𝑢 ∣ 𝑤𝑦𝑢})) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥∃𝑓∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧) → ∃𝑓(𝑓 ⊆ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑓 Fn dom 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dfac3 9808* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The left-hand side is defined as the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49. The right-hand side is the Axiom of Choice of [TakeutiZaring] p. 83. The proof does not depend on AC. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-2004.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑓∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧)) | ||
Theorem | dfac4 9809* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The right-hand side is Axiom AC of [BellMachover] p. 488. The proof does not depend on AC. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑓(𝑓 Fn 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem1 9810* | Lemma for dfac5 9815. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (({𝑤} × 𝑤) ∩ 𝑦) ↔ ∃!𝑔(𝑔 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 〈𝑤, 𝑔〉 ∈ 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem2 9811* | Lemma for dfac5 9815. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} ⇒ ⊢ (〈𝑤, 𝑔〉 ∈ ∪ 𝐴 ↔ (𝑤 ∈ ℎ ∧ 𝑔 ∈ 𝑤)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem3 9812* | Lemma for dfac5 9815. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} ⇒ ⊢ (({𝑤} × 𝑤) ∈ 𝐴 ↔ (𝑤 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝑤 ∈ ℎ)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem4 9813* | Lemma for dfac5 9815. (Contributed by NM, 11-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} & ⊢ 𝐵 = (∪ 𝐴 ∩ 𝑦) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5lem5 9814* | Lemma for dfac5 9815. (Contributed by NM, 12-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ (𝑢 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∃𝑡 ∈ ℎ 𝑢 = ({𝑡} × 𝑡))} & ⊢ 𝐵 = (∪ 𝐴 ∩ 𝑦) & ⊢ (𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑓∀𝑤 ∈ ℎ (𝑤 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑤) ∈ 𝑤)) | ||
Theorem | dfac5 9815* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The right-hand side is Theorem 6M(4) of [Enderton] p. 151 and asserts that given a family of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, a set exists containing exactly one member from each set in the family. The proof does not depend on AC. (Contributed by NM, 11-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | dfac2a 9816* | Our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac3 10149) implies the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49. The proof uses neither AC nor the Axiom of Regularity. See dfac2b 9817 for the converse (which does use the Axiom of Regularity). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣)) → CHOICE) | ||
Theorem | dfac2b 9817* | Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49 implies our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac3 10149). The proof does not make use of AC. Note that the Axiom of Regularity is used by the proof. Specifically, elneq 9287 and preleq 9304 that are referenced in the proof each make use of Regularity for their derivations. (The reverse implication can be derived without using Regularity; see dfac2a 9816.) (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) (Revised by AV, 16-Jun-2022.) |
⊢ (CHOICE → ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | dfac2 9818* | Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49 corresponds to our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac3 10149). The proof does not make use of AC, but the Axiom of Regularity is used (by applying dfac2b 9817). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) (Revised by AV, 16-Jun-2022.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑣 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | dfac7 9819* | Equivalence of the Axiom of Choice (first form) of [Enderton] p. 49 and our Axiom of Choice (in the form of ac2 10148). The proof does not depend on AC but does depend on the Axiom of Regularity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 ∃!𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑦 (𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑢)) | ||
Theorem | dfac0 9820* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice. The proof uses the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side is our original ax-ac 10146. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑣∀𝑢(∃𝑡((𝑢 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑡) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑡 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑢 = 𝑣))) | ||
Theorem | dfac1 9821* | Equivalence of two versions of the Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10146. The proof uses the Axiom of Regularity. The right-hand side expresses our AC with the fewest number of different variables. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑥∀𝑧(∃𝑥((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑧 = 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | dfac8 9822* | A proof of the equivalency of the well-ordering theorem weth 10182 and the axiom of choice ac7 10160. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑟 𝑟 We 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | dfac9 9823* | Equivalence of the axiom of choice with a statement related to ac9 10170; definition AC3 of [Schechter] p. 139. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑓((Fun 𝑓 ∧ ∅ ∉ ran 𝑓) → X𝑥 ∈ dom 𝑓(𝑓‘𝑥) ≠ ∅)) | ||
Theorem | dfac10 9824 | Axiom of Choice equivalent: the cardinality function measures every set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ dom card = V) | ||
Theorem | dfac10c 9825* | Axiom of Choice equivalent: every set is equinumerous to an ordinal. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦 ∈ On 𝑦 ≈ 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | dfac10b 9826 | Axiom of Choice equivalent: every set is equinumerous to an ordinal (quantifier-free short cryptic version alluded to in df-ac 9803). (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ( ≈ “ On) = V) | ||
Theorem | acacni 9827 | A choice equivalent: every set has choice sets of every length. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ ((CHOICE ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) → AC 𝐴 = V) | ||
Theorem | dfacacn 9828 | A choice equivalent: every set has choice sets of every length. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥AC 𝑥 = V) | ||
Theorem | dfac13 9829 | The axiom of choice holds iff every set has choice sequences as long as itself. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥 𝑥 ∈ AC 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | dfac12lem1 9830* | Lemma for dfac12 9836. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ On) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝒫 (har‘(𝑅1‘𝐴))–1-1→On) & ⊢ 𝐺 = recs((𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑦 ∈ (𝑅1‘dom 𝑥) ↦ if(dom 𝑥 = ∪ dom 𝑥, ((suc ∪ ran ∪ ran 𝑥 ·o (rank‘𝑦)) +o ((𝑥‘suc (rank‘𝑦))‘𝑦)), (𝐹‘((◡OrdIso( E , ran (𝑥‘∪ dom 𝑥)) ∘ (𝑥‘∪ dom 𝑥)) “ 𝑦)))))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ On) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (◡OrdIso( E , ran (𝐺‘∪ 𝐶)) ∘ (𝐺‘∪ 𝐶)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐺‘𝐶) = (𝑦 ∈ (𝑅1‘𝐶) ↦ if(𝐶 = ∪ 𝐶, ((suc ∪ ran ∪ (𝐺 “ 𝐶) ·o (rank‘𝑦)) +o ((𝐺‘suc (rank‘𝑦))‘𝑦)), (𝐹‘(𝐻 “ 𝑦))))) | ||
Theorem | dfac12lem2 9831* | Lemma for dfac12 9836. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ On) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝒫 (har‘(𝑅1‘𝐴))–1-1→On) & ⊢ 𝐺 = recs((𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑦 ∈ (𝑅1‘dom 𝑥) ↦ if(dom 𝑥 = ∪ dom 𝑥, ((suc ∪ ran ∪ ran 𝑥 ·o (rank‘𝑦)) +o ((𝑥‘suc (rank‘𝑦))‘𝑦)), (𝐹‘((◡OrdIso( E , ran (𝑥‘∪ dom 𝑥)) ∘ (𝑥‘∪ dom 𝑥)) “ 𝑦)))))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ On) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (◡OrdIso( E , ran (𝐺‘∪ 𝐶)) ∘ (𝐺‘∪ 𝐶)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐶 (𝐺‘𝑧):(𝑅1‘𝑧)–1-1→On) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐺‘𝐶):(𝑅1‘𝐶)–1-1→On) | ||
Theorem | dfac12lem3 9832* | Lemma for dfac12 9836. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ On) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝒫 (har‘(𝑅1‘𝐴))–1-1→On) & ⊢ 𝐺 = recs((𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (𝑦 ∈ (𝑅1‘dom 𝑥) ↦ if(dom 𝑥 = ∪ dom 𝑥, ((suc ∪ ran ∪ ran 𝑥 ·o (rank‘𝑦)) +o ((𝑥‘suc (rank‘𝑦))‘𝑦)), (𝐹‘((◡OrdIso( E , ran (𝑥‘∪ dom 𝑥)) ∘ (𝑥‘∪ dom 𝑥)) “ 𝑦)))))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝑅1‘𝐴) ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | dfac12r 9833 | The axiom of choice holds iff every ordinal has a well-orderable powerset. This version of dfac12 9836 does not assume the Axiom of Regularity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-May-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ On 𝒫 𝑥 ∈ dom card ↔ ∪ (𝑅1 “ On) ⊆ dom card) | ||
Theorem | dfac12k 9834* | Equivalence of dfac12 9836 and dfac12a 9835, without using Regularity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 21-May-2015.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ On 𝒫 𝑥 ∈ dom card ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ On 𝒫 (ℵ‘𝑦) ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | dfac12a 9835 | The axiom of choice holds iff every ordinal has a well-orderable powerset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ On 𝒫 𝑥 ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | dfac12 9836 | The axiom of choice holds iff every aleph has a well-orderable powerset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 21-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ On 𝒫 (ℵ‘𝑥) ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | kmlem1 9837* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, 1 => 2. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 𝜑) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 𝜑 → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem2 9838* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝜑 → ∃!𝑤 𝑤 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ↔ ∃𝑦(¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝜑 → ∃!𝑤 𝑤 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem3 9839* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. The right-hand side is part of the hypothesis of 4. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝑧 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑧})) ≠ ∅ ↔ ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → ¬ 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem4 9840* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑧 ≠ 𝑤) → ((𝑧 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑧})) ∩ 𝑤) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | kmlem5 9841* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑧 ≠ 𝑤) → ((𝑧 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑧})) ∩ (𝑤 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑤}))) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | kmlem6 9842* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 4 => 1. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝜑 → 𝐴 = ∅)) → ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑣 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | kmlem7 9843* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 4 => 1. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ¬ ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem8 9844* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4 1 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ ((¬ ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 𝜓 → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑤 𝑤 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦))) ↔ (∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 𝜓 ∨ ∃𝑦(¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑢 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑢 ∃!𝑤 𝑤 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem9 9845* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑡 ∈ 𝑥 𝑢 = (𝑡 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑡}))} ⇒ ⊢ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | kmlem10 9846* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑡 ∈ 𝑥 𝑢 = (𝑡 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑡}))} ⇒ ⊢ (∀ℎ(∀𝑧 ∈ ℎ ∀𝑤 ∈ ℎ (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ ℎ 𝜑) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | kmlem11 9847* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑡 ∈ 𝑥 𝑢 = (𝑡 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑡}))} ⇒ ⊢ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → (𝑧 ∩ ∪ 𝐴) = (𝑧 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑧}))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem12 9848* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 3 => 4. (Contributed by NM, 27-Mar-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑡 ∈ 𝑥 𝑢 = (𝑡 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑡}))} ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑧})) ≠ ∅ → (∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) → ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ (𝑦 ∩ ∪ 𝐴))))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem13 9849* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4 1 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ 𝐴 = {𝑢 ∣ ∃𝑡 ∈ 𝑥 𝑢 = (𝑡 ∖ ∪ (𝑥 ∖ {𝑡}))} ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥((∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 𝑧 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 → (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤) = ∅)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ↔ ∀𝑥(¬ ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤)) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)))) | ||
Theorem | kmlem14 9850* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 5 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑦 ≠ 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤)) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | kmlem15 9851* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4, part of 5 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑦 ≠ 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ ((¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜒) ↔ ∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢(¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | kmlem16 9852* | Lemma for 5-quantifier AC of Kurt Maes, Th. 4 5 <=> 4. (Contributed by NM, 4-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝜑 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑦 ≠ 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) & ⊢ (𝜓 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))) & ⊢ (𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∃!𝑣 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑦)) ⇒ ⊢ ((∃𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ∀𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ (𝑧 ∩ 𝑤)) ∨ ∃𝑦(¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜒)) ↔ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢((𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜑) ∨ (¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝜓))) | ||
Theorem | dfackm 9853* | Equivalence of the Axiom of Choice and Maes' AC ackm 10152. The proof consists of lemmas kmlem1 9837 through kmlem16 9852 and this final theorem. AC is not used for the proof. Note: bypassing the first step (i.e., replacing dfac5 9815 with biid 260) establishes the AC equivalence shown by Maes' writeup. The left-hand-side AC shown here was chosen because it is shorter to display. (Contributed by NM, 13-Apr-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ ∀𝑥∃𝑦∀𝑧∃𝑣∀𝑢((𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ¬ 𝑦 = 𝑣) ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑣))) ∨ (¬ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ((𝑣 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑣 ∈ 𝑦) ∧ ((𝑢 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑢 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑢 = 𝑣)))))) | ||
For cardinal arithmetic, we follow [Mendelson] p. 258. Rather than defining operations restricted to cardinal numbers, we use disjoint union df-dju 9590 (⊔) for cardinal addition, Cartesian product df-xp 5586 (×) for cardinal multiplication, and set exponentiation df-map 8575 (↑m) for cardinal exponentiation. Equinumerosity and dominance serve the roles of equality and ordering. If we wanted to, we could easily convert our theorems to actual cardinal number operations via carden 10238, carddom 10241, and cardsdom 10242. The advantage of Mendelson's approach is that we can directly use many equinumerosity theorems that we already have available. | ||
Theorem | undjudom 9854 | Cardinal addition dominates union. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 15-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≼ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | endjudisj 9855 | Equinumerosity of a disjoint union and a union of two disjoint sets. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2007.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djuen 9856 | Disjoint unions of equinumerous sets are equinumerous. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ≈ 𝐷) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐶) ≈ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | djuenun 9857 | Disjoint union is equinumerous to union for disjoint sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 19-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ≈ 𝐷 ∧ (𝐵 ∩ 𝐷) = ∅) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐶) ≈ (𝐵 ∪ 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | dju1en 9858 | Cardinal addition with cardinal one (which is the same as ordinal one). Used in proof of Theorem 6J of [Enderton] p. 143. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 1o) ≈ suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dju1dif 9859 | Adding and subtracting one gives back the original cardinality. Similar to pncan 11157 for cardinalities. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 20-Aug-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (𝐴 ⊔ 1o)) → ((𝐴 ⊔ 1o) ∖ {𝐵}) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dju1p1e2 9860 | 1+1=2 for cardinal number addition, derived from pm54.43 9690 as promised. Theorem *110.643 of Principia Mathematica, vol. II, p. 86, which adds the remark, "The above proposition is occasionally useful." Whitehead and Russell define cardinal addition on collections of all sets equinumerous to 1 and 2 (which for us are proper classes unless we restrict them as in karden 9584), but after applying definitions, our theorem is equivalent. Because we use a disjoint union for cardinal addition (as explained in the comment at the top of this section), we use ≈ instead of =. See dju1p1e2ALT 9861 for a shorter proof that doesn't use pm54.43 9690. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2007.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (1o ⊔ 1o) ≈ 2o | ||
Theorem | dju1p1e2ALT 9861 | Alternate proof of dju1p1e2 9860. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (1o ⊔ 1o) ≈ 2o | ||
Theorem | dju0en 9862 | Cardinal addition with cardinal zero (the empty set). Part (a1) of proof of Theorem 6J of [Enderton] p. 143. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ⊔ ∅) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | xp2dju 9863 | Two times a cardinal number. Exercise 4.56(g) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (2o × 𝐴) = (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | djucomen 9864 | Commutative law for cardinal addition. Exercise 4.56(c) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 24-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | djuassen 9865 | Associative law for cardinal addition. Exercise 4.56(c) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 26-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → ((𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ⊔ 𝐶) ≈ (𝐴 ⊔ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | xpdjuen 9866 | Cardinal multiplication distributes over cardinal addition. Theorem 6I(3) of [Enderton] p. 142. (Contributed by NM, 26-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴 × (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶)) ≈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) ⊔ (𝐴 × 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | mapdjuen 9867 | Sum of exponents law for cardinal arithmetic. Theorem 6I(4) of [Enderton] p. 142. (Contributed by NM, 27-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑋) → (𝐴 ↑m (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶)) ≈ ((𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) × (𝐴 ↑m 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | pwdjuen 9868 | Sum of exponents law for cardinal arithmetic. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝒫 (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝒫 𝐴 × 𝒫 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djudom1 9869 | Ordering law for cardinal addition. Exercise 4.56(f) of [Mendelson] p. 258. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 1-Sep-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐶) ≼ (𝐵 ⊔ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | djudom2 9870 | Ordering law for cardinal addition. Theorem 6L(a) of [Enderton] p. 149. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑉) → (𝐶 ⊔ 𝐴) ≼ (𝐶 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djudoml 9871 | A set is dominated by its disjoint union with another. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → 𝐴 ≼ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djuxpdom 9872 | Cartesian product dominates disjoint union for sets with cardinality greater than 1. Similar to Proposition 10.36 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 93. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((1o ≺ 𝐴 ∧ 1o ≺ 𝐵) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | djufi 9873 | The disjoint union of two finite sets is finite. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≺ ω ∧ 𝐵 ≺ ω) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≺ ω) | ||
Theorem | cdainflem 9874 | Any partition of omega into two pieces (which may be disjoint) contains an infinite subset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≈ ω → (𝐴 ≈ ω ∨ 𝐵 ≈ ω)) | ||
Theorem | djuinf 9875 | A set is infinite iff the cardinal sum with itself is infinite. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 ↔ ω ≼ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | infdju1 9876 | An infinite set is equinumerous to itself added with one. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 → (𝐴 ⊔ 1o) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pwdju1 9877 | The sum of a powerset with itself is equipotent to the successor powerset. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝒫 𝐴 ⊔ 𝒫 𝐴) ≈ 𝒫 (𝐴 ⊔ 1o)) | ||
Theorem | pwdjuidm 9878 | If the natural numbers inject into 𝐴, then 𝒫 𝐴 is idempotent under cardinal sum. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 → (𝒫 𝐴 ⊔ 𝒫 𝐴) ≈ 𝒫 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | djulepw 9879 | If 𝐴 is idempotent under cardinal sum and 𝐵 is dominated by the power set of 𝐴, then so is the cardinal sum of 𝐴 and 𝐵. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝒫 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≼ 𝒫 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | onadju 9880 | The cardinal and ordinal sums are always equinumerous. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Jim Kingdon, 7-Sep-2023.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 +o 𝐵) ≈ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardadju 9881 | The cardinal sum is equinumerous to an ordinal sum of the cardinals. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | djunum 9882 | The disjoint union of two numerable sets is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | unnum 9883 | The union of two numerable sets is numerable. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ dom card) | ||
Theorem | nnadju 9884 | The cardinal and ordinal sums of finite ordinals are equal. For a shorter proof using ax-rep 5205, see nnadjuALT 9885. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 11-Apr-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) Avoid ax-rep 5205. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 2-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (card‘(𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) = (𝐴 +o 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | nnadjuALT 9885 | Shorter proof of nnadju 9884 using ax-rep 5205. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 11-Apr-2009.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 6-Feb-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω) → (card‘(𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵)) = (𝐴 +o 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ficardadju 9886 | The disjoint union of finite sets is equinumerous to the ordinal sum of the cardinalities of those sets. (Contributed by BTernaryTau, 3-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ficardun 9887 | The cardinality of the union of disjoint, finite sets is the ordinal sum of their cardinalities. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 5-Jun-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) Avoid ax-rep 5205. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 3-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin ∧ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅) → (card‘(𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) = ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ficardunOLD 9888 | Obsolete version of ficardun 9887 as of 3-Jul-2024. (Contributed by Paul Chapman, 5-Jun-2009.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin ∧ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅) → (card‘(𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) = ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ficardun2 9889 | The cardinality of the union of finite sets is at most the ordinal sum of their cardinalities. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Feb-2013.) Avoid ax-rep 5205. (Revised by BTernaryTau, 3-Jul-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin) → (card‘(𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) ⊆ ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ficardun2OLD 9890 | Obsolete version of ficardun2 9889 as of 3-Jul-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 5-Feb-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐵 ∈ Fin) → (card‘(𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) ⊆ ((card‘𝐴) +o (card‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | pwsdompw 9891* | Lemma for domtriom 10130. This is the equinumerosity version of the algebraic identity Σ𝑘 ∈ 𝑛(2↑𝑘) = (2↑𝑛) − 1. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ((𝑛 ∈ ω ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ suc 𝑛(𝐵‘𝑘) ≈ 𝒫 𝑘) → ∪ 𝑘 ∈ 𝑛 (𝐵‘𝑘) ≺ (𝐵‘𝑛)) | ||
Theorem | unctb 9892 | The union of two countable sets is countable. (Contributed by FL, 25-Aug-2006.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ 𝐵 ≼ ω) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | infdjuabs 9893 | Absorption law for addition to an infinite cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infunabs 9894 | An infinite set is equinumerous to its union with a smaller one. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infdju 9895 | The sum of two cardinal numbers is their maximum, if one of them is infinite. Proposition 10.41 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 95. (Contributed by NM, 28-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐵) ≈ (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | infdif 9896 | The cardinality of an infinite set does not change after subtracting a strictly smaller one. Example in [Enderton] p. 164. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infdif2 9897 | Cardinality ordering for an infinite class difference. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-2007.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ 𝐵 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) → ((𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) ≼ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | infxpdom 9898 | Dominance law for multiplication with an infinite cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2006.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infxpabs 9899 | Absorption law for multiplication with an infinite cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 30-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 29-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝐴) ∧ (𝐵 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴)) → (𝐴 × 𝐵) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | infunsdom1 9900 | The union of two sets that are strictly dominated by the infinite set 𝑋 is also dominated by 𝑋. This version of infunsdom 9901 assumes additionally that 𝐴 is the smaller of the two. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 14-Dec-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝑋 ∈ dom card ∧ ω ≼ 𝑋) ∧ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ 𝑋)) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ≺ 𝑋) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |