![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 104 of 474) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-29923) |
![]() (29924-31446) |
![]() (31447-47372) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | isf32lem4 10301* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. Being a chain, difference sets are disjoint. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 5-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) ∧ (𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω)) → (((𝐹‘𝐴) ∖ (𝐹‘suc 𝐴)) ∩ ((𝐹‘𝐵) ∖ (𝐹‘suc 𝐵))) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem5 10302* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. There are infinite decrease points. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 5-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ ω ∣ (𝐹‘suc 𝑦) ⊊ (𝐹‘𝑦)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑆 ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem6 10303* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. Each K value is nonempty. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 5-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ ω ∣ (𝐹‘suc 𝑦) ⊊ (𝐹‘𝑦)} & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝑢 ∈ ω ↦ (℩𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 (𝑣 ∩ 𝑆) ≈ 𝑢)) & ⊢ 𝐾 = ((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ ((𝐹‘𝑤) ∖ (𝐹‘suc 𝑤))) ∘ 𝐽) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ω) → (𝐾‘𝐴) ≠ ∅) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem7 10304* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. Different K values are disjoint. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 5-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ ω ∣ (𝐹‘suc 𝑦) ⊊ (𝐹‘𝑦)} & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝑢 ∈ ω ↦ (℩𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 (𝑣 ∩ 𝑆) ≈ 𝑢)) & ⊢ 𝐾 = ((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ ((𝐹‘𝑤) ∖ (𝐹‘suc 𝑤))) ∘ 𝐽) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵) ∧ (𝐴 ∈ ω ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ω)) → ((𝐾‘𝐴) ∩ (𝐾‘𝐵)) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem8 10305* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. K sets are subsets of the base. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 6-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ ω ∣ (𝐹‘suc 𝑦) ⊊ (𝐹‘𝑦)} & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝑢 ∈ ω ↦ (℩𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 (𝑣 ∩ 𝑆) ≈ 𝑢)) & ⊢ 𝐾 = ((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ ((𝐹‘𝑤) ∖ (𝐹‘suc 𝑤))) ∘ 𝐽) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ω) → (𝐾‘𝐴) ⊆ 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem9 10306* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. Construction of the onto function. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 5-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Oct-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ ω ∣ (𝐹‘suc 𝑦) ⊊ (𝐹‘𝑦)} & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝑢 ∈ ω ↦ (℩𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 (𝑣 ∩ 𝑆) ≈ 𝑢)) & ⊢ 𝐾 = ((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ ((𝐹‘𝑤) ∖ (𝐹‘suc 𝑤))) ∘ 𝐽) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑡 ∈ 𝐺 ↦ (℩𝑠(𝑠 ∈ ω ∧ 𝑡 ∈ (𝐾‘𝑠)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐿:𝐺–onto→ω) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem10 10307* | Lemma for isfin3-2 . Write in terms of weak dominance. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 6-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑦 ∈ ω ∣ (𝐹‘suc 𝑦) ⊊ (𝐹‘𝑦)} & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝑢 ∈ ω ↦ (℩𝑣 ∈ 𝑆 (𝑣 ∩ 𝑆) ≈ 𝑢)) & ⊢ 𝐾 = ((𝑤 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ ((𝐹‘𝑤) ∖ (𝐹‘suc 𝑤))) ∘ 𝐽) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑡 ∈ 𝐺 ↦ (℩𝑠(𝑠 ∈ ω ∧ 𝑡 ∈ (𝐾‘𝑠)))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐺 ∈ 𝑉 → ω ≼* 𝐺)) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem11 10308* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. Remove hypotheses from isf32lem10 10307. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐺 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ (𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐺 ∧ ∀𝑏 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑏) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑏) ∧ ¬ ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹)) → ω ≼* 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | isf32lem12 10309* | Lemma for isfin3-2 10312. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 6-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = {𝑔 ∣ ∀𝑎 ∈ (𝒫 𝑔 ↑m ω)(∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝑎‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝑎‘𝑥) → ∩ ran 𝑎 ∈ ran 𝑎)} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐺 ∈ 𝑉 → (¬ ω ≼* 𝐺 → 𝐺 ∈ 𝐹)) | ||
Theorem | isfin32i 10310 | One half of isfin3-2 10312. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ FinIII → ¬ ω ≼* 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | isf33lem 10311* | Lemma for isfin3-3 10313. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ FinIII = {𝑔 ∣ ∀𝑎 ∈ (𝒫 𝑔 ↑m ω)(∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝑎‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝑎‘𝑥) → ∩ ran 𝑎 ∈ ran 𝑎)} | ||
Theorem | isfin3-2 10312 | Weakly Dedekind-infinite sets are exactly those which can be mapped onto ω. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 6-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ FinIII ↔ ¬ ω ≼* 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | isfin3-3 10313* | Weakly Dedekind-infinite sets are exactly those with an ω-indexed descending chain of subsets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ FinIII ↔ ∀𝑓 ∈ (𝒫 𝐴 ↑m ω)(∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝑓‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝑓‘𝑥) → ∩ ran 𝑓 ∈ ran 𝑓))) | ||
Theorem | fin33i 10314* | Inference from isfin3-3 10313. (This is actually a bit stronger than isfin3-3 10313 because it does not assume 𝐹 is a set and does not use the Axiom of Infinity either.) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ FinIII ∧ 𝐹:ω⟶𝒫 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐹‘suc 𝑥) ⊆ (𝐹‘𝑥)) → ∩ ran 𝐹 ∈ ran 𝐹) | ||
Theorem | compsscnvlem 10315* | Lemma for compsscnv 10316. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 = (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) → (𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 = (𝐴 ∖ 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | compsscnv 10316* | Complementation on a power set lattice is an involution. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ ◡𝐹 = 𝐹 | ||
Theorem | isf34lem1 10317* | Lemma for isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑋 ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝐹‘𝑋) = (𝐴 ∖ 𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | isf34lem2 10318* | Lemma for isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐹:𝒫 𝐴⟶𝒫 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | compssiso 10319* | Complementation is an antiautomorphism on power set lattices. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐹 Isom [⊊] , ◡ [⊊] (𝒫 𝐴, 𝒫 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | isf34lem3 10320* | Lemma for isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑋 ⊆ 𝒫 𝐴) → (𝐹 “ (𝐹 “ 𝑋)) = 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | compss 10321* | Express image under of the complementation isomorphism. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 5-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐹 “ 𝐺) = {𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ∣ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑦) ∈ 𝐺} | ||
Theorem | isf34lem4 10322* | Lemma for isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ (𝑋 ⊆ 𝒫 𝐴 ∧ 𝑋 ≠ ∅)) → (𝐹‘∪ 𝑋) = ∩ (𝐹 “ 𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | isf34lem5 10323* | Lemma for isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ (𝑋 ⊆ 𝒫 𝐴 ∧ 𝑋 ≠ ∅)) → (𝐹‘∩ 𝑋) = ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | isf34lem7 10324* | Lemma for isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ FinIII ∧ 𝐺:ω⟶𝒫 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ ω (𝐺‘𝑦) ⊆ (𝐺‘suc 𝑦)) → ∪ ran 𝐺 ∈ ran 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | isf34lem6 10325* | Lemma for isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴 ↦ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ FinIII ↔ ∀𝑓 ∈ (𝒫 𝐴 ↑m ω)(∀𝑦 ∈ ω (𝑓‘𝑦) ⊆ (𝑓‘suc 𝑦) → ∪ ran 𝑓 ∈ ran 𝑓))) | ||
Theorem | fin34i 10326* | Inference from isfin3-4 10327. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ FinIII ∧ 𝐺:ω⟶𝒫 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝐺‘𝑥) ⊆ (𝐺‘suc 𝑥)) → ∪ ran 𝐺 ∈ ran 𝐺) | ||
Theorem | isfin3-4 10327* | Weakly Dedekind-infinite sets are exactly those with an ω-indexed ascending chain of subsets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ FinIII ↔ ∀𝑓 ∈ (𝒫 𝐴 ↑m ω)(∀𝑥 ∈ ω (𝑓‘𝑥) ⊆ (𝑓‘suc 𝑥) → ∪ ran 𝑓 ∈ ran 𝑓))) | ||
Theorem | fin11a 10328 | Every I-finite set is Ia-finite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → 𝐴 ∈ FinIa) | ||
Theorem | enfin1ai 10329 | Ia-finiteness is a cardinal property. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ FinIa → 𝐵 ∈ FinIa)) | ||
Theorem | isfin1-2 10330 | A set is finite in the usual sense iff the power set of its power set is Dedekind finite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 3-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin ↔ 𝒫 𝒫 𝐴 ∈ FinIV) | ||
Theorem | isfin1-3 10331 | A set is I-finite iff every system of subsets contains a maximal subset. Definition I of [Levy58] p. 2. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ Fin ↔ ◡ [⊊] Fr 𝒫 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | isfin1-4 10332 | A set is I-finite iff every system of subsets contains a minimal subset. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ Fin ↔ [⊊] Fr 𝒫 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dffin1-5 10333 | Compact quantifier-free version of the standard definition df-fin 8894. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 6-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ Fin = ( ≈ “ ω) | ||
Theorem | fin23 10334 |
Every II-finite set (every chain of subsets has a maximal element) is
III-finite (has no denumerable collection of subsets). The proof here
is the only one I could find, from
http://matwbn.icm.edu.pl/ksiazki/fm/fm6/fm619.pdf
p.94 (writeup by
Tarski, credited to Kuratowski). Translated into English and modern
notation, the proof proceeds as follows (variables renamed for
uniqueness):
Suppose for a contradiction that 𝐴 is a set which is II-finite but not III-finite. For any countable sequence of distinct subsets 𝑇 of 𝐴, we can form a decreasing sequence of nonempty subsets (𝑈‘𝑇) by taking finite intersections of initial segments of 𝑇 while skipping over any element of 𝑇 which would cause the intersection to be empty. By II-finiteness (as fin2i2 10263) this sequence contains its intersection, call it 𝑌; since by induction every subset in the sequence 𝑈 is nonempty, the intersection must be nonempty. Suppose that an element 𝑋 of 𝑇 has nonempty intersection with 𝑌. Thus, said element has a nonempty intersection with the corresponding element of 𝑈, therefore it was used in the construction of 𝑈 and all further elements of 𝑈 are subsets of 𝑋, thus 𝑋 contains the 𝑌. That is, all elements of 𝑋 either contain 𝑌 or are disjoint from it. Since there are only two cases, there must exist an infinite subset of 𝑇 which uniformly either contain 𝑌 or are disjoint from it. In the former case we can create an infinite set by subtracting 𝑌 from each element. In either case, call the result 𝑍; this is an infinite set of subsets of 𝐴, each of which is disjoint from 𝑌 and contained in the union of 𝑇; the union of 𝑍 is strictly contained in the union of 𝑇, because only the latter is a superset of the nonempty set 𝑌. The preceding four steps may be iterated a countable number of times starting from the assumed denumerable set of subsets to produce a denumerable sequence 𝐵 of the 𝑇 sets from each stage. Great caution is required to avoid ax-dc 10391 here; in particular an effective version of the pigeonhole principle (for aleph-null pigeons and 2 holes) is required. Since a denumerable set of subsets is assumed to exist, we can conclude ω ∈ V without the axiom. This 𝐵 sequence is strictly decreasing, thus it has no minimum, contradicting the first assumption. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ FinII → 𝐴 ∈ FinIII) | ||
Theorem | fin34 10335 | Every III-finite set is IV-finite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ FinIII → 𝐴 ∈ FinIV) | ||
Theorem | isfin5-2 10336 | Alternate definition of V-finite which emphasizes the idempotent behavior of V-infinite sets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ FinV ↔ ¬ (𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐴 ≈ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴)))) | ||
Theorem | fin45 10337 | Every IV-finite set is V-finite: if we can pack two copies of the set into itself, we can certainly leave space. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 30-Oct-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ FinIV → 𝐴 ∈ FinV) | ||
Theorem | fin56 10338 | Every V-finite set is VI-finite because multiplication dominates addition for cardinals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ FinV → 𝐴 ∈ FinVI) | ||
Theorem | fin17 10339 | Every I-finite set is VII-finite. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → 𝐴 ∈ FinVII) | ||
Theorem | fin67 10340 | Every VI-finite set is VII-finite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ FinVI → 𝐴 ∈ FinVII) | ||
Theorem | isfin7-2 10341 | A set is VII-finite iff it is non-well-orderable or finite. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ FinVII ↔ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → 𝐴 ∈ Fin))) | ||
Theorem | fin71num 10342 | A well-orderable set is VII-finite iff it is I-finite. Thus, even without choice, on the class of well-orderable sets all eight definitions of finite set coincide. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom card → (𝐴 ∈ FinVII ↔ 𝐴 ∈ Fin)) | ||
Theorem | dffin7-2 10343 | Class form of isfin7-2 10341. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ FinVII = (Fin ∪ (V ∖ dom card)) | ||
Theorem | dfacfin7 10344 | Axiom of Choice equivalent: the VII-finite sets are the same as I-finite sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-May-2015.) |
⊢ (CHOICE ↔ FinVII = Fin) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem1 10345 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑥 ∈ On ↦ suc 𝑥) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝑆‘𝐴) = suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem2 10346 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. The successor operation on the ordinal numbers is injective or one-to-one. Lemma 1.17 of [Schloeder] p. 2. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑥 ∈ On ↦ suc 𝑥) ⇒ ⊢ 𝑆:On–1-1→On | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem3 10347 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = (𝑥 ∈ ω ↦ (2o ·o 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐸‘𝐴) = (2o ·o 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem4 10348 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = (𝑥 ∈ ω ↦ (2o ·o 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐸:ω–1-1→ω | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem5 10349 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = (𝑥 ∈ ω ↦ (2o ·o 𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ω → (𝐴 ∈ ran 𝐸 ↔ ¬ suc 𝐴 ∈ ran 𝐸)) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem6 10350 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. Establish that ω can be broken into two equipollent pieces. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = (𝑥 ∈ ω ↦ (2o ·o 𝑥)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑥 ∈ On ↦ suc 𝑥) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑆 ↾ ran 𝐸):ran 𝐸–1-1-onto→(ω ∖ ran 𝐸) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem7 10351* | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. Split a III-infinite set in two pieces. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐸 = (𝑥 ∈ ω ↦ (2o ·o 𝑥)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = (𝑥 ∈ On ↦ suc 𝑥) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴(𝑦 ∈ FinIII ∨ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑦) ∈ FinIII)) → 𝐴 ∈ FinIII) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem8 10352* | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. Split a III-infinite set in two pieces. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 7-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴(𝑥 ∈ FinIII ∨ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ FinIII)) → 𝐴 ∈ FinIII) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem9 10353* | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. In a chain of finite sets, initial segments are finite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (( [⊊] Or 𝑋 ∧ 𝑋 ⊆ Fin ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ω) → {𝑏 ∈ 𝑋 ∣ 𝑏 ≼ 𝐴} ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem10 10354 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. A nonempty finite union of members of a chain is a member of the chain. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ Fin ∧ [⊊] Or 𝐴) → ∪ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem11 10355* | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) |
⊢ (( [⊊] Or 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ Fin) → ran (𝑏 ∈ ω ↦ ∪ {𝑐 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝑐 ≼ 𝑏}) = (𝐴 ∪ {∅})) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem12 10356 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ 𝒫 𝐵 ∧ [⊊] Or 𝐴 ∧ ¬ ∪ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (𝐴 ⊆ Fin ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅)) → ¬ 𝐵 ∈ FinIII) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2lem13 10357 | Lemma for fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ 𝒫 𝐵 ∧ [⊊] Or 𝐴 ∧ ¬ ∪ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ (¬ 𝐶 ∈ Fin ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴)) → ¬ (𝐵 ∖ 𝐶) ∈ FinII) | ||
Theorem | fin12 10358 | Weak theorem which skips Ia but has a trivial proof, needed to prove fin1a2 10360. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ Fin → 𝐴 ∈ FinII) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2s 10359* | An II-infinite set can have an I-infinite part broken off and remain II-infinite. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝒫 𝐴(𝑥 ∈ Fin ∨ (𝐴 ∖ 𝑥) ∈ FinII)) → 𝐴 ∈ FinII) | ||
Theorem | fin1a2 10360 | Every Ia-finite set is II-finite. Theorem 1 of [Levy58], p. 3. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 8-Nov-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 17-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ FinIa → 𝐴 ∈ FinII) | ||
Theorem | itunifval 10361* | Function value of iterated unions. EDITORIAL: The iterated unions and order types of ordered sets are split out here because they could conceivably be independently useful. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑈‘𝐴) = (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝐴) ↾ ω)) | ||
Theorem | itunifn 10362* | Functionality of the iterated union. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝑈‘𝐴) Fn ω) | ||
Theorem | ituni0 10363* | A zero-fold iterated union. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ((𝑈‘𝐴)‘∅) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | itunisuc 10364* | Successor iterated union. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑈‘𝐴)‘suc 𝐵) = ∪ ((𝑈‘𝐴)‘𝐵) | ||
Theorem | itunitc1 10365* | Each union iterate is a member of the transitive closure. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑈‘𝐴)‘𝐵) ⊆ (TC‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | itunitc 10366* | The union of all union iterates creates the transitive closure; compare trcl 9673. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) ⇒ ⊢ (TC‘𝐴) = ∪ ran (𝑈‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ituniiun 10367* | Unwrap an iterated union from the "other end". (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ((𝑈‘𝐴)‘suc 𝐵) = ∪ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝑈‘𝑎)‘𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem7 10368* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. Properties of the recurrent sequence of ordinals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ (har‘𝒫 (𝑋 × 𝑧))), (har‘𝒫 𝑋)) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐻‘∅) = (har‘𝒫 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem8 10369* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. Properties of the recurrent sequence of ordinals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ (har‘𝒫 (𝑋 × 𝑧))), (har‘𝒫 𝑋)) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑎 ∈ ω → (𝐻‘suc 𝑎) = (har‘𝒫 (𝑋 × (𝐻‘𝑎)))) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem9 10370* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. Properties of the recurrent sequence of ordinals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ (har‘𝒫 (𝑋 × 𝑧))), (har‘𝒫 𝑋)) ↾ ω) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑎 ∈ ω → (𝐻‘𝑎) ∈ On) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem1 10371 | Lemma for hsmex 10377. Bound the order type of a limited-cardinality set of ordinals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑂 = OrdIso( E , 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ On ∧ 𝐴 ≼* 𝐵) → dom 𝑂 ∈ (har‘𝒫 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem2 10372* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. Bound the order type of a union of sets of ordinals, each of limited order type. Vaguely reminiscent of unictb 10520 but use of order types allows to canonically choose the sub-bijections, removing the choice requirement. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) (Revised by AV, 18-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = OrdIso( E , 𝐵) & ⊢ 𝐺 = OrdIso( E , ∪ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ On ∧ ∀𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐵 ∈ 𝒫 On ∧ dom 𝐹 ∈ 𝐶)) → dom 𝐺 ∈ (har‘𝒫 (𝐴 × 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem3 10373* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. Clear 𝐼 hypothesis and extend previous result by dominance. Note that this could be substantially strengthened, e.g., using the weak Hartogs function, but all we need here is that there be *some* dominating ordinal. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = OrdIso( E , 𝐵) & ⊢ 𝐺 = OrdIso( E , ∪ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ≼* 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ On) ∧ ∀𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐵 ∈ 𝒫 On ∧ dom 𝐹 ∈ 𝐶)) → dom 𝐺 ∈ (har‘𝒫 (𝐷 × 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem4 10374* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. The core induction, establishing bounds on the order types of iterated unions of the initial set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐻 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ (har‘𝒫 (𝑋 × 𝑧))), (har‘𝒫 𝑋)) ↾ ω) & ⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑎 ∈ ∪ (𝑅1 “ On) ∣ ∀𝑏 ∈ (TC‘{𝑎})𝑏 ≼ 𝑋} & ⊢ 𝑂 = OrdIso( E , (rank “ ((𝑈‘𝑑)‘𝑐))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑐 ∈ ω ∧ 𝑑 ∈ 𝑆) → dom 𝑂 ∈ (𝐻‘𝑐)) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem5 10375* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. Combining the above constraints, along with itunitc 10366 and tcrank 9829, gives an effective constraint on the rank of 𝑆. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐻 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ (har‘𝒫 (𝑋 × 𝑧))), (har‘𝒫 𝑋)) ↾ ω) & ⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑎 ∈ ∪ (𝑅1 “ On) ∣ ∀𝑏 ∈ (TC‘{𝑎})𝑏 ≼ 𝑋} & ⊢ 𝑂 = OrdIso( E , (rank “ ((𝑈‘𝑑)‘𝑐))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝑑 ∈ 𝑆 → (rank‘𝑑) ∈ (har‘𝒫 (ω × ∪ ran 𝐻))) | ||
Theorem | hsmexlem6 10376* | Lemma for hsmex 10377. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐻 = (rec((𝑧 ∈ V ↦ (har‘𝒫 (𝑋 × 𝑧))), (har‘𝒫 𝑋)) ↾ ω) & ⊢ 𝑈 = (𝑥 ∈ V ↦ (rec((𝑦 ∈ V ↦ ∪ 𝑦), 𝑥) ↾ ω)) & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑎 ∈ ∪ (𝑅1 “ On) ∣ ∀𝑏 ∈ (TC‘{𝑎})𝑏 ≼ 𝑋} & ⊢ 𝑂 = OrdIso( E , (rank “ ((𝑈‘𝑑)‘𝑐))) ⇒ ⊢ 𝑆 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | hsmex 10377* | The collection of hereditarily size-limited well-founded sets comprise a set. The proof is that of Randall Holmes at http://math.boisestate.edu/~holmes/holmes/hereditary.pdf, with modifications to use Hartogs' theorem instead of the weak variant (inconsequentially weakening some intermediate results), and making the well-foundedness condition explicit to avoid a direct dependence on ax-reg 9537. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑠 ∈ ∪ (𝑅1 “ On) ∣ ∀𝑥 ∈ (TC‘{𝑠})𝑥 ≼ 𝑋} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | hsmex2 10378* | The set of hereditary size-limited sets, assuming ax-reg 9537. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑠 ∣ ∀𝑥 ∈ (TC‘{𝑠})𝑥 ≼ 𝑋} ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | hsmex3 10379* | The set of hereditary size-limited sets, assuming ax-reg 9537, using strict comparison (an easy corollary by separation). (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Feb-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑠 ∣ ∀𝑥 ∈ (TC‘{𝑠})𝑥 ≺ 𝑋} ∈ V) | ||
In this section we add the Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10404, as well as weaker forms such as the axiom of countable choice ax-cc 10380 and dependent choice ax-dc 10391. We introduce these weaker forms so that theorems that do not need the full power of the axiom of choice, but need more than simple ZF, can use these intermediate axioms instead. The combination of the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms and the axiom of choice is often abbreviated as ZFC. The axiom of choice is widely accepted, and ZFC is the most commonly-accepted fundamental set of axioms for mathematics. However, there have been and still are some lingering controversies about the Axiom of Choice. The axiom of choice does not satisfy those who wish to have a constructive proof (e.g., it will not satisfy intuitionistic logic). Thus, we make it easy to identify which proofs depend on the axiom of choice or its weaker forms. | ||
Axiom | ax-cc 10380* | The axiom of countable choice (CC), also known as the axiom of denumerable choice. It is clearly a special case of ac5 10422, but is weak enough that it can be proven using DC (see axcc 10403). It is, however, strictly stronger than ZF and cannot be proven in ZF. It states that any countable collection of nonempty sets must have a choice function. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ≈ ω → ∃𝑓∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑧 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑧) ∈ 𝑧)) | ||
Theorem | axcc2lem 10381* | Lemma for axcc2 10382. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐾 = (𝑛 ∈ ω ↦ if((𝐹‘𝑛) = ∅, {∅}, (𝐹‘𝑛))) & ⊢ 𝐴 = (𝑛 ∈ ω ↦ ({𝑛} × (𝐾‘𝑛))) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑛 ∈ ω ↦ (2nd ‘(𝑓‘(𝐴‘𝑛)))) ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑔(𝑔 Fn ω ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ ω ((𝐹‘𝑛) ≠ ∅ → (𝑔‘𝑛) ∈ (𝐹‘𝑛))) | ||
Theorem | axcc2 10382* | A possibly more useful version of ax-cc using sequences instead of countable sets. The Axiom of Infinity is needed to prove this, and indeed this implies the Axiom of Infinity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ ∃𝑔(𝑔 Fn ω ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ ω ((𝐹‘𝑛) ≠ ∅ → (𝑔‘𝑛) ∈ (𝐹‘𝑛))) | ||
Theorem | axcc3 10383* | A possibly more useful version of ax-cc 10380 using sequences 𝐹(𝑛) instead of countable sets. The Axiom of Infinity is needed to prove this, and indeed this implies the Axiom of Infinity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 8-Feb-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Dec-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐹 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑁 ≈ ω ⇒ ⊢ ∃𝑓(𝑓 Fn 𝑁 ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ 𝑁 (𝐹 ≠ ∅ → (𝑓‘𝑛) ∈ 𝐹)) | ||
Theorem | axcc4 10384* | A version of axcc3 10383 that uses wffs instead of classes. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 7-Apr-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑁 ≈ ω & ⊢ (𝑥 = (𝑓‘𝑛) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑛 ∈ 𝑁 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 → ∃𝑓(𝑓:𝑁⟶𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ 𝑁 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | acncc 10385 | An ax-cc 10380 equivalent: every set has choice sets of length ω. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Aug-2015.) |
⊢ AC ω = V | ||
Theorem | axcc4dom 10386* | Relax the constraint on axcc4 10384 to dominance instead of equinumerosity. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jan-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = (𝑓‘𝑛) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ≼ ω ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ 𝑁 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) → ∃𝑓(𝑓:𝑁⟶𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑛 ∈ 𝑁 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | domtriomlem 10387* | Lemma for domtriom 10388. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 = {𝑦 ∣ (𝑦 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ≈ 𝒫 𝑛)} & ⊢ 𝐶 = (𝑛 ∈ ω ↦ ((𝑏‘𝑛) ∖ ∪ 𝑘 ∈ 𝑛 (𝑏‘𝑘))) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin → ω ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | domtriom 10388 | Trichotomy of equinumerosity for ω, proven using countable choice. Equivalently, all Dedekind-finite sets (as in isfin4-2 10259) are finite in the usual sense and conversely. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 ↔ ¬ 𝐴 ≺ ω) | ||
Theorem | fin41 10389 | Under countable choice, the IV-finite sets (Dedekind-finite) coincide with I-finite (finite in the usual sense) sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 16-May-2015.) |
⊢ FinIV = Fin | ||
Theorem | dominf 10390 | A nonempty set that is a subset of its union is infinite. This version is proved from ax-cc 10380. See dominfac 10518 for a version proved from ax-ac 10404. The axiom of Regularity is used for this proof, via inf3lem6 9578, and its use is necessary: otherwise the set 𝐴 = {𝐴} or 𝐴 = {∅, 𝐴} (where the second example even has nonempty well-founded part) provides a counterexample. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ ∪ 𝐴) → ω ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Axiom | ax-dc 10391* | Dependent Choice. Axiom DC1 of [Schechter] p. 149. This theorem is weaker than the Axiom of Choice but is stronger than Countable Choice. It shows the existence of a sequence whose values can only be shown to exist (but cannot be constructed explicitly) and also depend on earlier values in the sequence. Dependent choice is equivalent to the statement that every (nonempty) pruned tree has a branch. This axiom is redundant in ZFC; see axdc 10466. But ZF+DC is strictly weaker than ZF+AC, so this axiom provides for theorems that do not need the full power of AC. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ((∃𝑦∃𝑧 𝑦𝑥𝑧 ∧ ran 𝑥 ⊆ dom 𝑥) → ∃𝑓∀𝑛 ∈ ω (𝑓‘𝑛)𝑥(𝑓‘suc 𝑛)) | ||
Theorem | dcomex 10392 | The Axiom of Dependent Choice implies Infinity, the way we have stated it. Thus, we have Inf+AC implies DC and DC implies Inf, but AC does not imply Inf. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ ω ∈ V | ||
Theorem | axdc2lem 10393* | Lemma for axdc2 10394. We construct a relation 𝑅 based on 𝐹 such that 𝑥𝑅𝑦 iff 𝑦 ∈ (𝐹‘𝑥), and show that the "function" described by ax-dc 10391 can be restricted so that it is a real function (since the stated properties only show that it is the superset of a function). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 26-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑅 = {〈𝑥, 𝑦〉 ∣ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐹‘𝑥))} & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ ω ↦ (ℎ‘𝑥)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝒫 𝐴 ∖ {∅})) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:ω⟶𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ ω (𝑔‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑔‘𝑘)))) | ||
Theorem | axdc2 10394* | An apparent strengthening of ax-dc 10391 (but derived from it) which shows that there is a denumerable sequence 𝑔 for any function that maps elements of a set 𝐴 to nonempty subsets of 𝐴 such that 𝑔(𝑥 + 1) ∈ 𝐹(𝑔(𝑥)) for all 𝑥 ∈ ω. The finitistic version of this can be proven by induction, but the infinite version requires this new axiom. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 25-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝒫 𝐴 ∖ {∅})) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:ω⟶𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ ω (𝑔‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑔‘𝑘)))) | ||
Theorem | axdc3lem 10395* | The class 𝑆 of finite approximations to the DC sequence is a set. (We derive here the stronger statement that 𝑆 is a subset of a specific set, namely 𝒫 (ω × 𝐴).) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Jan-2013.) Remove unnecessary distinct variable conditions. (Revised by David Abernethy, 18-Mar-2014.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑠 ∣ ∃𝑛 ∈ ω (𝑠:suc 𝑛⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑠‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ 𝑛 (𝑠‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑠‘𝑘)))} ⇒ ⊢ 𝑆 ∈ V | ||
Theorem | axdc3lem2 10396* | Lemma for axdc3 10399. We have constructed a "candidate set" 𝑆, which consists of all finite sequences 𝑠 that satisfy our property of interest, namely 𝑠(𝑥 + 1) ∈ 𝐹(𝑠(𝑥)) on its domain, but with the added constraint that 𝑠(0) = 𝐶. These sets are possible "initial segments" of the infinite sequence satisfying these constraints, but we can leverage the standard ax-dc 10391 (with no initial condition) to select a sequence of ever-lengthening finite sequences, namely (ℎ‘𝑛):𝑚⟶𝐴 (for some integer 𝑚). We let our "choice" function select a sequence whose domain is one more than the last one, and agrees with the previous one on its domain. Thus, the application of vanilla ax-dc 10391 yields a sequence of sequences whose domains increase without bound, and whose union is a function which has all the properties we want. In this lemma, we show that given the sequence ℎ, we can construct the sequence 𝑔 that we are after. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑠 ∣ ∃𝑛 ∈ ω (𝑠:suc 𝑛⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑠‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ 𝑛 (𝑠‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑠‘𝑘)))} & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ {𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∣ (dom 𝑦 = suc dom 𝑥 ∧ (𝑦 ↾ dom 𝑥) = 𝑥)}) ⇒ ⊢ (∃ℎ(ℎ:ω⟶𝑆 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ ω (ℎ‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐺‘(ℎ‘𝑘))) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:ω⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑔‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ ω (𝑔‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑔‘𝑘)))) | ||
Theorem | axdc3lem3 10397* | Simple substitution lemma for axdc3 10399. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑠 ∣ ∃𝑛 ∈ ω (𝑠:suc 𝑛⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑠‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ 𝑛 (𝑠‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑠‘𝑘)))} & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑆 ↔ ∃𝑚 ∈ ω (𝐵:suc 𝑚⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝐵‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ 𝑚 (𝐵‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝐵‘𝑘)))) | ||
Theorem | axdc3lem4 10398* | Lemma for axdc3 10399. We have constructed a "candidate set" 𝑆, which consists of all finite sequences 𝑠 that satisfy our property of interest, namely 𝑠(𝑥 + 1) ∈ 𝐹(𝑠(𝑥)) on its domain, but with the added constraint that 𝑠(0) = 𝐶. These sets are possible "initial segments" of the infinite sequence satisfying these constraints, but we can leverage the standard ax-dc 10391 (with no initial condition) to select a sequence of ever-lengthening finite sequences, namely (ℎ‘𝑛):𝑚⟶𝐴 (for some integer 𝑚). We let our "choice" function select a sequence whose domain is one more than the last one, and agrees with the previous one on its domain. Thus, the application of vanilla ax-dc 10391 yields a sequence of sequences whose domains increase without bound, and whose union is a function which has all the properties we want. In this lemma, we show that 𝑆 is nonempty, and that 𝐺 always maps to a nonempty subset of 𝑆, so that we can apply axdc2 10394. See axdc3lem2 10396 for the rest of the proof. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 = {𝑠 ∣ ∃𝑛 ∈ ω (𝑠:suc 𝑛⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑠‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ 𝑛 (𝑠‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑠‘𝑘)))} & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ↦ {𝑦 ∈ 𝑆 ∣ (dom 𝑦 = suc dom 𝑥 ∧ (𝑦 ↾ dom 𝑥) = 𝑥)}) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝒫 𝐴 ∖ {∅})) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:ω⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑔‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ ω (𝑔‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑔‘𝑘)))) | ||
Theorem | axdc3 10399* | Dependent Choice. Axiom DC1 of [Schechter] p. 149, with the addition of an initial value 𝐶. This theorem is weaker than the Axiom of Choice but is stronger than Countable Choice. It shows the existence of a sequence whose values can only be shown to exist (but cannot be constructed explicitly) and also depend on earlier values in the sequence. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 27-Jan-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹:𝐴⟶(𝒫 𝐴 ∖ {∅})) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:ω⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑔‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ ω (𝑔‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝐹‘(𝑔‘𝑘)))) | ||
Theorem | axdc4lem 10400* | Lemma for axdc4 10401. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 31-Jan-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 16-Nov-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝑛 ∈ ω, 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ ({suc 𝑛} × (𝑛𝐹𝑥))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐹:(ω × 𝐴)⟶(𝒫 𝐴 ∖ {∅})) → ∃𝑔(𝑔:ω⟶𝐴 ∧ (𝑔‘∅) = 𝐶 ∧ ∀𝑘 ∈ ω (𝑔‘suc 𝑘) ∈ (𝑘𝐹(𝑔‘𝑘)))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |