![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 107 of 489) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30950) |
![]() (30951-32473) |
![]() (32474-48899) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | brdom6disj 10601* | An equivalence to a dominance relation for disjoint sets. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-2007.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) = ∅ ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑓(∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∃*𝑦{𝑥, 𝑦} ∈ 𝑓 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 {𝑦, 𝑥} ∈ 𝑓)) | ||
Theorem | fin71ac 10602 | Once we allow AC, the "strongest" definition of finite set becomes equivalent to the "weakest" and the entire hierarchy collapses. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 29-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ FinVII = Fin | ||
Theorem | imadomg 10603 | An image of a function under a set is dominated by the set. Proposition 10.34 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 92. (Contributed by NM, 23-Jul-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (Fun 𝐹 → (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ≼ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fimact 10604 | The image by a function of a countable set is countable. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 27-Mar-2018.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ Fun 𝐹) → (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | fnrndomg 10605 | The range of a function is dominated by its domain. (Contributed by NM, 1-Sep-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐹 Fn 𝐴 → ran 𝐹 ≼ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fnct 10606 | If the domain of a function is countable, the function is countable. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 29-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ≼ ω) → 𝐹 ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | mptct 10607* | A countable mapping set is countable. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 29-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≼ ω → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ 𝐵) ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | iunfo 10608* | Existence of an onto function from a disjoint union to a union. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 24-Jun-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jan-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (2nd ↾ 𝑇):𝑇–onto→∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 | ||
Theorem | iundom2g 10609* | An upper bound for the cardinality of a disjoint indexed union, with explicit choice principles. 𝐵 depends on 𝑥 and should be thought of as 𝐵(𝑥). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐶 ↑m 𝐵) ∈ AC 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≼ 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | iundomg 10610* | An upper bound for the cardinality of an indexed union, with explicit choice principles. 𝐵 depends on 𝑥 and should be thought of as 𝐵(𝑥). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ({𝑥} × 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐶 ↑m 𝐵) ∈ AC 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≼ 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 × 𝐶) ∈ AC ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | iundom 10611* | An upper bound for the cardinality of an indexed union. 𝐶 depends on 𝑥 and should be thought of as 𝐶(𝑥). (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2006.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ≼ 𝐵) → ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐶 ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | unidom 10612* | An upper bound for the cardinality of a union. Theorem 10.47 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 98. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2006.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 1-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ≼ 𝐵) → ∪ 𝐴 ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | uniimadom 10613* | An upper bound for the cardinality of the union of an image. Theorem 10.48 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 99. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2006.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ≼ 𝐵) → ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | uniimadomf 10614* | An upper bound for the cardinality of the union of an image. Theorem 10.48 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 99. This version of uniimadom 10613 uses a bound-variable hypothesis in place of a distinct variable condition. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2006.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐹 & ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝐹‘𝑥) ≼ 𝐵) → ∪ (𝐹 “ 𝐴) ≼ (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardval 10615* | The value of the cardinal number function. Definition 10.4 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 85. See cardval2 10060 for a simpler version of its value. (Contributed by NM, 21-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (card‘𝐴) = ∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝑥 ≈ 𝐴} | ||
Theorem | cardid 10616 | Any set is equinumerous to its cardinal number. Proposition 10.5 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 85. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 28-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (card‘𝐴) ≈ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | cardidg 10617 | Any set is equinumerous to its cardinal number. Closed theorem form of cardid 10616. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (card‘𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cardidd 10618 | Any set is equinumerous to its cardinal number. Deduction form of cardid 10616. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (card‘𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cardf 10619 | The cardinality function is a function with domain the well-orderable sets. Assuming AC, this is the universe. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Jun-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 13-Sep-2013.) |
⊢ card:V⟶On | ||
Theorem | carden 10620 |
Two sets are equinumerous iff their cardinal numbers are equal. This
important theorem expresses the essential concept behind
"cardinality" or
"size". This theorem appears as Proposition 10.10 of [TakeutiZaring]
p. 85, Theorem 7P of [Enderton] p. 197,
and Theorem 9 of [Suppes] p. 242
(among others). The Axiom of Choice is required for its proof. Related
theorems are hasheni 14397 and the finite-set-only hashen 14396.
This theorem is also known as Hume's Principle. Gottlob Frege's two-volume Grundgesetze der Arithmetik used his Basic Law V to prove this theorem. Unfortunately Basic Law V caused Frege's system to be inconsistent because it was subject to Russell's paradox (see ru 3802). Later scholars have found that Frege primarily used Basic Law V to Hume's Principle. If Basic Law V is replaced by Hume's Principle in Frege's system, much of Frege's work is restored. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, once Basic Law V is replaced, proves "Frege's theorem" (the Peano axioms of arithmetic can be derived in second-order logic from Hume's principle). See https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/frege-theorem 3802. We take a different approach, using first-order logic and ZFC, to prove the Peano axioms of arithmetic. The theory of cardinality can also be developed without AC by introducing "card" as a primitive notion and stating this theorem as an axiom, as is done with the axiom for cardinal numbers in [Suppes] p. 111. Finally, if we allow the Axiom of Regularity, we can avoid AC by defining the cardinal number of a set as the set of all sets equinumerous to it and having the least possible rank (see karden 9964). (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) → ((card‘𝐴) = (card‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardeq0 10621 | Only the empty set has cardinality zero. (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ((card‘𝐴) = ∅ ↔ 𝐴 = ∅)) | ||
Theorem | unsnen 10622 | Equinumerosity of a set with a new element added. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2008.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝐴 ∪ {𝐵}) ≈ suc (card‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | carddom 10623 | Two sets have the dominance relationship iff their cardinalities have the subset relationship. Equation i of [Quine] p. 232. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → ((card‘𝐴) ⊆ (card‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≼ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | cardsdom 10624 | Two sets have the strict dominance relationship iff their cardinalities have the membership relationship. Corollary 19.7(2) of [Eisenberg] p. 310. (Contributed by NM, 22-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → ((card‘𝐴) ∈ (card‘𝐵) ↔ 𝐴 ≺ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | domtri 10625 | Trichotomy law for dominance and strict dominance. This theorem is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ↔ ¬ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | entric 10626 | Trichotomy of equinumerosity and strict dominance. This theorem is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. Theorem 8 of [Suppes] p. 242. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | entri2 10627 | Trichotomy of dominance and strict dominance. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | entri3 10628 | Trichotomy of dominance. This theorem is equivalent to the Axiom of Choice. Part of Proposition 4.42(d) of [Mendelson] p. 275. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑊) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | sdomsdomcard 10629 | A set strictly dominates iff its cardinal strictly dominates. (Contributed by NM, 30-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ≺ (card‘𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | canth3 10630 | Cantor's theorem in terms of cardinals. This theorem tells us that no matter how large a cardinal number is, there is a still larger cardinal number. Theorem 18.12 of [Monk1] p. 133. (Contributed by NM, 5-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (card‘𝐴) ∈ (card‘𝒫 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | infxpidm 10631 | Every infinite class is equinumerous to its Cartesian square. This theorem, which is equivalent to the axiom of choice over ZF, provides the basis for infinite cardinal arithmetic. Proposition 10.40 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 95. This is a corollary of infxpen 10083 (used via infxpidm2 10086). (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (ω ≼ 𝐴 → (𝐴 × 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ondomon 10632* | The class of ordinals dominated by a given set is an ordinal. Theorem 56 of [Suppes] p. 227. This theorem can be proved without the axiom of choice, see hartogs 9613. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2003.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) Use hartogs 9613 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝑥 ≼ 𝐴} ∈ On) | ||
Theorem | cardmin 10633* | The smallest ordinal that strictly dominates a set is a cardinal. (Contributed by NM, 28-Oct-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 20-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (card‘∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝐴 ≺ 𝑥}) = ∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝐴 ≺ 𝑥}) | ||
Theorem | ficard 10634 | A set is finite iff its cardinal is a natural number. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ Fin ↔ (card‘𝐴) ∈ ω)) | ||
Theorem | infinf 10635 | Equivalence between two infiniteness criteria for sets. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin ↔ ω ≼ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | unirnfdomd 10636 | The union of the range of a function from an infinite set into the class of finite sets is dominated by its domain. Deduction form. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹:𝑇⟶Fin) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑇 ∈ Fin) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 ∈ 𝑉) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∪ ran 𝐹 ≼ 𝑇) | ||
Theorem | konigthlem 10637* | Lemma for konigth 10638. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 = ∪ 𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑀‘𝑖) & ⊢ 𝑃 = X𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑁‘𝑖) & ⊢ 𝐷 = (𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝑎 ∈ (𝑀‘𝑖) ↦ ((𝑓‘𝑎)‘𝑖))) & ⊢ 𝐸 = (𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 ↦ (𝑒‘𝑖)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑀‘𝑖) ≺ (𝑁‘𝑖) → 𝑆 ≺ 𝑃) | ||
Theorem | konigth 10638* | Konig's Theorem. If 𝑚(𝑖) ≺ 𝑛(𝑖) for all 𝑖 ∈ 𝐴, then Σ𝑖 ∈ 𝐴𝑚(𝑖) ≺ ∏𝑖 ∈ 𝐴𝑛(𝑖), where the sums and products stand in for disjoint union and infinite cartesian product. The version here is proven with unions rather than disjoint unions for convenience, but the version with disjoint unions is clearly a special case of this version. The Axiom of Choice is needed for this proof, but it contains AC as a simple corollary (letting 𝑚(𝑖) = ∅, this theorem says that an infinite cartesian product of nonempty sets is nonempty), so this is an AC equivalent. Theorem 11.26 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 107. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 22-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝑆 = ∪ 𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑀‘𝑖) & ⊢ 𝑃 = X𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑁‘𝑖) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑖 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑀‘𝑖) ≺ (𝑁‘𝑖) → 𝑆 ≺ 𝑃) | ||
Theorem | alephsucpw 10639 | The power set of an aleph dominates the successor aleph. (The Generalized Continuum Hypothesis says they are equinumerous, see gch3 10745 or gchaleph2 10741.) (Contributed by NM, 27-Aug-2005.) |
⊢ (ℵ‘suc 𝐴) ≼ 𝒫 (ℵ‘𝐴) | ||
Theorem | aleph1 10640 | The set exponentiation of 2 to the aleph-zero has cardinality of at least aleph-one. (If we were to assume the Continuum Hypothesis, their cardinalities would be the same.) (Contributed by NM, 7-Jul-2004.) |
⊢ (ℵ‘1o) ≼ (2o ↑m (ℵ‘∅)) | ||
Theorem | alephval2 10641* | An alternate way to express the value of the aleph function for nonzero arguments. Theorem 64 of [Suppes] p. 229. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ ∅ ∈ 𝐴) → (ℵ‘𝐴) = ∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (ℵ‘𝑦) ≺ 𝑥}) | ||
Theorem | dominfac 10642 | A nonempty set that is a subset of its union is infinite. This version is proved from ax-ac 10528. See dominf 10514 for a version proved from ax-cc 10504. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-2007.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ ∪ 𝐴) → ω ≼ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | iunctb 10643* | The countable union of countable sets is countable (indexed union version of unictb 10644). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 18-Jan-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≼ ω) → ∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | unictb 10644* | The countable union of countable sets is countable. Theorem 6Q of [Enderton] p. 159. See iunctb 10643 for indexed union version. (Contributed by NM, 26-Mar-2006.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≼ ω ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 ≼ ω) → ∪ 𝐴 ≼ ω) | ||
Theorem | infmap 10645* | An exponentiation law for infinite cardinals. Similar to Lemma 6.2 of [Jech] p. 43. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2004.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((ω ≼ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴) → (𝐴 ↑m 𝐵) ≈ {𝑥 ∣ (𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑥 ≈ 𝐵)}) | ||
Theorem | alephadd 10646 | The sum of two alephs is their maximum. Equation 6.1 of [Jech] p. 42. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((ℵ‘𝐴) ⊔ (ℵ‘𝐵)) ≈ ((ℵ‘𝐴) ∪ (ℵ‘𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | alephmul 10647 | The product of two alephs is their maximum. Equation 6.1 of [Jech] p. 42. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → ((ℵ‘𝐴) × (ℵ‘𝐵)) ≈ ((ℵ‘𝐴) ∪ (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephexp1 10648 | An exponentiation law for alephs. Lemma 6.1 of [Jech] p. 42. (Contributed by NM, 29-Sep-2004.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 30-Apr-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) ∧ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵) → ((ℵ‘𝐴) ↑m (ℵ‘𝐵)) ≈ (2o ↑m (ℵ‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | alephsuc3 10649* | An alternate representation of a successor aleph. Compare alephsuc 10137 and alephsuc2 10149. Equality can be obtained by taking the card of the right-hand side then using alephcard 10139 and carden 10620. (Contributed by NM, 23-Oct-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (ℵ‘suc 𝐴) ≈ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝑥 ≈ (ℵ‘𝐴)}) | ||
Theorem | alephexp2 10650* | An expression equinumerous to 2 to an aleph power. The proof equates the two laws for cardinal exponentiation alephexp1 10648 (which works if the base is less than or equal to the exponent) and infmap 10645 (which works if the exponent is less than or equal to the base). They can be equated only when the base is equal to the exponent, and this is the result. (Contributed by NM, 23-Oct-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (2o ↑m (ℵ‘𝐴)) ≈ {𝑥 ∣ (𝑥 ⊆ (ℵ‘𝐴) ∧ 𝑥 ≈ (ℵ‘𝐴))}) | ||
Theorem | alephreg 10651 | A successor aleph is regular. Theorem 11.15 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 103. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 9-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (cf‘(ℵ‘suc 𝐴)) = (ℵ‘suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pwcfsdom 10652* | A corollary of Konig's Theorem konigth 10638. Theorem 11.28 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 108. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐻 = (𝑦 ∈ (cf‘(ℵ‘𝐴)) ↦ (har‘(𝑓‘𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ (ℵ‘𝐴) ≺ ((ℵ‘𝐴) ↑m (cf‘(ℵ‘𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | cfpwsdom 10653 | A corollary of Konig's Theorem konigth 10638. Theorem 11.29 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 108. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 20-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (2o ≼ 𝐵 → (ℵ‘𝐴) ≺ (cf‘(card‘(𝐵 ↑m (ℵ‘𝐴))))) | ||
Theorem | alephom 10654 | From canth2 9196, we know that (ℵ‘0) < (2↑ω), but we cannot prove that (2↑ω) = (ℵ‘1) (this is the Continuum Hypothesis), nor can we prove that it is less than any bound whatsoever (i.e. the statement (ℵ‘𝐴) < (2↑ω) is consistent for any ordinal 𝐴). However, we can prove that (2↑ω) is not equal to (ℵ‘ω), nor (ℵ‘(ℵ‘ω)), on cofinality grounds, because by Konig's Theorem konigth 10638 (in the form of cfpwsdom 10653), (2↑ω) has uncountable cofinality, which eliminates limit alephs like (ℵ‘ω). (The first limit aleph that is not eliminated is (ℵ‘(ℵ‘1)), which has cofinality (ℵ‘1).) (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 21-Mar-2013.) |
⊢ (card‘(2o ↑m ω)) ≠ (ℵ‘ω) | ||
Theorem | smobeth 10655 | The beth function is strictly monotone. This function is not strictly the beth function, but rather bethA is the same as (card‘(𝑅1‘(ω +o 𝐴))), since conventionally we start counting at the first infinite level, and ignore the finite levels. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 6-Jun-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 2-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ Smo (card ∘ 𝑅1) | ||
Theorem | nd1 10656 | A lemma for proving conditionless ZFC axioms. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑦 ∈ 𝑧) | ||
Theorem | nd2 10657 | A lemma for proving conditionless ZFC axioms. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | nd3 10658 | A lemma for proving conditionless ZFC axioms. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ¬ ∀𝑧 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | nd4 10659 | A lemma for proving conditionless ZFC axioms. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ¬ ∀𝑧 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | axextnd 10660 | A version of the Axiom of Extensionality with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 14-Aug-2003.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥((𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 = 𝑧) | ||
Theorem | axrepndlem1 10661* | Lemma for the Axiom of Replacement with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑧 → ∃𝑥(∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑)))) | ||
Theorem | axrepndlem2 10662 | Lemma for the Axiom of Replacement with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 6-Dec-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (((¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 ∧ ¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑧) ∧ ¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑧) → ∃𝑥(∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑)))) | ||
Theorem | axrepnd 10663 | A version of the Axiom of Replacement with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥(∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∀𝑧(∀𝑦 𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ ∃𝑥(∀𝑧 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | axunndlem1 10664* | Lemma for the Axiom of Union with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥∀𝑦(∃𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | axunnd 10665 | A version of the Axiom of Union with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥∀𝑦(∃𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | axpowndlem1 10666 | Lemma for the Axiom of Power Sets with no distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦(∀𝑥(∃𝑧 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | axpowndlem2 10667* | Lemma for the Axiom of Power Sets with no distinct variable conditions. Revised to remove a redundant antecedent from the consequence. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 6-Dec-2016.) (Revised and shortened by Wolf Lammen, 9-Jun-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → (¬ ∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑧 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦(∀𝑥(∃𝑧 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | axpowndlem3 10668* | Lemma for the Axiom of Power Sets with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 10-Dec-2016.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 10-Jun-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦(∀𝑥(∃𝑧 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | axpowndlem4 10669 | Lemma for the Axiom of Power Sets with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Dec-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥 → (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑧 → (¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦(∀𝑥(∃𝑧 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥)))) | ||
Theorem | axpownd 10670 | A version of the Axiom of Power Sets with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 4-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦(∀𝑥(∃𝑧 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∀𝑦 𝑥 ∈ 𝑧) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | axregndlem1 10671 | Lemma for the Axiom of Regularity with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑧 → (𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦)))) | ||
Theorem | axregndlem2 10672* | Lemma for the Axiom of Regularity with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Dec-2016.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | axregnd 10673 | A version of the Axiom of Regularity with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 18-Aug-2019.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 → ∃𝑥(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | axinfndlem1 10674* | Lemma for the Axiom of Infinity with no distinct variable conditions. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 → ∃𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 → ∃𝑧(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑥)))) | ||
Theorem | axinfnd 10675 | A version of the Axiom of Infinity with no distinct variable conditions. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by NM, 5-Jan-2002.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 → (𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 → ∃𝑧(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑥)))) | ||
Theorem | axacndlem1 10676 | Lemma for the Axiom of Choice with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑦 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) → ∃𝑤∀𝑦(∃𝑤((𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) ∧ (𝑦 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥)) ↔ 𝑦 = 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | axacndlem2 10677 | Lemma for the Axiom of Choice with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 𝑥 = 𝑧 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) → ∃𝑤∀𝑦(∃𝑤((𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) ∧ (𝑦 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥)) ↔ 𝑦 = 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | axacndlem3 10678 | Lemma for the Axiom of Choice with no distinct variable conditions. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑧 → ∃𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) → ∃𝑤∀𝑦(∃𝑤((𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) ∧ (𝑦 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥)) ↔ 𝑦 = 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | axacndlem4 10679* | Lemma for the Axiom of Choice with no distinct variable conditions. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by NM, 8-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) → ∃𝑤∀𝑦(∃𝑤((𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) ∧ (𝑦 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥)) ↔ 𝑦 = 𝑤)) | ||
Theorem | axacndlem5 10680* | Lemma for the Axiom of Choice with no distinct variable conditions. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) → ∃𝑤∀𝑦(∃𝑤((𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) ∧ (𝑦 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥)) ↔ 𝑦 = 𝑤)) | ||
Theorem | axacnd 10681 | A version of the Axiom of Choice with no distinct variable conditions. (New usage is discouraged.) (Contributed by NM, 3-Jan-2002.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥∀𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑥(𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) → ∃𝑤∀𝑦(∃𝑤((𝑦 ∈ 𝑧 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑤) ∧ (𝑦 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥)) ↔ 𝑦 = 𝑤)) | ||
Theorem | zfcndext 10682* | Axiom of Extensionality ax-ext 2711, reproved from conditionless ZFC version and predicate calculus. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑥 = 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | zfcndrep 10683* | Axiom of Replacement ax-rep 5303, reproved from conditionless ZFC axioms. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∀𝑤∃𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑦𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝑦) → ∃𝑦∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 ↔ ∃𝑤(𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | zfcndun 10684* | Axiom of Union ax-un 7770, reproved from conditionless ZFC axioms. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑦∀𝑧(∃𝑤(𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | zfcndpow 10685* | Axiom of Power Sets ax-pow 5383, reproved from conditionless ZFC axioms. The proof uses the "Axiom of Twoness" dtru 5456. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑦∀𝑧(∀𝑤(𝑤 ∈ 𝑧 → 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | zfcndreg 10686* | Axiom of Regularity ax-reg 9661, reproved from conditionless ZFC axioms. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2380. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (∃𝑦 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 → ∃𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | zfcndinf 10687* | Axiom of Infinity ax-inf 9707, reproved from conditionless ZFC axioms. Since we have already reproved Extensionality, Replacement, and Power Sets above, we are justified in referencing Theorem el 5457 in the proof. (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) |
⊢ ∃𝑦(𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 ∧ ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → ∃𝑤(𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | zfcndac 10688* | Axiom of Choice ax-ac 10528, reproved from conditionless ZFC axioms. (Contributed by NM, 15-Aug-2003.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ ∃𝑦∀𝑧∀𝑤((𝑧 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑥) → ∃𝑣∀𝑢(∃𝑡((𝑢 ∈ 𝑤 ∧ 𝑤 ∈ 𝑡) ∧ (𝑢 ∈ 𝑡 ∧ 𝑡 ∈ 𝑦)) ↔ 𝑢 = 𝑣)) | ||
Syntax | cgch 10689 | Extend class notation to include the collection of sets that satisfy the GCH. |
class GCH | ||
Definition | df-gch 10690* | Define the collection of "GCH-sets", or sets for which the generalized continuum hypothesis holds. In this language the generalized continuum hypothesis can be expressed as GCH = V. A set 𝑥 satisfies the generalized continuum hypothesis if it is finite or there is no set 𝑦 strictly between 𝑥 and its powerset in cardinality. The continuum hypothesis is equivalent to ω ∈ GCH. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ GCH = (Fin ∪ {𝑥 ∣ ∀𝑦 ¬ (𝑥 ≺ 𝑦 ∧ 𝑦 ≺ 𝒫 𝑥)}) | ||
Theorem | elgch 10691* | Elementhood in the collection of GCH-sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ GCH ↔ (𝐴 ∈ Fin ∨ ∀𝑥 ¬ (𝐴 ≺ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 ≺ 𝒫 𝐴)))) | ||
Theorem | fingch 10692 | A finite set is a GCH-set. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ Fin ⊆ GCH | ||
Theorem | gchi 10693 | The only GCH-sets which have other sets between it and its power set are finite sets. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ GCH ∧ 𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ 𝒫 𝐴) → 𝐴 ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | gchen1 10694 | If 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵 < 𝒫 𝐴, and 𝐴 is an infinite GCH-set, then 𝐴 = 𝐵 in cardinality. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ GCH ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) ∧ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≺ 𝒫 𝐴)) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | gchen2 10695 | If 𝐴 < 𝐵 ≤ 𝒫 𝐴, and 𝐴 is an infinite GCH-set, then 𝐵 = 𝒫 𝐴 in cardinality. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ GCH ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) ∧ (𝐴 ≺ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝒫 𝐴)) → 𝐵 ≈ 𝒫 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | gchor 10696 | If 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵 ≤ 𝒫 𝐴, and 𝐴 is an infinite GCH-set, then either 𝐴 = 𝐵 or 𝐵 = 𝒫 𝐴 in cardinality. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ GCH ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) ∧ (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝒫 𝐴)) → (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ≈ 𝒫 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | engch 10697 | The property of being a GCH-set is a cardinal invariant. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ≈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ GCH ↔ 𝐵 ∈ GCH)) | ||
Theorem | gchdomtri 10698 | Under certain conditions, a GCH-set can demonstrate trichotomy of dominance. Lemma for gchac 10750. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ GCH ∧ (𝐴 ⊔ 𝐴) ≈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ≼ 𝒫 𝐴) → (𝐴 ≼ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ≼ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | fpwwe2cbv 10699* | Lemma for fpwwe2 10712. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑊 = {〈𝑥, 𝑟〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑟 ⊆ (𝑥 × 𝑥)) ∧ (𝑟 We 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 [(◡𝑟 “ {𝑦}) / 𝑢](𝑢𝐹(𝑟 ∩ (𝑢 × 𝑢))) = 𝑦))} ⇒ ⊢ 𝑊 = {〈𝑎, 𝑠〉 ∣ ((𝑎 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑠 ⊆ (𝑎 × 𝑎)) ∧ (𝑠 We 𝑎 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝑎 [(◡𝑠 “ {𝑧}) / 𝑣](𝑣𝐹(𝑠 ∩ (𝑣 × 𝑣))) = 𝑧))} | ||
Theorem | fpwwe2lem1 10700* | Lemma for fpwwe2 10712. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 15-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑊 = {〈𝑥, 𝑟〉 ∣ ((𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑟 ⊆ (𝑥 × 𝑥)) ∧ (𝑟 We 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 [(◡𝑟 “ {𝑦}) / 𝑢](𝑢𝐹(𝑟 ∩ (𝑢 × 𝑢))) = 𝑦))} ⇒ ⊢ 𝑊 ⊆ (𝒫 𝐴 × 𝒫 (𝐴 × 𝐴)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |