Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 37 of 466) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29289) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29290-30812) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30813-46532) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | elab6g 3601* | Membership in a class abstraction. Class version of sb6 2089. (Contributed by SN, 5-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | elabd2 3602* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Deduction version of elab 3610. (Contributed by Gino Giotto, 12-Oct-2024.) (Revised by BJ, 16-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝜓}) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | elabd3 3603* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Deduction version of elab 3610. (Contributed by Gino Giotto, 12-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜓} ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | elabgt 3604* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Closed theorem version of elabg 3608.) (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) Reduce axiom usage. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 12-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elabgtOLD 3605* | Obsolete version of elabgt 3604 as of 12-Oct-2024. (Contributed by NM, 7-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 8-Jun-2011.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓))) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elabgf 3606 | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Compare Theorem 6.13 of [Quine] p. 44. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2003.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elabf 3607* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | elabg 3608* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Compare Theorem 6.13 of [Quine] p. 44. (Contributed by NM, 14-Apr-1995.) Avoid ax-13 2373. (Revised by SN, 23-Nov-2022.) Avoid ax-10 2138, ax-11 2155, ax-12 2172. (Revised by SN, 5-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elabgOLD 3609* | Obsolete version of elabg 3608 as of 5-Oct-2024. (Contributed by NM, 14-Apr-1995.) Remove dependency on ax-13 2373. (Revised by SN, 23-Nov-2022.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elab 3610* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Compare Theorem 6.13 of [Quine] p. 44. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) Avoid ax-10 2138, ax-11 2155, ax-12 2172. (Revised by SN, 5-Oct-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | elabOLD 3611* | Obsolete version of elab 3610 as of 5-Oct-2024. (Contributed by NM, 1-Aug-1994.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | elab2g 3612* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝐵 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elabd 3613* | Explicit demonstration the class {𝑥 ∣ 𝜓} is not empty by the example 𝐴. (Contributed by RP, 12-Aug-2020.) (Revised by AV, 23-Mar-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜓}) | ||
Theorem | elab2 3614* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝐵 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | elab4g 3615* | Membership in a class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 17-Oct-2012.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝐵 = {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ V ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elab3gf 3616 | Membership in a class abstraction, with a weaker antecedent than elabgf 3606. (Contributed by NM, 6-Sep-2011.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elab3g 3617* | Membership in a class abstraction, with a weaker antecedent than elabg 3608. (Contributed by NM, 29-Aug-2006.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elab3 3618* | Membership in a class abstraction using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 10-Nov-2000.) (Revised by AV, 16-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝜓 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | elrabi 3619* | Implication for the membership in a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 31-Dec-2017.) Remove disjoint variable condition on 𝐴, 𝑥 and avoid ax-10 2138, ax-11 2155, ax-12 2172. (Revised by SN, 5-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝑉 ∣ 𝜑} → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) | ||
Theorem | elrabiOLD 3620* | Obsolete version of elrabi 3619 as of 5-Aug-2024. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 31-Dec-2017.) (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝑉 ∣ 𝜑} → 𝐴 ∈ 𝑉) | ||
Theorem | elrabf 3621 | Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. This version has bound-variable hypotheses in place of distinct variable restrictions. (Contributed by NM, 21-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐵 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | rabtru 3622 | Abstract builder using the constant wff ⊤. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 4-May-2020.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ ⊤} = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | rabeqc 3623* | A restricted class abstraction equals the restricting class if its condition follows from the membership of the free setvar variable in the restricting class. (Contributed by AV, 20-Apr-2022.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑} = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | elrab3t 3624* | Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Closed theorem version of elrab3 3626.) (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 31-Aug-2017.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥(𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elrab 3625* | Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-1999.) Remove dependency on ax-13 2373. (Revised by Steven Nguyen, 23-Nov-2022.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elrab3 3626* | Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 5-Oct-2006.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | elrabd 3627* | Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. Deduction version of elrab 3625. (Contributed by Glauco Siliprandi, 23-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜓}) | ||
Theorem | elrab2 3628* | Membership in a restricted class abstraction, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 2-Nov-2006.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝐶 = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∣ 𝜑} ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | ralab 3629* | Universal quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) Reduce axiom usage. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 2-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | ralabOLD 3630* | Obsolete version of ralab 3629 as of 2-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑥(𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | ralrab 3631* | Universal quantification over a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 10-Jun-2010.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜓 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | rexab 3632* | Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Jan-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) Reduce axiom usage. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 2-Nov-2024.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | rexabOLD 3633* | Obsolete version of rexab 3632 as of 2-Nov-2024. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 23-Jan-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∃𝑥(𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | rexrab 3634* | Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 17-Jun-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑥 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑}𝜒 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | ralab2 3635* | Universal quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) Drop ax-8 2109. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 1-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | ralrab2 3636* | Universal quantification over a restricted class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 → 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | rexab2 3637* | Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) Drop ax-8 2109. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 1-Dec-2023.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∣ 𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑦(𝜑 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | rexrab2 3638* | Existential quantification over a class abstraction. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 3-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝜑}𝜓 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 ∧ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | abidnf 3639* | Identity used to create closed-form versions of bound-variable hypothesis builders for class expressions. (Contributed by NM, 10-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 12-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 → {𝑧 ∣ ∀𝑥 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴} = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dedhb 3640* | A deduction theorem for converting the inference ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 => ⊢ 𝜑 into a closed theorem. Use nfa1 2149 and nfab 2914 to eliminate the hypothesis of the substitution instance 𝜓 of the inference. For converting the inference form into a deduction form, abidnf 3639 is useful. (Contributed by NM, 8-Dec-2006.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = {𝑧 ∣ ∀𝑥 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴} → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 → 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nelrdva 3641* | Deduce negative membership from an implication. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 27-Nov-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝑥 ≠ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | eqeu 3642* | A condition which implies existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Jeff Hankins, 8-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝑥 = 𝐴)) → ∃!𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | moeq 3643* | There exists at most one set equal to a given class. (Contributed by NM, 8-Mar-1995.) Shorten combined proofs of moeq 3643 and eueq 3644. (Proof shortened by BJ, 24-Sep-2022.) |
⊢ ∃*𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | eueq 3644* | A class is a set if and only if there exists a unique set equal to it. (Contributed by NM, 25-Nov-1994.) Shorten combined proofs of moeq 3643 and eueq 3644. (Proof shortened by BJ, 24-Sep-2022.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ V ↔ ∃!𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | eueqi 3645* | There exists a unique set equal to a given set. Inference associated with euequ 2598. See euequ 2598 in the case of a setvar. (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ∃!𝑥 𝑥 = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | eueq2 3646* | Equality has existential uniqueness (split into 2 cases). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ∃!𝑥((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) ∨ (¬ 𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | eueq3 3647* | Equality has existential uniqueness (split into 3 cases). (Contributed by NM, 5-Apr-1995.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 28-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ∃!𝑥((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) ∨ (¬ (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | moeq3 3648* | "At most one" property of equality (split into 3 cases). (The first two hypotheses could be eliminated with longer proof.) (Contributed by NM, 23-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V & ⊢ ¬ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ ∃*𝑥((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) ∨ (¬ (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓) ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐵) ∨ (𝜓 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | mosub 3649* | "At most one" remains true after substitution. (Contributed by NM, 9-Mar-1995.) |
⊢ ∃*𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ ∃*𝑥∃𝑦(𝑦 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | mo2icl 3650* | Theorem for inferring "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 17-Oct-1996.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝑥 = 𝐴) → ∃*𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | mob2 3651* | Consequence of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 2-Jan-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜑) → (𝑥 = 𝐴 ↔ 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | moi2 3652* | Consequence of "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 29-Jun-2008.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑) ∧ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)) → 𝑥 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | mob 3653* | Equality implied by "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2006.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → (𝐴 = 𝐵 ↔ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | moi 3654* | Equality implied by "at most one". (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2006.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐷) ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑 ∧ (𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | morex 3655* | Derive membership from uniqueness. (Contributed by Jeff Madsen, 2-Sep-2009.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∃*𝑥𝜑) → (𝜓 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | euxfr2w 3656* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. Version of euxfr2 3658 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2373. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.) (Revised by Gino Giotto, 10-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ ∃*𝑦 𝑥 = 𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥∃𝑦(𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ ∃!𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | euxfrw 3657* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. Version of euxfr 3659 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2373. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.) (Revised by Gino Giotto, 10-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ ∃!𝑦 𝑥 = 𝐴 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∃!𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | euxfr2 3658* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2373. Use the weaker euxfr2w 3656 when possible. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ ∃*𝑦 𝑥 = 𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥∃𝑦(𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ ∃!𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | euxfr 3659* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2373. Use the weaker euxfrw 3657 when possible. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ ∃!𝑦 𝑥 = 𝐴 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥𝜑 ↔ ∃!𝑦𝜓) | ||
Theorem | euind 3660* | Existential uniqueness via an indirect equality. (Contributed by NM, 11-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑥∀𝑦((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ∧ ∃𝑥𝜑) → ∃!𝑧∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝑧 = 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | reu2 3661* | A way to express restricted uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 22-Nov-1994.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ [𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑) → 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | reu6 3662* | A way to express restricted uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 20-Oct-2006.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | reu3 3663* | A way to express restricted uniqueness. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 → 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | reu6i 3664* | A condition which implies existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Oct-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝐵)) → ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | eqreu 3665* | A condition which implies existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 2-Oct-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 → 𝑥 = 𝐵)) → ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | rmo4 3666* | Restricted "at most one" using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝑥 = 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | reu4 3667* | Restricted uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 23-Nov-1994.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | reu7 3668* | Restricted uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜓 → 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | reu8 3669* | Restricted uniqueness using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜓 → 𝑥 = 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | rmo3f 3670* | Restricted "at most one" using explicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2012.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 8-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ [𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑) → 𝑥 = 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | rmo4f 3671* | Restricted "at most one" using implicit substitution. (Contributed by NM, 24-Oct-2006.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 11-Oct-2016.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 8-Mar-2017.) (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 8-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ((𝜑 ∧ 𝜓) → 𝑥 = 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | reu2eqd 3672* | Deduce equality from restricted uniqueness, deduction version. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 27-Nov-2019.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐶 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜒) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | reueq 3673* | Equality has existential uniqueness. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 1-Sep-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ↔ ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥 = 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | rmoeq 3674* | Equality's restricted existential "at most one" property. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 30-Mar-2018.) (Revised by AV, 27-Oct-2020.) (Proof shortened by NM, 29-Oct-2020.) |
⊢ ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝑥 = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | rmoan 3675 | Restricted "at most one" still holds when a conjunct is added. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜓 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | rmoim 3676 | Restricted "at most one" is preserved through implication (note wff reversal). (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | rmoimia 3677 | Restricted "at most one" is preserved through implication (note wff reversal). (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝜑 → 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | rmoimi 3678 | Restricted "at most one" is preserved through implication (note wff reversal). (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | rmoimi2 3679 | Restricted "at most one" is preserved through implication (note wff reversal). (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ ∀𝑥((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) → (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 2reu5a 3680 | Double restricted existential uniqueness in terms of restricted existence and restricted "at most one". (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ↔ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ∧ ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) ∧ ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ∧ ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑))) | ||
Theorem | reuimrmo 3681 | Restricted uniqueness implies restricted "at most one" through implication, analogous to euimmo 2619. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 25-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (𝜑 → 𝜓) → (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜓 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | 2reuswap 3682* | A condition allowing swap of uniqueness and existential quantifiers. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 7-Apr-2017.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | 2reuswap2 3683* | A condition allowing swap of uniqueness and existential quantifiers. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 7-Apr-2017.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃*𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜑) → (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | reuxfrd 3684* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jan-2012.) Separate variables 𝐵 and 𝐶. (Revised by Thierry Arnoux, 8-Oct-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) → ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝑥 = 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 (𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜓) ↔ ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | reuxfr 3685* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.) (Revised by NM, 16-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 → ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝑥 = 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 (𝑥 = 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑) ↔ ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | reuxfr1d 3686* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. Cf. reuxfr1ds 3687. (Contributed by Thierry Arnoux, 7-Apr-2017.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) → ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝑥 = 𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 = 𝐴) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝜓 ↔ ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | reuxfr1ds 3687* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. Use reuhypd 5343 to eliminate the second hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jan-2012.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) → ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝑥 = 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝜓 ↔ ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | reuxfr1 3688* | Transfer existential uniqueness from a variable 𝑥 to another variable 𝑦 contained in expression 𝐴. Use reuhyp 5344 to eliminate the second hypothesis. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 → ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝑥 = 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ↔ ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐶 𝜓) | ||
Theorem | reuind 3689* | Existential uniqueness via an indirect equality. (Contributed by NM, 16-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑥∀𝑦(((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝜑) ∧ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝜓)) → 𝐴 = 𝐵) ∧ ∃𝑥(𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝜑)) → ∃!𝑧 ∈ 𝐶 ∀𝑥((𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝜑) → 𝑧 = 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | 2rmorex 3690* | Double restricted quantification with "at most one", analogous to 2moex 2643. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 2reu5lem1 3691* | Lemma for 2reu5 3694. Note that ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵𝜑 does not mean "there is exactly one 𝑥 in 𝐴 and exactly one 𝑦 in 𝐵 such that 𝜑 holds"; see comment for 2eu5 2658. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ↔ ∃!𝑥∃!𝑦(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | 2reu5lem2 3692* | Lemma for 2reu5 3694. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ↔ ∀𝑥∃*𝑦(𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | 2reu5lem3 3693* | Lemma for 2reu5 3694. This lemma is interesting in its own right, showing that existential restriction in the last conjunct (the "at most one" part) is optional; compare rmo2 3821. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ ((∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) ↔ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑧∃𝑤∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑧 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝑤)))) | ||
Theorem | 2reu5 3694* | Double restricted existential uniqueness in terms of restricted existential quantification and restricted universal quantification, analogous to 2eu5 2658 and reu3 3663. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 17-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ ((∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) ↔ (∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ∧ ∃𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 (𝜑 → (𝑥 = 𝑧 ∧ 𝑦 = 𝑤)))) | ||
Theorem | 2reurmo 3695 | Double restricted quantification with restricted existential uniqueness and restricted "at most one", analogous to 2eumo 2645. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 24-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → ∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 2reurex 3696* | Double restricted quantification with existential uniqueness, analogous to 2euex 2644. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 24-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | 2rmoswap 3697* | A condition allowing to swap restricted "at most one" and restricted existential quantifiers, analogous to 2moswap 2647. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 25-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → (∃*𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 → ∃*𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | 2rexreu 3698* | Double restricted existential uniqueness implies double restricted unique existential quantification, analogous to 2exeu 2649. (Contributed by Alexander van der Vekens, 25-Jun-2017.) |
⊢ ((∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ∧ ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝜑) → ∃!𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃!𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑) | ||
This is a very useless definition, which "abbreviates" (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) as CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑). What this display hides, though, is that the first expression, even though it has a shorter constant string, is actually much more complicated in its parse tree: it is parsed as (wi (wceq (cv vx) (cv vy)) wph), while the CondEq version is parsed as (wcdeq vx vy wph). It also allows us to give a name to the specific ternary operation (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑). This is all used as part of a metatheorem: we want to say that ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑(𝑥) ↔ 𝜑(𝑦))) and ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐴(𝑥) = 𝐴(𝑦)) are provable, for any expressions 𝜑(𝑥) or 𝐴(𝑥) in the language. The proof is by induction, so the base case is each of the primitives, which is why you will see a theorem for each of the set.mm primitive operations. The metatheorem comes with a disjoint variables assumption: every variable in 𝜑(𝑥) is assumed disjoint from 𝑥 except 𝑥 itself. For such a proof by induction, we must consider each of the possible forms of 𝜑(𝑥). If it is a variable other than 𝑥, then we have CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐴 = 𝐴) or CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜑)), which is provable by cdeqth 3703 and reflexivity. Since we are only working with class and wff expressions, it can't be 𝑥 itself in set.mm, but if it was we'd have to also prove CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝑥 = 𝑦) (where set equality is being used on the right). Otherwise, it is a primitive operation applied to smaller expressions. In these cases, for each setvar variable parameter to the operation, we must consider if it is equal to 𝑥 or not, which yields 2^n proof obligations. Luckily, all primitive operations in set.mm have either zero or one setvar variable, so we only need to prove one statement for the non-set constructors (like implication) and two for the constructors taking a set (the universal quantifier and the class builder). In each of the primitive proofs, we are allowed to assume that 𝑦 is disjoint from 𝜑(𝑥) and vice versa, because this is maintained through the induction. This is how we satisfy the disjoint variable conditions of cdeqab1 3708 and cdeqab 3706. | ||
Syntax | wcdeq 3699 | Extend wff notation to include conditional equality. This is a technical device used in the proof that Ⅎ is the not-free predicate, and that definitions are conservative as a result. |
wff CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) | ||
Definition | df-cdeq 3700 | Define conditional equality. All the notation to the left of the ↔ is fake; the parentheses and arrows are all part of the notation, which could equally well be written CondEq𝑥𝑦𝜑. On the right side is the actual implication arrow. The reason for this definition is to "flatten" the structure on the right side (whose tree structure is something like (wi (wceq (cv vx) (cv vy)) wph) ) into just (wcdeq vx vy wph). (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 11-Aug-2016.) |
⊢ (CondEq(𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑) ↔ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝜑)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |