Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 407 of 466) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29289) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29290-30812) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30813-46532) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | diophin 40601 | If two sets are Diophantine, so is their intersection. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) → (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | diophun 40602 | If two sets are Diophantine, so is their union. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 9-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | eldiophss 40603 | Diophantine sets are sets of tuples of nonnegative integers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (Dioph‘𝐵) → 𝐴 ⊆ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | diophrex 40604* | Projecting a Diophantine set by removing a coordinate results in a Diophantine set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑀 ∈ (ℤ≥‘𝑁) ∧ 𝑆 ∈ (Dioph‘𝑀)) → {𝑡 ∣ ∃𝑢 ∈ 𝑆 𝑡 = (𝑢 ↾ (1...𝑁))} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | eq0rabdioph 40605* | This is the first of a number of theorems which allow sets to be proven Diophantine by syntactic induction, and models the correspondence between Diophantine sets and monotone existential first-order logic. This first theorem shows that the zero set of an implicit polynomial is Diophantine. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 = 0} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | eqrabdioph 40606* | Diophantine set builder for equality of polynomial expressions. Note that the two expressions need not be nonnegative; only variables are so constrained. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁)) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐵) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 = 𝐵} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 0dioph 40607 | The null set is Diophantine. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 → ∅ ∈ (Dioph‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | vdioph 40608 | The "universal" set (as large as possible given eldiophss 40603) is Diophantine. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 → (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐴)) ∈ (Dioph‘𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | anrabdioph 40609* | Diophantine set builder for conjunctions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (({𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜓} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | orrabdioph 40610* | Diophantine set builder for disjunctions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (({𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜓} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓)} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 3anrabdioph 40611* | Diophantine set builder for ternary conjunctions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (({𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜓} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜒} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ (𝜑 ∧ 𝜓 ∧ 𝜒)} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 3orrabdioph 40612* | Diophantine set builder for ternary disjunctions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (({𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜓} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜒} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ (𝜑 ∨ 𝜓 ∨ 𝜒)} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 2sbcrex 40613* | Exchange an existential quantifier with two substitutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by NM, 24-Aug-2018.) |
⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑎][𝐵 / 𝑏]∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 [𝐴 / 𝑎][𝐵 / 𝑏]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sbcrexgOLD 40614* | Interchange class substitution and restricted existential quantifier. (Contributed by NM, 15-Nov-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 29-Jun-2011.) Obsolete as of 18-Aug-2018. Use sbcrex 3809 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑥]∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 [𝐴 / 𝑥]𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | 2sbcrexOLD 40615* | Exchange an existential quantifier with two substitutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) Obsolete as of 24-Aug-2018. Use csbov123 7326 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑎][𝐵 / 𝑏]∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 [𝐴 / 𝑎][𝐵 / 𝑏]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sbc2rex 40616* | Exchange a substitution with two existentials. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by NM, 24-Aug-2018.) |
⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑎]∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 [𝐴 / 𝑎]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sbc2rexgOLD 40617* | Exchange a substitution with two existentials. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) Obsolete as of 24-Aug-2018. Use csbov123 7326 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑎]∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 [𝐴 / 𝑎]𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | sbc4rex 40618* | Exchange a substitution with four existentials. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by NM, 24-Aug-2018.) |
⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑎]∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 ∃𝑑 ∈ 𝐷 ∃𝑒 ∈ 𝐸 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 ∃𝑑 ∈ 𝐷 ∃𝑒 ∈ 𝐸 [𝐴 / 𝑎]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sbc4rexgOLD 40619* | Exchange a substitution with four existentials. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) Obsolete as of 24-Aug-2018. Use csbov123 7326 instead. (New usage is discouraged.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ([𝐴 / 𝑎]∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 ∃𝑑 ∈ 𝐷 ∃𝑒 ∈ 𝐸 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝐶 ∃𝑑 ∈ 𝐷 ∃𝑒 ∈ 𝐸 [𝐴 / 𝑎]𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | sbcrot3 40620* | Rotate a sequence of three explicit substitutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑎][𝐵 / 𝑏][𝐶 / 𝑐]𝜑 ↔ [𝐵 / 𝑏][𝐶 / 𝑐][𝐴 / 𝑎]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sbcrot5 40621* | Rotate a sequence of five explicit substitutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑎][𝐵 / 𝑏][𝐶 / 𝑐][𝐷 / 𝑑][𝐸 / 𝑒]𝜑 ↔ [𝐵 / 𝑏][𝐶 / 𝑐][𝐷 / 𝑑][𝐸 / 𝑒][𝐴 / 𝑎]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | sbccomieg 40622* | Commute two explicit substitutions, using an implicit substitution to rewrite the exiting substitution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ (𝑎 = 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ([𝐴 / 𝑎][𝐵 / 𝑏]𝜑 ↔ [𝐶 / 𝑏][𝐴 / 𝑎]𝜑) | ||
Theorem | rexrabdioph 40623* | Diophantine set builder for existential quantification. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) & ⊢ (𝑣 = (𝑡‘𝑀) → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑢 = (𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜑)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑀)) ∣ 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑀)) → {𝑢 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑣 ∈ ℕ0 𝜓} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | rexfrabdioph 40624* | Diophantine set builder for existential quantifier, explicit substitution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑀)) ∣ [(𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) / 𝑢][(𝑡‘𝑀) / 𝑣]𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑀)) → {𝑢 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑣 ∈ ℕ0 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 2rexfrabdioph 40625* | Diophantine set builder for existential quantifier, explicit substitution, two variables. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑀 + 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐿)) ∣ [(𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) / 𝑢][(𝑡‘𝑀) / 𝑣][(𝑡‘𝐿) / 𝑤]𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝐿)) → {𝑢 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑣 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 3rexfrabdioph 40626* | Diophantine set builder for existential quantifier, explicit substitution, two variables. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑀 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐿 + 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐾)) ∣ [(𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) / 𝑢][(𝑡‘𝑀) / 𝑣][(𝑡‘𝐿) / 𝑤][(𝑡‘𝐾) / 𝑥]𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝐾)) → {𝑢 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑣 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑥 ∈ ℕ0 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 4rexfrabdioph 40627* | Diophantine set builder for existential quantifier, explicit substitution, four variables. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑀 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐿 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐾 + 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐽)) ∣ [(𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) / 𝑢][(𝑡‘𝑀) / 𝑣][(𝑡‘𝐿) / 𝑤][(𝑡‘𝐾) / 𝑥][(𝑡‘𝐽) / 𝑦]𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝐽)) → {𝑢 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑣 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑥 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 6rexfrabdioph 40628* | Diophantine set builder for existential quantifier, explicit substitution, six variables. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑀 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐿 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐾 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (𝐽 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (𝐼 + 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐻)) ∣ [(𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) / 𝑢][(𝑡‘𝑀) / 𝑣][(𝑡‘𝐿) / 𝑤][(𝑡‘𝐾) / 𝑥][(𝑡‘𝐽) / 𝑦][(𝑡‘𝐼) / 𝑧][(𝑡‘𝐻) / 𝑝]𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝐻)) → {𝑢 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑣 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑥 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑝 ∈ ℕ0 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | 7rexfrabdioph 40629* | Diophantine set builder for existential quantifier, explicit substitution, seven variables. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐿 = (𝑀 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐾 = (𝐿 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐽 = (𝐾 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐼 = (𝐽 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (𝐼 + 1) & ⊢ 𝐺 = (𝐻 + 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐺)) ∣ [(𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) / 𝑢][(𝑡‘𝑀) / 𝑣][(𝑡‘𝐿) / 𝑤][(𝑡‘𝐾) / 𝑥][(𝑡‘𝐽) / 𝑦][(𝑡‘𝐼) / 𝑧][(𝑡‘𝐻) / 𝑝][(𝑡‘𝐺) / 𝑞]𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝐺)) → {𝑢 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑣 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑥 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑝 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑞 ∈ ℕ0 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | rabdiophlem1 40630* | Lemma for arithmetic diophantine sets. Convert polynomial-ness of an expression into a constraint suitable for ralimi 3088. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁)) → ∀𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁))𝐴 ∈ ℤ) | ||
Theorem | rabdiophlem2 40631* | Lemma for arithmetic diophantine sets. Reuse a polynomial expression under a new quantifier. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 10-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑀 = (𝑁 + 1) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑢 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑀)) ↦ ⦋(𝑡 ↾ (1...𝑁)) / 𝑢⦌𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑀))) | ||
Theorem | elnn0rabdioph 40632* | Diophantine set builder for nonnegativity constraints. The first builder which uses a witness variable internally; an expression is nonnegative if there is a nonnegative integer equal to it. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 ∈ ℕ0} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | rexzrexnn0 40633* | Rewrite an existential quantification restricted to integers into an existential quantification restricted to naturals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = -𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥 ∈ ℤ 𝜑 ↔ ∃𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 (𝜓 ∨ 𝜒)) | ||
Theorem | lerabdioph 40634* | Diophantine set builder for the "less than or equal to" relation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁)) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐵) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 ≤ 𝐵} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | eluzrabdioph 40635* | Diophantine set builder for membership in a fixed upper set of integers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘𝑀)} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | elnnrabdioph 40636* | Diophantine set builder for positivity. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 ∈ ℕ} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | ltrabdioph 40637* | Diophantine set builder for the strict less than relation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁)) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐵) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 < 𝐵} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | nerabdioph 40638* | Diophantine set builder for inequality. This not quite trivial theorem touches on something important; Diophantine sets are not closed under negation, but they contain an important subclass that is, namely the recursive sets. With this theorem and De Morgan's laws, all quantifier-free formulas can be negated. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁)) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐵) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | dvdsrabdioph 40639* | Divisibility is a Diophantine relation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 11-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐴) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁)) ∧ (𝑡 ∈ (ℤ ↑m (1...𝑁)) ↦ 𝐵) ∈ (mzPoly‘(1...𝑁))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝐴 ∥ 𝐵} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | eldioph4b 40640* | Membership in Dioph expressed using a quantified union to add witness variables instead of a restriction to remove them. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑊 ∈ V & ⊢ ¬ 𝑊 ∈ Fin & ⊢ (𝑊 ∩ ℕ) = ∅ ⇒ ⊢ (𝑆 ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ↔ (𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ ∃𝑝 ∈ (mzPoly‘(𝑊 ∪ (1...𝑁)))𝑆 = {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑤 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m 𝑊)(𝑝‘(𝑡 ∪ 𝑤)) = 0})) | ||
Theorem | eldioph4i 40641* | Forward-only version of eldioph4b 40640. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ 𝑊 ∈ V & ⊢ ¬ 𝑊 ∈ Fin & ⊢ (𝑊 ∩ ℕ) = ∅ ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑃 ∈ (mzPoly‘(𝑊 ∪ (1...𝑁)))) → {𝑡 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ ∃𝑤 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m 𝑊)(𝑃‘(𝑡 ∪ 𝑤)) = 0} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | diophren 40642* | Change variables in a Diophantine set, using class notation. This allows already proved Diophantine sets to be reused in contexts with more variables. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 5-Jun-2015.) |
⊢ ((𝑆 ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝐹:(1...𝑁)⟶(1...𝑀)) → {𝑎 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑀)) ∣ (𝑎 ∘ 𝐹) ∈ 𝑆} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑀)) | ||
Theorem | rabrenfdioph 40643* | Change variable numbers in a Diophantine class abstraction using explicit substitution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐵 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝐹:(1...𝐴)⟶(1...𝐵) ∧ {𝑎 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐴)) ∣ 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝐴)) → {𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝐵)) ∣ [(𝑏 ∘ 𝐹) / 𝑎]𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | rabren3dioph 40644* | Change variable numbers in a 3-variable Diophantine class abstraction. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝑎‘1) = (𝑏‘𝑋) ∧ (𝑎‘2) = (𝑏‘𝑌) ∧ (𝑎‘3) = (𝑏‘𝑍)) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ 𝑋 ∈ (1...𝑁) & ⊢ 𝑌 ∈ (1...𝑁) & ⊢ 𝑍 ∈ (1...𝑁) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ {𝑎 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...3)) ∣ 𝜑} ∈ (Dioph‘3)) → {𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 ↑m (1...𝑁)) ∣ 𝜓} ∈ (Dioph‘𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | fphpd 40645* | Pigeonhole principle expressed with implicit substitution. If the range is smaller than the domain, two inputs must be mapped to the same output. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐶 = 𝐷) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑥 ≠ 𝑦 ∧ 𝐶 = 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | fphpdo 40646* | Pigeonhole principle for sets of real numbers with implicit output reordering. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 12-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ⊆ ℝ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ V) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ≺ 𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝑥 → 𝐶 = 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝑦 → 𝐶 = 𝐸) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑥 < 𝑦 ∧ 𝐷 = 𝐸)) | ||
Theorem | ctbnfien 40647 | An infinite subset of a countable set is countable, without using choice. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) (Revised by Stefan O'Rear, 6-May-2015.) |
⊢ (((𝑋 ≈ ω ∧ 𝑌 ≈ ω) ∧ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝑋 ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin)) → 𝐴 ≈ 𝑌) | ||
Theorem | fiphp3d 40648* | Infinite pigeonhole principle for partitioning an infinite set between finitely many buckets. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ≈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ Fin) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐷 ∈ 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ 𝐷 = 𝑦} ≈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | rencldnfilem 40649* | Lemma for rencldnfi 40650. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ ℝ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ ∧ (𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ ¬ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴)) ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ℝ+ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (abs‘(𝑦 − 𝐵)) < 𝑥) → ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | rencldnfi 40650* | A set of real numbers which comes arbitrarily close to some target yet excludes it is infinite. The work is done in rencldnfilem 40649 using infima; this theorem removes the requirement that A be nonempty. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ ℝ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ ∧ ¬ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ ℝ+ ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (abs‘(𝑦 − 𝐵)) < 𝑥) → ¬ 𝐴 ∈ Fin) | ||
Theorem | irrapxlem1 40651* | Lemma for irrapx1 40657. Divides the unit interval into 𝐵 half-open sections and using the pigeonhole principle fphpdo 40646 finds two multiples of 𝐴 in the same section mod 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 12-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → ∃𝑥 ∈ (0...𝐵)∃𝑦 ∈ (0...𝐵)(𝑥 < 𝑦 ∧ (⌊‘(𝐵 · ((𝐴 · 𝑥) mod 1))) = (⌊‘(𝐵 · ((𝐴 · 𝑦) mod 1))))) | ||
Theorem | irrapxlem2 40652* | Lemma for irrapx1 40657. Two multiples in the same bucket means they are very close mod 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 12-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → ∃𝑥 ∈ (0...𝐵)∃𝑦 ∈ (0...𝐵)(𝑥 < 𝑦 ∧ (abs‘(((𝐴 · 𝑥) mod 1) − ((𝐴 · 𝑦) mod 1))) < (1 / 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | irrapxlem3 40653* | Lemma for irrapx1 40657. By subtraction, there is a multiple very close to an integer. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → ∃𝑥 ∈ (1...𝐵)∃𝑦 ∈ ℕ0 (abs‘((𝐴 · 𝑥) − 𝑦)) < (1 / 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | irrapxlem4 40654* | Lemma for irrapx1 40657. Eliminate ranges, use positivity of the input to force positivity of the output by increasing 𝐵 as needed. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) → ∃𝑥 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑦 ∈ ℕ (abs‘((𝐴 · 𝑥) − 𝑦)) < (1 / if(𝑥 ≤ 𝐵, 𝐵, 𝑥))) | ||
Theorem | irrapxlem5 40655* | Lemma for irrapx1 40657. Switching to real intervals and fraction syntax. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ+) → ∃𝑥 ∈ ℚ (0 < 𝑥 ∧ (abs‘(𝑥 − 𝐴)) < 𝐵 ∧ (abs‘(𝑥 − 𝐴)) < ((denom‘𝑥)↑-2))) | ||
Theorem | irrapxlem6 40656* | Lemma for irrapx1 40657. Explicit description of a non-closed set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 13-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ+) → ∃𝑥 ∈ {𝑦 ∈ ℚ ∣ (0 < 𝑦 ∧ (abs‘(𝑦 − 𝐴)) < ((denom‘𝑦)↑-2))} (abs‘(𝑥 − 𝐴)) < 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | irrapx1 40657* | Dirichlet's approximation theorem. Every positive irrational number has infinitely many rational approximations which are closer than the inverse squares of their reduced denominators. Lemma 61 in [vandenDries] p. 42. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℝ+ ∖ ℚ) → {𝑦 ∈ ℚ ∣ (0 < 𝑦 ∧ (abs‘(𝑦 − 𝐴)) < ((denom‘𝑦)↑-2))} ≈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | pellexlem1 40658 | Lemma for pellex 40664. Arithmetical core of pellexlem3, norm lower bound. This begins Dirichlet's proof of the Pell equation solution existence; the proof here follows theorem 62 of [vandenDries] p. 43. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐷 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) ∧ ¬ (√‘𝐷) ∈ ℚ) → ((𝐴↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝐵↑2))) ≠ 0) | ||
Theorem | pellexlem2 40659 | Lemma for pellex 40664. Arithmetical core of pellexlem3, norm upper bound. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐷 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) ∧ (abs‘((𝐴 / 𝐵) − (√‘𝐷))) < (𝐵↑-2)) → (abs‘((𝐴↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝐵↑2)))) < (1 + (2 · (√‘𝐷)))) | ||
Theorem | pellexlem3 40660* | Lemma for pellex 40664. To each good rational approximation of (√‘𝐷), there exists a near-solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ ℕ ∧ ¬ (√‘𝐷) ∈ ℚ) → {𝑥 ∈ ℚ ∣ (0 < 𝑥 ∧ (abs‘(𝑥 − (√‘𝐷))) < ((denom‘𝑥)↑-2))} ≼ {〈𝑦, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑦 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑧 ∈ ℕ) ∧ (((𝑦↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑧↑2))) ≠ 0 ∧ (abs‘((𝑦↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑧↑2)))) < (1 + (2 · (√‘𝐷)))))}) | ||
Theorem | pellexlem4 40661* | Lemma for pellex 40664. Invoking irrapx1 40657, we have infinitely many near-solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ ℕ ∧ ¬ (√‘𝐷) ∈ ℚ) → {〈𝑦, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑦 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑧 ∈ ℕ) ∧ (((𝑦↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑧↑2))) ≠ 0 ∧ (abs‘((𝑦↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑧↑2)))) < (1 + (2 · (√‘𝐷)))))} ≈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | pellexlem5 40662* | Lemma for pellex 40664. Invoking fiphp3d 40648, we have infinitely many near-solutions for some specific norm. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ ℕ ∧ ¬ (√‘𝐷) ∈ ℚ) → ∃𝑥 ∈ ℤ (𝑥 ≠ 0 ∧ {〈𝑦, 𝑧〉 ∣ ((𝑦 ∈ ℕ ∧ 𝑧 ∈ ℕ) ∧ ((𝑦↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑧↑2))) = 𝑥)} ≈ ℕ)) | ||
Theorem | pellexlem6 40663* | Lemma for pellex 40664. Doing a field division between near solutions get us to norm 1, and the modularity constraint ensures we still have an integer. Returning NN guarantees that we are not returning the trivial solution (1,0). We are not explicitly defining the Pell-field, Pell-ring, and Pell-norm explicitly because after this construction is done we will never use them. This is mostly basic algebraic number theory and could be simplified if a generic framework for that were in place. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐴 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐵 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ∈ ℤ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐷 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ (√‘𝐷) ∈ ℚ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐸 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐹 ∈ ℕ) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ (𝐴 = 𝐸 ∧ 𝐵 = 𝐹)) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝐶 ≠ 0) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝐴↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝐵↑2))) = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ((𝐸↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝐹↑2))) = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐴 mod (abs‘𝐶)) = (𝐸 mod (abs‘𝐶))) & ⊢ (𝜑 → (𝐵 mod (abs‘𝐶)) = (𝐹 mod (abs‘𝐶))) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑎 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑏 ∈ ℕ ((𝑎↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑏↑2))) = 1) | ||
Theorem | pellex 40664* | Every Pell equation has a nontrivial solution. Theorem 62 in [vandenDries] p. 43. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ ℕ ∧ ¬ (√‘𝐷) ∈ ℚ) → ∃𝑥 ∈ ℕ ∃𝑦 ∈ ℕ ((𝑥↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑦↑2))) = 1) | ||
Syntax | csquarenn 40665 | Extend class notation to include the set of square positive integers. |
class ◻NN | ||
Syntax | cpell1qr 40666 | Extend class notation to include the class of quadrant-1 Pell solutions. |
class Pell1QR | ||
Syntax | cpell1234qr 40667 | Extend class notation to include the class of any-quadrant Pell solutions. |
class Pell1234QR | ||
Syntax | cpell14qr 40668 | Extend class notation to include the class of positive Pell solutions. |
class Pell14QR | ||
Syntax | cpellfund 40669 | Extend class notation to include the Pell-equation fundamental solution function. |
class PellFund | ||
Definition | df-squarenn 40670 | Define the set of square positive integers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ◻NN = {𝑥 ∈ ℕ ∣ (√‘𝑥) ∈ ℚ} | ||
Definition | df-pell1qr 40671* | Define the solutions of a Pell equation in the first quadrant. To avoid pair pain, we represent this via the canonical embedding into the reals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ Pell1QR = (𝑥 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ↦ {𝑦 ∈ ℝ ∣ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 (𝑦 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝑥) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝑥 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)}) | ||
Definition | df-pell14qr 40672* | Define the positive solutions of a Pell equation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ Pell14QR = (𝑥 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ↦ {𝑦 ∈ ℝ ∣ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℤ (𝑦 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝑥) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝑥 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)}) | ||
Definition | df-pell1234qr 40673* | Define the general solutions of a Pell equation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ Pell1234QR = (𝑥 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ↦ {𝑦 ∈ ℝ ∣ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℤ ∃𝑤 ∈ ℤ (𝑦 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝑥) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝑥 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)}) | ||
Definition | df-pellfund 40674* | A function mapping Pell discriminants to the corresponding fundamental solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) (Revised by AV, 17-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ PellFund = (𝑥 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ↦ inf({𝑧 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝑥) ∣ 1 < 𝑧}, ℝ, < )) | ||
Theorem | pell1qrval 40675* | Value of the set of first-quadrant Pell solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (Pell1QR‘𝐷) = {𝑦 ∈ ℝ ∣ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 (𝑦 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)}) | ||
Theorem | elpell1qr 40676* | Membership in a first-quadrant Pell solution set. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷) ↔ (𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℕ0 (𝐴 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)))) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrval 40677* | Value of the set of positive Pell solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (Pell14QR‘𝐷) = {𝑦 ∈ ℝ ∣ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℤ (𝑦 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)}) | ||
Theorem | elpell14qr 40678* | Membership in the set of positive Pell solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ↔ (𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑤 ∈ ℤ (𝐴 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)))) | ||
Theorem | pell1234qrval 40679* | Value of the set of general Pell solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (Pell1234QR‘𝐷) = {𝑦 ∈ ℝ ∣ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℤ ∃𝑤 ∈ ℤ (𝑦 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)}) | ||
Theorem | elpell1234qr 40680* | Membership in the set of general Pell solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷) ↔ (𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ ∃𝑧 ∈ ℤ ∃𝑤 ∈ ℤ (𝐴 = (𝑧 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝑤)) ∧ ((𝑧↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝑤↑2))) = 1)))) | ||
Theorem | pell1234qrre 40681 | General Pell solutions are (coded as) real numbers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | pell1234qrne0 40682 | No solution to a Pell equation is zero. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) → 𝐴 ≠ 0) | ||
Theorem | pell1234qrreccl 40683 | General solutions of the Pell equation are closed under reciprocals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) → (1 / 𝐴) ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell1234qrmulcl 40684 | General solutions of the Pell equation are closed under multiplication. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 · 𝐵) ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrss1234 40685 | A positive Pell solution is a general Pell solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ⊆ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrre 40686 | A positive Pell solution is a real number. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrne0 40687 | A positive Pell solution is a nonzero number. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → 𝐴 ≠ 0) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrgt0 40688 | A positive Pell solution is a positive number. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → 0 < 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrrp 40689 | A positive Pell solution is a positive real. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ+) | ||
Theorem | pell1234qrdich 40690 | A general Pell solution is either a positive solution, or its negation is. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∨ -𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷))) | ||
Theorem | elpell14qr2 40691 | A number is a positive Pell solution iff it is positive and a Pell solution, justifying our name choice. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ↔ (𝐴 ∈ (Pell1234QR‘𝐷) ∧ 0 < 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrmulcl 40692 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under multiplication. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 · 𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrreccl 40693 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under reciprocal. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (1 / 𝐴) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrdivcl 40694 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under division. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 / 𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrexpclnn0 40695 | Lemma for pell14qrexpcl 40696. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝐴↑𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrexpcl 40696 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under integer powers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴↑𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell1qrss14 40697 | First-quadrant Pell solutions are a subset of the positive solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (Pell1QR‘𝐷) ⊆ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrdich 40698 | A positive Pell solution is either in the first quadrant, or its reciprocal is. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷) ∨ (1 / 𝐴) ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷))) | ||
Theorem | pell1qrge1 40699 | A Pell solution in the first quadrant is at least 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)) → 1 ≤ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pell1qr1 40700 | 1 is a Pell solution and in the first quadrant as one. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → 1 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |