Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 407 of 464) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29181) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29182-30704) |
Users' Mathboxes
(30705-46395) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | pell14qrmulcl 40601 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under multiplication. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 · 𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrreccl 40602 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under reciprocal. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (1 / 𝐴) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrdivcl 40603 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under division. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 / 𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrexpclnn0 40604 | Lemma for pell14qrexpcl 40605. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝐴↑𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrexpcl 40605 | Positive Pell solutions are closed under integer powers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴↑𝐵) ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell1qrss14 40606 | First-quadrant Pell solutions are a subset of the positive solutions. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (Pell1QR‘𝐷) ⊆ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrdich 40607 | A positive Pell solution is either in the first quadrant, or its reciprocal is. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷) ∨ (1 / 𝐴) ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷))) | ||
Theorem | pell1qrge1 40608 | A Pell solution in the first quadrant is at least 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)) → 1 ≤ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pell1qr1 40609 | 1 is a Pell solution and in the first quadrant as one. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 17-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → 1 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | elpell1qr2 40610 | The first quadrant solutions are precisely the positive Pell solutions which are at least one. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷) ↔ (𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 1 ≤ 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | pell1qrgaplem 40611 | Lemma for pell1qrgap 40612. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐷 ∈ ℕ ∧ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ0)) ∧ (1 < (𝐴 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝐵)) ∧ ((𝐴↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝐵↑2))) = 1)) → ((√‘(𝐷 + 1)) + (√‘𝐷)) ≤ (𝐴 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | pell1qrgap 40612 | First-quadrant Pell solutions are bounded away from 1. (This particular bound allows us to prove exact values for the fundamental solution later.) (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷) ∧ 1 < 𝐴) → ((√‘(𝐷 + 1)) + (√‘𝐷)) ≤ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrgap 40613 | Positive Pell solutions are bounded away from 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 1 < 𝐴) → ((√‘(𝐷 + 1)) + (√‘𝐷)) ≤ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pell14qrgapw 40614 | Positive Pell solutions are bounded away from 1, with a friendlier bound. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 1 < 𝐴) → 2 < 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pellqrexplicit 40615 | Condition for a calculated real to be a Pell solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℕ0) ∧ ((𝐴↑2) − (𝐷 · (𝐵↑2))) = 1) → (𝐴 + ((√‘𝐷) · 𝐵)) ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | infmrgelbi 40616* | Any lower bound of a nonempty set of real numbers is less than or equal to its infimum, one-direction version. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 1-Sep-2013.) (Revised by AV, 17-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (((𝐴 ⊆ ℝ ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ) ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ≤ 𝑥) → 𝐵 ≤ inf(𝐴, ℝ, < )) | ||
Theorem | pellqrex 40617* | There is a nontrivial solution of a Pell equation in the first quadrant. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → ∃𝑥 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)1 < 𝑥) | ||
Theorem | pellfundval 40618* | Value of the fundamental solution of a Pell equation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) (Revised by AV, 17-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (PellFund‘𝐷) = inf({𝑥 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∣ 1 < 𝑥}, ℝ, < )) | ||
Theorem | pellfundre 40619 | The fundamental solution of a Pell equation exists as a real number. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (PellFund‘𝐷) ∈ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | pellfundge 40620 | Lower bound on the fundamental solution of a Pell equation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → ((√‘(𝐷 + 1)) + (√‘𝐷)) ≤ (PellFund‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pellfundgt1 40621 | Weak lower bound on the Pell fundamental solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → 1 < (PellFund‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pellfundlb 40622 | A nontrivial first quadrant solution is at least as large as the fundamental solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 15-Sep-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ 1 < 𝐴) → (PellFund‘𝐷) ≤ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | pellfundglb 40623* | If a real is larger than the fundamental solution, there is a nontrivial solution less than it. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℝ ∧ (PellFund‘𝐷) < 𝐴) → ∃𝑥 ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)((PellFund‘𝐷) ≤ 𝑥 ∧ 𝑥 < 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | pellfundex 40624 |
The fundamental solution as an infimum is itself a solution, showing
that the solution set is discrete.
Since the fundamental solution is an infimum, there must be an element ge to Fund and lt 2*Fund. If this element is equal to the fundamental solution we're done, otherwise use the infimum again to find another element which must be ge Fund and lt the first element; their ratio is a group element in (1,2), contradicting pell14qrgapw 40614. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (PellFund‘𝐷) ∈ (Pell1QR‘𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | pellfund14gap 40625 | There are no solutions between 1 and the fundamental solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 18-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ∧ (1 ≤ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 < (PellFund‘𝐷))) → 𝐴 = 1) | ||
Theorem | pellfundrp 40626 | The fundamental Pell solution is a positive real. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (PellFund‘𝐷) ∈ ℝ+) | ||
Theorem | pellfundne1 40627 | The fundamental Pell solution is never 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (PellFund‘𝐷) ≠ 1) | ||
Section should be obsolete because its contents are covered by section "Logarithms to an arbitrary base" now. | ||
Theorem | reglogcl 40628 | General logarithm is a real number. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use relogbcl 25828 instead. |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ≠ 1) → ((log‘𝐴) / (log‘𝐵)) ∈ ℝ) | ||
Theorem | reglogltb 40629 | General logarithm preserves "less than". (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use logblt 25839 instead. |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ+) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 1 < 𝐶)) → (𝐴 < 𝐵 ↔ ((log‘𝐴) / (log‘𝐶)) < ((log‘𝐵) / (log‘𝐶)))) | ||
Theorem | reglogleb 40630 | General logarithm preserves ≤. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use logbleb 25838 instead. |
⊢ (((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ+) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 1 < 𝐶)) → (𝐴 ≤ 𝐵 ↔ ((log‘𝐴) / (log‘𝐶)) ≤ ((log‘𝐵) / (log‘𝐶)))) | ||
Theorem | reglogmul 40631 | Multiplication law for general log. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use relogbmul 25832 instead. |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ (𝐶 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐶 ≠ 1)) → ((log‘(𝐴 · 𝐵)) / (log‘𝐶)) = (((log‘𝐴) / (log‘𝐶)) + ((log‘𝐵) / (log‘𝐶)))) | ||
Theorem | reglogexp 40632 | Power law for general log. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use relogbzexp 25831 instead. |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐶 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐶 ≠ 1)) → ((log‘(𝐴↑𝑁)) / (log‘𝐶)) = (𝑁 · ((log‘𝐴) / (log‘𝐶)))) | ||
Theorem | reglogbas 40633 | General log of the base is 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use logbid1 25823 instead. |
⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐶 ≠ 1) → ((log‘𝐶) / (log‘𝐶)) = 1) | ||
Theorem | reglog1 40634 | General log of 1 is 0. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use logb1 25824 instead. |
⊢ ((𝐶 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐶 ≠ 1) → ((log‘1) / (log‘𝐶)) = 0) | ||
Theorem | reglogexpbas 40635 | General log of a power of the base is the exponent. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) (New usage is discouraged.) Use relogbexp 25835 instead. |
⊢ ((𝑁 ∈ ℤ ∧ (𝐶 ∈ ℝ+ ∧ 𝐶 ≠ 1)) → ((log‘(𝐶↑𝑁)) / (log‘𝐶)) = 𝑁) | ||
Theorem | pellfund14 40636* | Every positive Pell solution is a power of the fundamental solution. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) ∧ 𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷)) → ∃𝑥 ∈ ℤ 𝐴 = ((PellFund‘𝐷)↑𝑥)) | ||
Theorem | pellfund14b 40637* | The positive Pell solutions are precisely the integer powers of the fundamental solution. To get the general solution set (which we will not be using), throw in a copy of Z/2Z. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐷 ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN) → (𝐴 ∈ (Pell14QR‘𝐷) ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ ℤ 𝐴 = ((PellFund‘𝐷)↑𝑥))) | ||
Syntax | crmx 40638 | Extend class notation to include the Robertson-Matiyasevich X sequence. |
class Xrm | ||
Syntax | crmy 40639 | Extend class notation to include the Robertson-Matiyasevich Y sequence. |
class Yrm | ||
Definition | df-rmx 40640* | Define the X sequence as the rational part of some solution of a special Pell equation. See frmx 40651 and rmxyval 40653 for a more useful but non-eliminable definition. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ Xrm = (𝑎 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2), 𝑛 ∈ ℤ ↦ (1st ‘(◡(𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 × ℤ) ↦ ((1st ‘𝑏) + ((√‘((𝑎↑2) − 1)) · (2nd ‘𝑏))))‘((𝑎 + (√‘((𝑎↑2) − 1)))↑𝑛)))) | ||
Definition | df-rmy 40641* | Define the X sequence as the irrational part of some solution of a special Pell equation. See frmy 40652 and rmxyval 40653 for a more useful but non-eliminable definition. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ Yrm = (𝑎 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2), 𝑛 ∈ ℤ ↦ (2nd ‘(◡(𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 × ℤ) ↦ ((1st ‘𝑏) + ((√‘((𝑎↑2) − 1)) · (2nd ‘𝑏))))‘((𝑎 + (√‘((𝑎↑2) − 1)))↑𝑛)))) | ||
Theorem | rmxfval 40642* | Value of the X sequence. Not used after rmxyval 40653 is proved. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁) = (1st ‘(◡(𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 × ℤ) ↦ ((1st ‘𝑏) + ((√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) · (2nd ‘𝑏))))‘((𝐴 + (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)))↑𝑁)))) | ||
Theorem | rmyfval 40643* | Value of the Y sequence. Not used after rmxyval 40653 is proved. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁) = (2nd ‘(◡(𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 × ℤ) ↦ ((1st ‘𝑏) + ((√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) · (2nd ‘𝑏))))‘((𝐴 + (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)))↑𝑁)))) | ||
Theorem | rmspecsqrtnq 40644 | The discriminant used to define the X and Y sequences has an irrational square root. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) (Proof shortened by AV, 2-Aug-2021.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) ∈ (ℂ ∖ ℚ)) | ||
Theorem | rmspecnonsq 40645 | The discriminant used to define the X and Y sequences is a nonsquare positive integer and thus a valid Pell equation discriminant. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → ((𝐴↑2) − 1) ∈ (ℕ ∖ ◻NN)) | ||
Theorem | qirropth 40646 | This lemma implements the concept of "equate rational and irrational parts", used to prove many arithmetical properties of the X and Y sequences. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℂ ∖ ℚ) ∧ (𝐵 ∈ ℚ ∧ 𝐶 ∈ ℚ) ∧ (𝐷 ∈ ℚ ∧ 𝐸 ∈ ℚ)) → ((𝐵 + (𝐴 · 𝐶)) = (𝐷 + (𝐴 · 𝐸)) ↔ (𝐵 = 𝐷 ∧ 𝐶 = 𝐸))) | ||
Theorem | rmspecfund 40647 | The base of exponent used to define the X and Y sequences is the fundamental solution of the corresponding Pell equation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (PellFund‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) = (𝐴 + (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)))) | ||
Theorem | rmxyelqirr 40648* | The solutions used to construct the X and Y sequences are quadratic irrationals. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → ((𝐴 + (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)))↑𝑁) ∈ {𝑎 ∣ ∃𝑐 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑑 ∈ ℤ 𝑎 = (𝑐 + ((√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) · 𝑑))}) | ||
Theorem | rmxypairf1o 40649* | The function used to extract rational and irrational parts in df-rmx 40640 and df-rmy 40641 in fact achieves a one-to-one mapping from the quadratic irrationals to pairs of integers. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 21-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 × ℤ) ↦ ((1st ‘𝑏) + ((√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) · (2nd ‘𝑏)))):(ℕ0 × ℤ)–1-1-onto→{𝑎 ∣ ∃𝑐 ∈ ℕ0 ∃𝑑 ∈ ℤ 𝑎 = (𝑐 + ((√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) · 𝑑))}) | ||
Theorem | rmxyelxp 40650* | Lemma for frmx 40651 and frmy 40652. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (◡(𝑏 ∈ (ℕ0 × ℤ) ↦ ((1st ‘𝑏) + ((√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) · (2nd ‘𝑏))))‘((𝐴 + (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)))↑𝑁)) ∈ (ℕ0 × ℤ)) | ||
Theorem | frmx 40651 | The X sequence is a nonnegative integer. See rmxnn 40689 for a strengthening. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ Xrm :((ℤ≥‘2) × ℤ)⟶ℕ0 | ||
Theorem | frmy 40652 | The Y sequence is an integer. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ Yrm :((ℤ≥‘2) × ℤ)⟶ℤ | ||
Theorem | rmxyval 40653 | Main definition of the X and Y sequences. Compare definition 2.3 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 694. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → ((𝐴 Xrm 𝑁) + ((√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) = ((𝐴 + (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1)))↑𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | rmspecpos 40654 | The discriminant used to define the X and Y sequences is a positive real. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → ((𝐴↑2) − 1) ∈ ℝ+) | ||
Theorem | rmxycomplete 40655* | The X and Y sequences taken together enumerate all solutions to the corresponding Pell equation in the right half-plane. This is Metamath 100 proof #39. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑋 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ ℤ) → (((𝑋↑2) − (((𝐴↑2) − 1) · (𝑌↑2))) = 1 ↔ ∃𝑛 ∈ ℤ (𝑋 = (𝐴 Xrm 𝑛) ∧ 𝑌 = (𝐴 Yrm 𝑛)))) | ||
Theorem | rmxynorm 40656 | The X and Y sequences define a solution to the corresponding Pell equation. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (((𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)↑2) − (((𝐴↑2) − 1) · ((𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)↑2))) = 1) | ||
Theorem | rmbaserp 40657 | The base of exponentiation for the X and Y sequences is a positive real. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (𝐴 + (√‘((𝐴↑2) − 1))) ∈ ℝ+) | ||
Theorem | rmxyneg 40658 | Negation law for X and Y sequences. JonesMatijasevic is inconsistent on whether the X and Y sequences have domain ℕ0 or ℤ; we use ℤ consistently to avoid the need for a separate subtraction law. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → ((𝐴 Xrm -𝑁) = (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁) ∧ (𝐴 Yrm -𝑁) = -(𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | rmxyadd 40659 | Addition formula for X and Y sequences. See rmxadd 40665 and rmyadd 40669 for most uses. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → ((𝐴 Xrm (𝑀 + 𝑁)) = (((𝐴 Xrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) + (((𝐴↑2) − 1) · ((𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)))) ∧ (𝐴 Yrm (𝑀 + 𝑁)) = (((𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) + ((𝐴 Xrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))))) | ||
Theorem | rmxy1 40660 | Value of the X and Y sequences at 1. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → ((𝐴 Xrm 1) = 𝐴 ∧ (𝐴 Yrm 1) = 1)) | ||
Theorem | rmxy0 40661 | Value of the X and Y sequences at 0. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → ((𝐴 Xrm 0) = 1 ∧ (𝐴 Yrm 0) = 0)) | ||
Theorem | rmxneg 40662 | Negation law (even function) for the X sequence. The method of proof used for the previous four theorems rmxyneg 40658, rmxyadd 40659, rmxy0 40661, and rmxy1 40660 via qirropth 40646 results in two theorems at once, but typical use requires only one, so this group of theorems serves to separate the cases. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm -𝑁) = (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | rmx0 40663 | Value of X sequence at 0. Part 1 of equation 2.11 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (𝐴 Xrm 0) = 1) | ||
Theorem | rmx1 40664 | Value of X sequence at 1. Part 2 of equation 2.11 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (𝐴 Xrm 1) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | rmxadd 40665 | Addition formula for X sequence. Equation 2.7 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm (𝑀 + 𝑁)) = (((𝐴 Xrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) + (((𝐴↑2) − 1) · ((𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))))) | ||
Theorem | rmyneg 40666 | Negation formula for Y sequence (odd function). (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm -𝑁) = -(𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | rmy0 40667 | Value of Y sequence at 0. Part 1 of equation 2.12 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (𝐴 Yrm 0) = 0) | ||
Theorem | rmy1 40668 | Value of Y sequence at 1. Part 2 of equation 2.12 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) → (𝐴 Yrm 1) = 1) | ||
Theorem | rmyadd 40669 | Addition formula for Y sequence. Equation 2.8 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 22-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm (𝑀 + 𝑁)) = (((𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) + ((𝐴 Xrm 𝑀) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)))) | ||
Theorem | rmxp1 40670 | Special addition-of-1 formula for X sequence. Part 1 of equation 2.9 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm (𝑁 + 1)) = (((𝐴 Xrm 𝑁) · 𝐴) + (((𝐴↑2) − 1) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)))) | ||
Theorem | rmyp1 40671 | Special addition of 1 formula for Y sequence. Part 2 of equation 2.9 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 + 1)) = (((𝐴 Yrm 𝑁) · 𝐴) + (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | rmxm1 40672 | Subtraction of 1 formula for X sequence. Part 1 of equation 2.10 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm (𝑁 − 1)) = ((𝐴 · (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) − (((𝐴↑2) − 1) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)))) | ||
Theorem | rmym1 40673 | Subtraction of 1 formula for Y sequence. Part 2 of equation 2.10 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 19-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 − 1)) = (((𝐴 Yrm 𝑁) · 𝐴) − (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | rmxluc 40674 | The X sequence is a Lucas (second-order integer recurrence) sequence. Part 3 of equation 2.11 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm (𝑁 + 1)) = (((2 · 𝐴) · (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) − (𝐴 Xrm (𝑁 − 1)))) | ||
Theorem | rmyluc 40675 | The Y sequence is a Lucas sequence, definable via this second-order recurrence with rmy0 40667 and rmy1 40668. Part 3 of equation 2.12 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. JonesMatijasevic uses this theorem to redefine the X and Y sequences to have domain (ℤ × ℤ), which simplifies some later theorems. It may shorten the derivation to use this as our initial definition. Incidentally, the X sequence satisfies the exact same recurrence. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 1-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 + 1)) = ((2 · ((𝐴 Yrm 𝑁) · 𝐴)) − (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 − 1)))) | ||
Theorem | rmyluc2 40676 | Lucas sequence property of Y with better output ordering. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 + 1)) = (((2 · 𝐴) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)) − (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 − 1)))) | ||
Theorem | rmxdbl 40677 | "Double-angle formula" for X-values. Equation 2.13 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm (2 · 𝑁)) = ((2 · ((𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)↑2)) − 1)) | ||
Theorem | rmydbl 40678 | "Double-angle formula" for Y-values. Equation 2.14 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 695. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 2-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Yrm (2 · 𝑁)) = ((2 · (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) · (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | monotuz 40679* | A function defined on an upper set of integers which increases at every adjacent pair is globally strictly monotonic by induction. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐻) → 𝐹 < 𝐺) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐻) → 𝐶 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ 𝐻 = (ℤ≥‘𝐼) & ⊢ (𝑥 = (𝑦 + 1) → 𝐶 = 𝐺) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐶 = 𝐹) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐶 = 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐵 → 𝐶 = 𝐸) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐻 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐻)) → (𝐴 < 𝐵 ↔ 𝐷 < 𝐸)) | ||
Theorem | monotoddzzfi 40680* | A function which is odd and monotonic on ℕ0 is monotonic on ℤ. This proof is far too long. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 25-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐹‘𝑥) ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐹‘-𝑥) = -(𝐹‘𝑥)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑥 < 𝑦 → (𝐹‘𝑥) < (𝐹‘𝑦))) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 < 𝐵 ↔ (𝐹‘𝐴) < (𝐹‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | monotoddzz 40681* | A function (given implicitly) which is odd and monotonic on ℕ0 is monotonic on ℤ. This proof is far too long. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 25-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑥 < 𝑦 → 𝐸 < 𝐹)) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ℤ) → 𝐸 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℤ) → 𝐺 = -𝐹) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐸 = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐵 → 𝐸 = 𝐷) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐸 = 𝐹) & ⊢ (𝑥 = -𝑦 → 𝐸 = 𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 < 𝐵 ↔ 𝐶 < 𝐷)) | ||
Theorem | oddcomabszz 40682* | An odd function which takes nonnegative values on nonnegative arguments commutes with abs. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 26-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ℤ) → 𝐴 ∈ ℝ) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑥 ∈ ℤ ∧ 0 ≤ 𝑥) → 0 ≤ 𝐴) & ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ℤ) → 𝐶 = -𝐵) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → 𝐴 = 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝑥 = -𝑦 → 𝐴 = 𝐶) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐷 → 𝐴 = 𝐸) & ⊢ (𝑥 = (abs‘𝐷) → 𝐴 = 𝐹) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜑 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ ℤ) → (abs‘𝐸) = 𝐹) | ||
Theorem | 2nn0ind 40683* | Induction on nonnegative integers with two base cases, for use with Lucas-type sequences. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 1-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ 𝜓 & ⊢ 𝜒 & ⊢ (𝑦 ∈ ℕ → ((𝜃 ∧ 𝜏) → 𝜂)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 0 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 1 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = (𝑦 − 1) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = (𝑦 + 1) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜂)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜌)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℕ0 → 𝜌) | ||
Theorem | zindbi 40684* | Inductively transfer a property to the integers if it holds for zero and passes between adjacent integers in either direction. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 1-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ (𝑦 ∈ ℤ → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = (𝑦 + 1) → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 0 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ℤ → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | rmxypos 40685 | For all nonnegative indices, X is positive and Y is nonnegative. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (0 < (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁) ∧ 0 ≤ (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | ltrmynn0 40686 | The Y-sequence is strictly monotonic on ℕ0. Strengthened by ltrmy 40690. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 24-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑀 < 𝑁 ↔ (𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) < (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | ltrmxnn0 40687 | The X-sequence is strictly monotonic on ℕ0. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑀 < 𝑁 ↔ (𝐴 Xrm 𝑀) < (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | lermxnn0 40688 | The X-sequence is monotonic on ℕ0. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℕ0 ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝑀 ≤ 𝑁 ↔ (𝐴 Xrm 𝑀) ≤ (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | rmxnn 40689 | The X-sequence is defined to range over ℕ0 but never actually takes the value 0. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 4-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | ltrmy 40690 | The Y-sequence is strictly monotonic over ℤ. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 25-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝑀 < 𝑁 ↔ (𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) < (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | rmyeq0 40691 | Y is zero only at zero. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 26-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝑁 = 0 ↔ (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁) = 0)) | ||
Theorem | rmyeq 40692 | Y is one-to-one. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 3-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝑀 = 𝑁 ↔ (𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) = (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | lermy 40693 | Y is monotonic (non-strict). (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 3-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑀 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℤ) → (𝑀 ≤ 𝑁 ↔ (𝐴 Yrm 𝑀) ≤ (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁))) | ||
Theorem | rmynn 40694 | Yrm is positive for positive arguments. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) → (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁) ∈ ℕ) | ||
Theorem | rmynn0 40695 | Yrm is nonnegative for nonnegative arguments. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 16-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁) ∈ ℕ0) | ||
Theorem | rmyabs 40696 | Yrm commutes with abs. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 26-Sep-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ) → (abs‘(𝐴 Yrm 𝐵)) = (𝐴 Yrm (abs‘𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | jm2.24nn 40697 | X(n) is strictly greater than Y(n) + Y(n-1). Lemma 2.24 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 697 restricted to ℕ. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 3-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) → ((𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 − 1)) + (𝐴 Yrm 𝑁)) < (𝐴 Xrm 𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | jm2.17a 40698 | First half of lemma 2.17 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 696. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 14-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (((2 · 𝐴) − 1)↑𝑁) ≤ (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 + 1))) | ||
Theorem | jm2.17b 40699 | Weak form of the second half of lemma 2.17 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 696, allowing induction to start lower. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ0) → (𝐴 Yrm (𝑁 + 1)) ≤ ((2 · 𝐴)↑𝑁)) | ||
Theorem | jm2.17c 40700 | Second half of lemma 2.17 of [JonesMatijasevic] p. 696. (Contributed by Stefan O'Rear, 15-Oct-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ (ℤ≥‘2) ∧ 𝑁 ∈ ℕ) → (𝐴 Yrm ((𝑁 + 1) + 1)) < ((2 · 𝐴)↑(𝑁 + 1))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |