Home | Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 342 of 470) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | Metamath Proof Explorer
(1-29646) |
Hilbert Space Explorer
(29647-31169) |
Users' Mathboxes
(31170-46966) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | gcdabsorb 34101 | Absorption law for gcd. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Apr-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Apr-2014.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ ℤ ∧ 𝐵 ∈ ℤ) → ((𝐴 gcd 𝐵) gcd 𝐵) = (𝐴 gcd 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | dftr6 34102 | A potential definition of transitivity for sets. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 18-Mar-2012.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 ∈ (V ∖ ran (( E ∘ E ) ∖ E ))) | ||
Theorem | coep 34103* | Composition with the membership relation. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 18-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴( E ∘ 𝑅)𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 𝐴𝑅𝑥) | ||
Theorem | coepr 34104* | Composition with the converse membership relation. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 18-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴(𝑅 ∘ ◡ E )𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑥𝑅𝐵) | ||
Theorem | dffr5 34105 | A quantifier-free definition of a well-founded relationship. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 11-Apr-2011.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Fr 𝐴 ↔ (𝒫 𝐴 ∖ {∅}) ⊆ ran ( E ∖ ( E ∘ ◡𝑅))) | ||
Theorem | dfso2 34106 | Quantifier-free definition of a strict order. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 22-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Or 𝐴 ↔ (𝑅 Po 𝐴 ∧ (𝐴 × 𝐴) ⊆ (𝑅 ∪ ( I ∪ ◡𝑅)))) | ||
Theorem | br8 34107* | Substitution for an eight-place predicate. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 26-Sep-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑎 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑐 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑑 = 𝐷 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑒 = 𝐸 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜂)) & ⊢ (𝑓 = 𝐹 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) & ⊢ (𝑔 = 𝐺 → (𝜁 ↔ 𝜎)) & ⊢ (ℎ = 𝐻 → (𝜎 ↔ 𝜌)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑋 → 𝑃 = 𝑄) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {⟨𝑝, 𝑞⟩ ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑑 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑒 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑓 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑔 ∈ 𝑃 ∃ℎ ∈ 𝑃 (𝑝 = ⟨⟨𝑎, 𝑏⟩, ⟨𝑐, 𝑑⟩⟩ ∧ 𝑞 = ⟨⟨𝑒, 𝑓⟩, ⟨𝑔, ℎ⟩⟩ ∧ 𝜑)} ⇒ ⊢ (((𝑋 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ 𝐴 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑄) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐸 ∈ 𝑄) ∧ (𝐹 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐺 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐻 ∈ 𝑄)) → (⟨⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩, ⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩⟩𝑅⟨⟨𝐸, 𝐹⟩, ⟨𝐺, 𝐻⟩⟩ ↔ 𝜌)) | ||
Theorem | br6 34108* | Substitution for a six-place predicate. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 4-Oct-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ (𝑎 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑐 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑑 = 𝐷 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑒 = 𝐸 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜂)) & ⊢ (𝑓 = 𝐹 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑋 → 𝑃 = 𝑄) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {⟨𝑝, 𝑞⟩ ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑑 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑒 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑓 ∈ 𝑃 (𝑝 = ⟨𝑎, ⟨𝑏, 𝑐⟩⟩ ∧ 𝑞 = ⟨𝑑, ⟨𝑒, 𝑓⟩⟩ ∧ 𝜑)} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐶 ∈ 𝑄) ∧ (𝐷 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐸 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐹 ∈ 𝑄)) → (⟨𝐴, ⟨𝐵, 𝐶⟩⟩𝑅⟨𝐷, ⟨𝐸, 𝐹⟩⟩ ↔ 𝜁)) | ||
Theorem | br4 34109* | Substitution for a four-place predicate. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 9-Oct-2013.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 14-Oct-2013.) |
⊢ (𝑎 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝐵 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑐 = 𝐶 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑑 = 𝐷 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑋 → 𝑃 = 𝑄) & ⊢ 𝑅 = {⟨𝑝, 𝑞⟩ ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∃𝑎 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑐 ∈ 𝑃 ∃𝑑 ∈ 𝑃 (𝑝 = ⟨𝑎, 𝑏⟩ ∧ 𝑞 = ⟨𝑐, 𝑑⟩ ∧ 𝜑)} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝑆 ∧ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝑄) ∧ (𝐶 ∈ 𝑄 ∧ 𝐷 ∈ 𝑄)) → (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩𝑅⟨𝐶, 𝐷⟩ ↔ 𝜏)) | ||
Theorem | cnvco1 34110 | Another distributive law of converse over class composition. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 3-May-2014.) |
⊢ ◡(◡𝐴 ∘ 𝐵) = (◡𝐵 ∘ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | cnvco2 34111 | Another distributive law of converse over class composition. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 3-May-2014.) |
⊢ ◡(𝐴 ∘ ◡𝐵) = (𝐵 ∘ ◡𝐴) | ||
Theorem | eldm3 34112 | Quantifier-free definition of membership in a domain. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ dom 𝐵 ↔ (𝐵 ↾ {𝐴}) ≠ ∅) | ||
Theorem | elrn3 34113 | Quantifier-free definition of membership in a range. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Jan-2017.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ ran 𝐵 ↔ (𝐵 ∩ (V × {𝐴})) ≠ ∅) | ||
Theorem | pocnv 34114 | The converse of a partial ordering is still a partial ordering. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Po 𝐴 → ◡𝑅 Po 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | socnv 34115 | The converse of a strict ordering is still a strict ordering. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑅 Or 𝐴 → ◡𝑅 Or 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | sotrd 34116 | Transitivity law for strict orderings, deduction form. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 24-Nov-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Or 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑌 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑍 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋𝑅𝑌) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑌𝑅𝑍) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋𝑅𝑍) | ||
Theorem | elintfv 34117* | Membership in an intersection of function values. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 9-Dec-2021.) |
⊢ 𝑋 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐹 Fn 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) → (𝑋 ∈ ∩ (𝐹 “ 𝐵) ↔ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 𝑋 ∈ (𝐹‘𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | funpsstri 34118 | A condition for subset trichotomy for functions. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 19-Apr-2011.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐻 ∧ (𝐹 ⊆ 𝐻 ∧ 𝐺 ⊆ 𝐻) ∧ (dom 𝐹 ⊆ dom 𝐺 ∨ dom 𝐺 ⊆ dom 𝐹)) → (𝐹 ⊊ 𝐺 ∨ 𝐹 = 𝐺 ∨ 𝐺 ⊊ 𝐹)) | ||
Theorem | fundmpss 34119 | If a class 𝐹 is a proper subset of a function 𝐺, then dom 𝐹 ⊊ dom 𝐺. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 20-Apr-2011.) |
⊢ (Fun 𝐺 → (𝐹 ⊊ 𝐺 → dom 𝐹 ⊊ dom 𝐺)) | ||
Theorem | funsseq 34120 | Given two functions with equal domains, equality only requires one direction of the subset relationship. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 24-Apr-2012.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ Fun 𝐺 ∧ dom 𝐹 = dom 𝐺) → (𝐹 = 𝐺 ↔ 𝐹 ⊆ 𝐺)) | ||
Theorem | fununiq 34121 | The uniqueness condition of functions. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 18-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Fun 𝐹 → ((𝐴𝐹𝐵 ∧ 𝐴𝐹𝐶) → 𝐵 = 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | funbreq 34122 | An equality condition for functions. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 18-Feb-2013.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐶 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((Fun 𝐹 ∧ 𝐴𝐹𝐵) → (𝐴𝐹𝐶 ↔ 𝐵 = 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | br1steq 34123 | Uniqueness condition for the binary relation 1st. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 11-Apr-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩1st 𝐶 ↔ 𝐶 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | br2ndeq 34124 | Uniqueness condition for the binary relation 2nd. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 11-Apr-2014.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 3-May-2015.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩2nd 𝐶 ↔ 𝐶 = 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | dfdm5 34125 | Definition of domain in terms of 1st and image. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 11-Apr-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Apr-2014.) (Proof shortened by Peter Mazsa, 2-Oct-2022.) |
⊢ dom 𝐴 = ((1st ↾ (V × V)) “ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dfrn5 34126 | Definition of range in terms of 2nd and image. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 17-Apr-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Apr-2014.) (Proof shortened by Peter Mazsa, 2-Oct-2022.) |
⊢ ran 𝐴 = ((2nd ↾ (V × V)) “ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | opelco3 34127 | Alternate way of saying that an ordered pair is in a composition. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 6-May-2018.) |
⊢ (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩ ∈ (𝐶 ∘ 𝐷) ↔ 𝐵 ∈ (𝐶 “ (𝐷 “ {𝐴}))) | ||
Theorem | elima4 34128 | Quantifier-free expression saying that a class is a member of an image. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-May-2018.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ (𝑅 “ 𝐵) ↔ (𝑅 ∩ (𝐵 × {𝐴})) ≠ ∅) | ||
Theorem | fv1stcnv 34129 | The value of the converse of 1st restricted to a singleton. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 2-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝑉) → (◡(1st ↾ (𝐴 × {𝑌}))‘𝑋) = ⟨𝑋, 𝑌⟩) | ||
Theorem | fv2ndcnv 34130 | The value of the converse of 2nd restricted to a singleton. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 2-Jul-2020.) |
⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝑉 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐴) → (◡(2nd ↾ ({𝑋} × 𝐴))‘𝑌) = ⟨𝑋, 𝑌⟩) | ||
Theorem | setinds 34131* | Principle of set induction (or E-induction). If a property passes from all elements of 𝑥 to 𝑥 itself, then it holds for all 𝑥. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 10-Mar-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 [𝑦 / 𝑥]𝜑 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | setinds2f 34132* | E induction schema, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 10-Mar-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 𝜓 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | setinds2 34133* | E induction schema, using implicit substitution. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 10-Mar-2011.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑦 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 𝜓 → 𝜑) ⇒ ⊢ 𝜑 | ||
Theorem | elpotr 34134* | A class of transitive sets is partially ordered by E. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Oct-2010.) |
⊢ (∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 Tr 𝑧 → E Po 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dford5reg 34135 | Given ax-reg 9462, an ordinal is a transitive class totally ordered by the membership relation. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 28-Jan-2011.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 ↔ (Tr 𝐴 ∧ E Or 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem1 34136 | Lemma for dfon2 34145. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 28-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ Tr ∪ {𝑥 ∣ (𝜑 ∧ Tr 𝑥 ∧ 𝜓)} | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem2 34137* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 28-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ∪ {𝑥 ∣ (𝑥 ⊆ 𝐴 ∧ 𝜑 ∧ 𝜓)} ⊆ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem3 34138* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. All sets satisfying the new definition are transitive and untangled. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊊ 𝐴 ∧ Tr 𝑥) → 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → (Tr 𝐴 ∧ ∀𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ¬ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑧))) | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem4 34139* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. If two sets satisfy the new definition, then one is a subset of the other. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊊ 𝐴 ∧ Tr 𝑥) → 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ ∀𝑦((𝑦 ⊊ 𝐵 ∧ Tr 𝑦) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵)) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem5 34140* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. Two sets satisfying the new definition also satisfy trichotomy with respect to ∈. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ ((∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊊ 𝐴 ∧ Tr 𝑥) → 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) ∧ ∀𝑦((𝑦 ⊊ 𝐵 ∧ Tr 𝑦) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵)) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem6 34141* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. A transitive class of sets satisfying the new definition satisfies the new definition. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((Tr 𝑆 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 ∀𝑧((𝑧 ⊊ 𝑥 ∧ Tr 𝑧) → 𝑧 ∈ 𝑥)) → ∀𝑦((𝑦 ⊊ 𝑆 ∧ Tr 𝑦) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑆)) | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem7 34142* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. All elements of a new ordinal are new ordinals. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 25-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (∀𝑥((𝑥 ⊊ 𝐴 ∧ Tr 𝑥) → 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴) → (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → ∀𝑦((𝑦 ⊊ 𝐵 ∧ Tr 𝑦) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem8 34143* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. The intersection of a nonempty class 𝐴 of new ordinals is itself a new ordinal and is contained within 𝐴 (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 26-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ≠ ∅ ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦((𝑦 ⊊ 𝑥 ∧ Tr 𝑦) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥)) → (∀𝑧((𝑧 ⊊ ∩ 𝐴 ∧ Tr 𝑧) → 𝑧 ∈ ∩ 𝐴) ∧ ∩ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | dfon2lem9 34144* | Lemma for dfon2 34145. A class of new ordinals is well-founded by E. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 3-Mar-2011.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∀𝑦((𝑦 ⊊ 𝑥 ∧ Tr 𝑦) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥) → E Fr 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | dfon2 34145* | On consists of all sets that contain all its transitive proper subsets. This definition comes from J. R. Isbell, "A Definition of Ordinal Numbers", American Mathematical Monthly, vol 67 (1960), pp. 51-52. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 20-Feb-2011.) |
⊢ On = {𝑥 ∣ ∀𝑦((𝑦 ⊊ 𝑥 ∧ Tr 𝑦) → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑥)} | ||
Theorem | rdgprc0 34146 | The value of the recursive definition generator at ∅ when the base value is a proper class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 26-Mar-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Apr-2014.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐼 ∈ V → (rec(𝐹, 𝐼)‘∅) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | rdgprc 34147 | The value of the recursive definition generator when 𝐼 is a proper class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 26-Mar-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Apr-2014.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐼 ∈ V → rec(𝐹, 𝐼) = rec(𝐹, ∅)) | ||
Theorem | dfrdg2 34148* | Alternate definition of the recursive function generator when 𝐼 is a set. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 26-Mar-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Apr-2014.) |
⊢ (𝐼 ∈ 𝑉 → rec(𝐹, 𝐼) = ∪ {𝑓 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ On (𝑓 Fn 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑓‘𝑦) = if(𝑦 = ∅, 𝐼, if(Lim 𝑦, ∪ (𝑓 “ 𝑦), (𝐹‘(𝑓‘∪ 𝑦)))))}) | ||
Theorem | dfrdg3 34149* | Generalization of dfrdg2 34148 to remove sethood requirement. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 27-Mar-2014.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 19-Apr-2014.) |
⊢ rec(𝐹, 𝐼) = ∪ {𝑓 ∣ ∃𝑥 ∈ On (𝑓 Fn 𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 (𝑓‘𝑦) = if(𝑦 = ∅, if(𝐼 ∈ V, 𝐼, ∅), if(Lim 𝑦, ∪ (𝑓 “ 𝑦), (𝐹‘(𝑓‘∪ 𝑦)))))} | ||
Theorem | axextdfeq 34150 | A version of ax-ext 2709 for use with defined equality. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 12-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ∃𝑧((𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦) → ((𝑧 ∈ 𝑦 → 𝑧 ∈ 𝑥) → (𝑥 ∈ 𝑤 → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑤))) | ||
Theorem | ax8dfeq 34151 | A version of ax-8 2109 for use with defined equality. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 12-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ∃𝑧((𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 → 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦) → (𝑤 ∈ 𝑥 → 𝑤 ∈ 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | axextdist 34152 | ax-ext 2709 with distinctors instead of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ((¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∧ ¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦) → (∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦) → 𝑥 = 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | axextbdist 34153 | axextb 2712 with distinctors instead of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ((¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑥 ∧ ¬ ∀𝑧 𝑧 = 𝑦) → (𝑥 = 𝑦 ↔ ∀𝑧(𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | 19.12b 34154* | Version of 19.12vv 2345 with not-free hypotheses, instead of distinct variable conditions. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 11-Dec-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜓 ⇒ ⊢ (∃𝑥∀𝑦(𝜑 → 𝜓) ↔ ∀𝑦∃𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | exnel 34155 | There is always a set not in 𝑦. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ∃𝑥 ¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦 | ||
Theorem | distel 34156 | Distinctors in terms of membership. (NOTE: this only works with relations where we can prove el 5393 and elirrv 9466.) (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ (¬ ∀𝑦 𝑦 = 𝑥 ↔ ¬ ∀𝑦 ¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑦) | ||
Theorem | axextndbi 34157 | axextnd 10461 as a biconditional. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 14-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ∃𝑧(𝑥 = 𝑦 ↔ (𝑧 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ 𝑧 ∈ 𝑦)) | ||
Theorem | hbntg 34158 | A more general form of hbnt 2292. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) → (¬ 𝜓 → ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑)) | ||
Theorem | hbimtg 34159 | A more general and closed form of hbim 2297. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ ((∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜒) ∧ (𝜓 → ∀𝑥𝜃)) → ((𝜒 → 𝜓) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜃))) | ||
Theorem | hbaltg 34160 | A more general and closed form of hbal 2168. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ (∀𝑥(𝜑 → ∀𝑦𝜓) → (∀𝑥𝜑 → ∀𝑦∀𝑥𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | hbng 34161 | A more general form of hbn 2293. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (¬ 𝜓 → ∀𝑥 ¬ 𝜑) | ||
Theorem | hbimg 34162 | A more general form of hbim 2297. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Dec-2010.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → ∀𝑥𝜓) & ⊢ (𝜒 → ∀𝑥𝜃) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝜓 → 𝜒) → ∀𝑥(𝜑 → 𝜃)) | ||
Theorem | frpoins3xpg 34163* | Special case of founded partial induction over a cross product. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵) → (∀𝑧∀𝑤(⟨𝑧, 𝑤⟩ ∈ Pred(𝑅, (𝐴 × 𝐵), ⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩) → 𝜒) → 𝜑)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑧 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑤 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑋 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑌 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜏)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝑅 Fr (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑅 Po (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑅 Se (𝐴 × 𝐵)) ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵)) → 𝜏) | ||
Theorem | frpoins3xp3g 34164* | Special case of founded partial recursion over a triple cross product. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑧 ∈ 𝐶) → (∀𝑤∀𝑡∀𝑢(⟨⟨𝑤, 𝑡⟩, 𝑢⟩ ∈ Pred(𝑅, ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶), ⟨⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩, 𝑧⟩) → 𝜃) → 𝜑)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑤 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑡 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝑢 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝑋 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑦 = 𝑌 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜂)) & ⊢ (𝑧 = 𝑍 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜁)) ⇒ ⊢ (((𝑅 Fr ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑅 Po ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑅 Se ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶)) ∧ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐶)) → 𝜁) | ||
Theorem | xpord2lem 34165* | Lemma for cross product ordering. Calculate the value of the cross product relationship. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 19-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥)𝑅(1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑆(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} ⇒ ⊢ (⟨𝑎, 𝑏⟩𝑇⟨𝑐, 𝑑⟩ ↔ ((𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝐵) ∧ (𝑐 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑑 ∈ 𝐵) ∧ ((𝑎𝑅𝑐 ∨ 𝑎 = 𝑐) ∧ (𝑏𝑆𝑑 ∨ 𝑏 = 𝑑) ∧ (𝑎 ≠ 𝑐 ∨ 𝑏 ≠ 𝑑)))) | ||
Theorem | poxp2 34166* | Another way of partially ordering a cross product of two classes. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 19-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥)𝑅(1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑆(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Po 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Po 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Po (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | frxp2 34167* | Another way of giving a founded order to a cross product of two classes. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 19-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥)𝑅(1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑆(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Fr 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Fr 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Fr (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | xpord2pred 34168* | Calculate the predecessor class in frxp2 34167. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥)𝑅(1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑆(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵) → Pred(𝑇, (𝐴 × 𝐵), ⟨𝑋, 𝑌⟩) = (((Pred(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) ∪ {𝑋}) × (Pred(𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑌) ∪ {𝑌})) ∖ {⟨𝑋, 𝑌⟩})) | ||
Theorem | sexp2 34169* | Condition for the relationship in frxp2 34167 to be set-like. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 19-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥)𝑅(1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑆(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Se 𝐵) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Se (𝐴 × 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | xpord2ind 34170* | Induction over the cross product ordering. Note that the substitutions cover all possible cases of membership in the predecessor class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 22-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑇 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (𝐴 × 𝐵) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥)𝑅(1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑆(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ 𝑅 Fr 𝐴 & ⊢ 𝑅 Po 𝐴 & ⊢ 𝑅 Se 𝐴 & ⊢ 𝑆 Fr 𝐵 & ⊢ 𝑆 Po 𝐵 & ⊢ 𝑆 Se 𝐵 & ⊢ (𝑎 = 𝑐 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝑑 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑎 = 𝑐 → (𝜃 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑎 = 𝑋 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝑌 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜂)) & ⊢ ((𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝐵) → ((∀𝑐 ∈ Pred (𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑎)∀𝑑 ∈ Pred (𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑏)𝜒 ∧ ∀𝑐 ∈ Pred (𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑎)𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑑 ∈ Pred (𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑏)𝜃) → 𝜑)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝜂) | ||
Theorem | xpord3lem 34171* | Lemma for triple ordering. Calculate the value of the relationship. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ ((((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑅(1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑆(2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑇(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦))) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} ⇒ ⊢ (⟨⟨𝑎, 𝑏⟩, 𝑐⟩𝑈⟨⟨𝑑, 𝑒⟩, 𝑓⟩ ↔ ((𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑐 ∈ 𝐶) ∧ (𝑑 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑒 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑓 ∈ 𝐶) ∧ (((𝑎𝑅𝑑 ∨ 𝑎 = 𝑑) ∧ (𝑏𝑆𝑒 ∨ 𝑏 = 𝑒) ∧ (𝑐𝑇𝑓 ∨ 𝑐 = 𝑓)) ∧ (𝑎 ≠ 𝑑 ∨ 𝑏 ≠ 𝑒 ∨ 𝑐 ≠ 𝑓)))) | ||
Theorem | poxp3 34172* | Triple cross product partial ordering. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ ((((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑅(1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑆(2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑇(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦))) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Po 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Po 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Po 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 Po ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | frxp3 34173* | Give foundedness over a triple cross product. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ ((((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑅(1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑆(2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑇(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦))) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Fr 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Fr 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Fr 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 Fr ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | xpord3pred 34174* | Calculate the predecsessor class for the triple order. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ ((((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑅(1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑆(2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑇(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦))) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐶) → Pred(𝑈, ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶), ⟨⟨𝑋, 𝑌⟩, 𝑍⟩) = ((((Pred(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) ∪ {𝑋}) × (Pred(𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑌) ∪ {𝑌})) × (Pred(𝑇, 𝐶, 𝑍) ∪ {𝑍})) ∖ {⟨⟨𝑋, 𝑌⟩, 𝑍⟩})) | ||
Theorem | sexp3 34175* | Show that the triple order is set-like. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 21-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ ((((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑅(1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑆(2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑇(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦))) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑆 Se 𝐵) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑇 Se 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑈 Se ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | xpord3ind 34176* | Induction over the triple cross product ordering. Note that the substitutions cover all possible cases of membership in the predecessor class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 4-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝑈 = {⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ ((𝐴 × 𝐵) × 𝐶) ∧ ((((1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑅(1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (1st ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥))𝑆(2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦)) ∨ (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑥)) = (2nd ‘(1st ‘𝑦))) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥)𝑇(2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦))) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))} & ⊢ 𝑅 Fr 𝐴 & ⊢ 𝑅 Po 𝐴 & ⊢ 𝑅 Se 𝐴 & ⊢ 𝑆 Fr 𝐵 & ⊢ 𝑆 Po 𝐵 & ⊢ 𝑆 Se 𝐵 & ⊢ 𝑇 Fr 𝐶 & ⊢ 𝑇 Po 𝐶 & ⊢ 𝑇 Se 𝐶 & ⊢ (𝑎 = 𝑑 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝑒 → (𝜓 ↔ 𝜒)) & ⊢ (𝑐 = 𝑓 → (𝜒 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑎 = 𝑑 → (𝜏 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝑒 → (𝜂 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝑒 → (𝜁 ↔ 𝜃)) & ⊢ (𝑐 = 𝑓 → (𝜎 ↔ 𝜏)) & ⊢ (𝑎 = 𝑋 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜌)) & ⊢ (𝑏 = 𝑌 → (𝜌 ↔ 𝜇)) & ⊢ (𝑐 = 𝑍 → (𝜇 ↔ 𝜆)) & ⊢ ((𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑏 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑐 ∈ 𝐶) → (((∀𝑑 ∈ Pred (𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑎)∀𝑒 ∈ Pred (𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑏)∀𝑓 ∈ Pred (𝑇, 𝐶, 𝑐)𝜃 ∧ ∀𝑑 ∈ Pred (𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑎)∀𝑒 ∈ Pred (𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑏)𝜒 ∧ ∀𝑑 ∈ Pred (𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑎)∀𝑓 ∈ Pred (𝑇, 𝐶, 𝑐)𝜁) ∧ (∀𝑑 ∈ Pred (𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑎)𝜓 ∧ ∀𝑒 ∈ Pred (𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑏)∀𝑓 ∈ Pred (𝑇, 𝐶, 𝑐)𝜏 ∧ ∀𝑒 ∈ Pred (𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑏)𝜎) ∧ ∀𝑓 ∈ Pred (𝑇, 𝐶, 𝑐)𝜂) → 𝜑)) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑌 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝑍 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝜆) | ||
Syntax | cwsuc 34177 | Declare the syntax for well-founded successor. |
class wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) | ||
Syntax | cwlim 34178 | Declare the syntax for well-founded limit class. |
class WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) | ||
Definition | df-wsuc 34179 | Define the concept of a successor in a well-founded set. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) (Revised by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) = inf(Pred(◡𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋), 𝐴, 𝑅) | ||
Definition | df-wlim 34180* | Define the class of limit points of a well-founded set. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) (Revised by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) = {𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ∣ (𝑥 ≠ inf(𝐴, 𝐴, 𝑅) ∧ 𝑥 = sup(Pred(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑥), 𝐴, 𝑅))} | ||
Theorem | wsuceq123 34181 | Equality theorem for well-founded successor. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 = 𝑆 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝐵 ∧ 𝑋 = 𝑌) → wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) = wsuc(𝑆, 𝐵, 𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | wsuceq1 34182 | Equality theorem for well-founded successor. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = 𝑆 → wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) = wsuc(𝑆, 𝐴, 𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | wsuceq2 34183 | Equality theorem for well-founded successor. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) = wsuc(𝑅, 𝐵, 𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | wsuceq3 34184 | Equality theorem for well-founded successor. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑋 = 𝑌 → wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) = wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑌)) | ||
Theorem | nfwsuc 34185 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for well-founded successor. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑅 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑋 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) | ||
Theorem | wlimeq12 34186 | Equality theorem for the limit class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 = 𝑆 ∧ 𝐴 = 𝐵) → WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) = WLim(𝑆, 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | wlimeq1 34187 | Equality theorem for the limit class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝑅 = 𝑆 → WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) = WLim(𝑆, 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | wlimeq2 34188 | Equality theorem for the limit class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) = WLim(𝑅, 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | nfwlim 34189 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the limit class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝑅 & ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | elwlim 34190 | Membership in the limit class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) (Revised by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝑋 ∈ WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) ↔ (𝑋 ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝑋 ≠ inf(𝐴, 𝐴, 𝑅) ∧ 𝑋 = sup(Pred(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋), 𝐴, 𝑅))) | ||
Theorem | wzel 34191 | The zero of a well-founded set is a member of that set. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 13-Jun-2018.) (Revised by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ ((𝑅 We 𝐴 ∧ 𝑅 Se 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ ∅) → inf(𝐴, 𝐴, 𝑅) ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | wsuclem 34192* | Lemma for the supremum properties of well-founded successor. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) (Revised by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 We 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑤 ∈ 𝐴 𝑋𝑅𝑤) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 (∀𝑦 ∈ Pred (◡𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) ¬ 𝑦𝑅𝑥 ∧ ∀𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 (𝑥𝑅𝑦 → ∃𝑧 ∈ Pred (◡𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋)𝑧𝑅𝑦))) | ||
Theorem | wsucex 34193 | Existence theorem for well-founded successor. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Jun-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Or 𝐴) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) ∈ V) | ||
Theorem | wsuccl 34194* | If 𝑋 is a set with an 𝑅 successor in 𝐴, then its well-founded successor is a member of 𝐴. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 15-Jun-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 We 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → ∃𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 𝑋𝑅𝑦) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋) ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | wsuclb 34195 | A well-founded successor is a lower bound on points after 𝑋. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Jun-2018.) (Proof shortened by AV, 10-Oct-2021.) |
⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 We 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑅 Se 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋 ∈ 𝑉) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑌 ∈ 𝐴) & ⊢ (𝜑 → 𝑋𝑅𝑌) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → ¬ 𝑌𝑅wsuc(𝑅, 𝐴, 𝑋)) | ||
Theorem | wlimss 34196 | The class of limit points is a subclass of the base class. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 16-Jun-2018.) |
⊢ WLim(𝑅, 𝐴) ⊆ 𝐴 | ||
Syntax | cnadd 34197 | Declare the syntax for natural ordinal addition. See df-nadd 34198. |
class +no | ||
Definition | df-nadd 34198* | Define natural ordinal addition. This is a commutative form of addition over the ordinals. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 26-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ +no = frecs({⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (On × On) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥) E (1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥) E (2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))}, (On × On), (𝑧 ∈ V, 𝑎 ∈ V ↦ ∩ {𝑤 ∈ On ∣ ((𝑎 “ ({(1st ‘𝑧)} × (2nd ‘𝑧))) ⊆ 𝑤 ∧ (𝑎 “ ((1st ‘𝑧) × {(2nd ‘𝑧)})) ⊆ 𝑤)})) | ||
Theorem | on2recsfn 34199* | Show that double recursion over ordinals yields a function over pairs of ordinals. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 3-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = frecs({⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (On × On) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥) E (1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥) E (2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))}, (On × On), 𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ 𝐹 Fn (On × On) | ||
Theorem | on2recsov 34200* | Calculate the value of the double ordinal recursion operator. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 3-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ 𝐹 = frecs({⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩ ∣ (𝑥 ∈ (On × On) ∧ 𝑦 ∈ (On × On) ∧ (((1st ‘𝑥) E (1st ‘𝑦) ∨ (1st ‘𝑥) = (1st ‘𝑦)) ∧ ((2nd ‘𝑥) E (2nd ‘𝑦) ∨ (2nd ‘𝑥) = (2nd ‘𝑦)) ∧ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑦))}, (On × On), 𝐺) ⇒ ⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴𝐹𝐵) = (⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩𝐺(𝐹 ↾ ((suc 𝐴 × suc 𝐵) ∖ {⟨𝐴, 𝐵⟩})))) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |