![]() |
Metamath
Proof Explorer Theorem List (p. 65 of 479) | < Previous Next > |
Bad symbols? Try the
GIF version. |
||
Mirrors > Metamath Home Page > MPE Home Page > Theorem List Contents > Recent Proofs This page: Page List |
Color key: | ![]() (1-30166) |
![]() (30167-31689) |
![]() (31690-47842) |
Type | Label | Description |
---|---|---|
Statement | ||
Theorem | ordtri4 6401 | A trichotomy law for ordinals. (Contributed by NM, 1-Nov-2003.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐵) → (𝐴 = 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | orddisj 6402 | An ordinal class and its singleton are disjoint. (Contributed by NM, 19-May-1998.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → (𝐴 ∩ {𝐴}) = ∅) | ||
Theorem | onfr 6403 | The ordinal class is well-founded. This proof does not require the axiom of regularity. This lemma is used in ordon 7763 (through epweon 7761) in order to eliminate the need for the axiom of regularity. (Contributed by NM, 17-May-1994.) |
⊢ E Fr On | ||
Theorem | onelpss 6404 | Relationship between membership and proper subset of an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐴 ≠ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | onsseleq 6405 | Relationship between subset and membership of an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | onelss 6406 | An element of an ordinal number is a subset of the number. (Contributed by NM, 5-Jun-1994.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ordtr1 6407 | Transitive law for ordinal classes. (Contributed by NM, 12-Dec-2004.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐶 → ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | ordtr2 6408 | Transitive law for ordinal classes. (Contributed by NM, 12-Dec-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐶) → ((𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | ordtr3 6409 | Transitive law for ordinal classes. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 30-Dec-2014.) (Proof shortened by JJ, 24-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐵 ∧ Ord 𝐶) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∨ 𝐶 ∈ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ontr1 6410 | Transitive law for ordinal numbers. Theorem 7M(b) of [Enderton] p. 192. Theorem 1.9(ii) of [Schloeder] p. 1. (Contributed by NM, 11-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐶 ∈ On → ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | ontr2 6411 | Transitive law for ordinal numbers. Exercise 3 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 40. (Contributed by NM, 6-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐶 ∈ On) → ((𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶) → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐶)) | ||
Theorem | onelssex 6412* | Ordinal less than is equivalent to having an ordinal between them. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 8-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐶 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ↔ ∃𝑏 ∈ 𝐶 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑏)) | ||
Theorem | ordunidif 6413 | The union of an ordinal stays the same if a subset equal to one of its elements is removed. (Contributed by NM, 10-Dec-2004.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → ∪ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) = ∪ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ordintdif 6414 | If 𝐵 is smaller than 𝐴, then it equals the intersection of the difference. Exercise 11 in [TakeutiZaring] p. 44. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 14-Nov-2011.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐵 ∧ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵) ≠ ∅) → 𝐵 = ∩ (𝐴 ∖ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | onintss 6415* | If a property is true for an ordinal number, then the minimum ordinal number for which it is true is smaller or equal. Theorem Schema 61 of [Suppes] p. 228. (Contributed by NM, 3-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → (𝜑 ↔ 𝜓)) ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝜓 → ∩ {𝑥 ∈ On ∣ 𝜑} ⊆ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | oneqmini 6416* | A way to show that an ordinal number equals the minimum of a collection of ordinal numbers: it must be in the collection, and it must not be larger than any member of the collection. (Contributed by NM, 14-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ⊆ On → ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ ∀𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 ¬ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵) → 𝐴 = ∩ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ord0 6417 | The empty set is an ordinal class. Remark 1.5 of [Schloeder] p. 1. (Contributed by NM, 11-May-1994.) |
⊢ Ord ∅ | ||
Theorem | 0elon 6418 | The empty set is an ordinal number. Corollary 7N(b) of [Enderton] p. 193. Remark 1.5 of [Schloeder] p. 1. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1993.) |
⊢ ∅ ∈ On | ||
Theorem | ord0eln0 6419 | A nonempty ordinal contains the empty set. Lemma 1.10 of [Schloeder] p. 2. (Contributed by NM, 25-Nov-1995.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → (∅ ∈ 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 ≠ ∅)) | ||
Theorem | on0eln0 6420 | An ordinal number contains zero iff it is nonzero. (Contributed by NM, 6-Dec-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (∅ ∈ 𝐴 ↔ 𝐴 ≠ ∅)) | ||
Theorem | dflim2 6421 | An alternate definition of a limit ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 4-Nov-2004.) |
⊢ (Lim 𝐴 ↔ (Ord 𝐴 ∧ ∅ ∈ 𝐴 ∧ 𝐴 = ∪ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | inton 6422 | The intersection of the class of ordinal numbers is the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 20-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ ∩ On = ∅ | ||
Theorem | nlim0 6423 | The empty set is not a limit ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 24-Mar-1995.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ ¬ Lim ∅ | ||
Theorem | limord 6424 | A limit ordinal is ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 4-May-1995.) |
⊢ (Lim 𝐴 → Ord 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | limuni 6425 | A limit ordinal is its own supremum (union). Lemma 2.13 of [Schloeder] p. 5. (Contributed by NM, 4-May-1995.) |
⊢ (Lim 𝐴 → 𝐴 = ∪ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | limuni2 6426 | The union of a limit ordinal is a limit ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 19-Sep-2006.) |
⊢ (Lim 𝐴 → Lim ∪ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | 0ellim 6427 | A limit ordinal contains the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 15-May-1994.) |
⊢ (Lim 𝐴 → ∅ ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | limelon 6428 | A limit ordinal class that is also a set is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 26-Apr-2004.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ Lim 𝐴) → 𝐴 ∈ On) | ||
Theorem | onn0 6429 | The class of all ordinal numbers is not empty. (Contributed by NM, 17-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ On ≠ ∅ | ||
Theorem | suceq 6430 | Equality of successors. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 25-Jul-2011.) |
⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → suc 𝐴 = suc 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | elsuci 6431 | Membership in a successor. This one-way implication does not require that either 𝐴 or 𝐵 be sets. Lemma 1.13 of [Schloeder] p. 2. (Contributed by NM, 6-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵 → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elsucg 6432 | Membership in a successor. Exercise 5 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 17. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | elsuc2g 6433 | Variant of membership in a successor, requiring that 𝐵 rather than 𝐴 be a set. (Contributed by NM, 28-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝑉 → (𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | elsuc 6434 | Membership in a successor. Exercise 5 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 17. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | elsuc2 6435 | Membership in a successor. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ suc 𝐴 ↔ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 ∨ 𝐵 = 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | nfsuc 6436 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for successor. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝐴 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥 suc 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | elelsuc 6437 | Membership in a successor. (Contributed by NM, 20-Jun-1998.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | sucel 6438* | Membership of a successor in another class. (Contributed by NM, 29-Jun-2004.) |
⊢ (suc 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ↔ ∃𝑥 ∈ 𝐵 ∀𝑦(𝑦 ∈ 𝑥 ↔ (𝑦 ∈ 𝐴 ∨ 𝑦 = 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | suc0 6439 | The successor of the empty set. (Contributed by NM, 1-Feb-2005.) |
⊢ suc ∅ = {∅} | ||
Theorem | sucprc 6440 | A proper class is its own successor. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ (¬ 𝐴 ∈ V → suc 𝐴 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | unisucs 6441 | The union of the successor of a set is equal to the binary union of that set with its union. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) Extract from unisuc 6443. (Revised by BJ, 28-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → ∪ suc 𝐴 = (∪ 𝐴 ∪ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | unisucg 6442 | A transitive class is equal to the union of its successor, closed form. Combines Theorem 4E of [Enderton] p. 72 and Exercise 6 of [Enderton] p. 73. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) Generalize from unisuc 6443. (Revised by BJ, 28-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∪ suc 𝐴 = 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | unisuc 6443 | A transitive class is equal to the union of its successor, inference form. Combines Theorem 4E of [Enderton] p. 72 and Exercise 6 of [Enderton] p. 73. (Contributed by NM, 30-Aug-1993.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (Tr 𝐴 ↔ ∪ suc 𝐴 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | sssucid 6444 | A class is included in its own successor. Part of Proposition 7.23 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 41 (generalized to arbitrary classes). (Contributed by NM, 31-May-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ⊆ suc 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | sucidg 6445 | Part of Proposition 7.23 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 41 (generalized). Lemma 1.7 of [Schloeder] p. 1. (Contributed by NM, 25-Mar-1995.) (Proof shortened by Scott Fenton, 20-Feb-2012.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | sucid 6446 | A set belongs to its successor. (Contributed by NM, 22-Jun-1994.) (Proof shortened by Alan Sare, 18-Feb-2012.) (Proof shortened by Scott Fenton, 20-Feb-2012.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | nsuceq0 6447 | No successor is empty. (Contributed by NM, 3-Apr-1995.) |
⊢ suc 𝐴 ≠ ∅ | ||
Theorem | eqelsuc 6448 | A set belongs to the successor of an equal set. (Contributed by NM, 18-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 = 𝐵 → 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | iunsuc 6449* | Inductive definition for the indexed union at a successor. (Contributed by Mario Carneiro, 4-Feb-2013.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 18-Nov-2016.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ V & ⊢ (𝑥 = 𝐴 → 𝐵 = 𝐶) ⇒ ⊢ ∪ 𝑥 ∈ suc 𝐴𝐵 = (∪ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝐵 ∪ 𝐶) | ||
Theorem | suctr 6450 | The successor of a transitive class is transitive. (Contributed by Alan Sare, 11-Apr-2009.) (Proof shortened by JJ, 24-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 → Tr suc 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | trsuc 6451 | A set whose successor belongs to a transitive class also belongs. (Contributed by NM, 5-Sep-2003.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ ((Tr 𝐴 ∧ suc 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) → 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | trsucss 6452 | A member of the successor of a transitive class is a subclass of it. Lemma 1.13 of [Schloeder] p. 2. (Contributed by NM, 4-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (Tr 𝐴 → (𝐵 ∈ suc 𝐴 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ordsssuc 6453 | An ordinal is a subset of another ordinal if and only if it belongs to its successor. (Contributed by NM, 28-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ Ord 𝐵) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | onsssuc 6454 | A subset of an ordinal number belongs to its successor. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ordsssuc2 6455 | An ordinal subset of an ordinal number belongs to its successor. (Contributed by NM, 1-Feb-2005.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ∈ suc 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | onmindif 6456 | When its successor is subtracted from a class of ordinal numbers, an ordinal number is less than the minimum of the resulting subclass. (Contributed by NM, 1-Dec-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → 𝐵 ∈ ∩ (𝐴 ∖ suc 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | ordnbtwn 6457 | There is no set between an ordinal class and its successor. Generalized Proposition 7.25 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 41. Lemma 1.15 of [Schloeder] p. 2. (Contributed by NM, 21-Jun-1998.) (Proof shortened by JJ, 24-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → ¬ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ suc 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | onnbtwn 6458 | There is no set between an ordinal number and its successor. Proposition 7.25 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 41. Lemma 1.15 of [Schloeder] p. 2. (Contributed by NM, 9-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → ¬ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ suc 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | sucssel 6459 | A set whose successor is a subset of another class is a member of that class. (Contributed by NM, 16-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ 𝑉 → (suc 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | orddif 6460 | Ordinal derived from its successor. (Contributed by NM, 20-May-1998.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → 𝐴 = (suc 𝐴 ∖ {𝐴})) | ||
Theorem | orduniss 6461 | An ordinal class includes its union. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → ∪ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | ordtri2or 6462 | A trichotomy law for ordinal classes. (Contributed by NM, 13-Sep-2003.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐵) → (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ordtri2or2 6463 | A trichotomy law for ordinal classes. (Contributed by NM, 2-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐵) → (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | ordtri2or3 6464 | A consequence of total ordering for ordinal classes. Similar to ordtri2or2 6463. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐵) → (𝐴 = (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) ∨ 𝐵 = (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵))) | ||
Theorem | ordelinel 6465 | The intersection of two ordinal classes is an element of a third if and only if either one of them is. (Contributed by David Moews, 1-May-2017.) (Proof shortened by JJ, 24-Sep-2021.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐵 ∧ Ord 𝐶) → ((𝐴 ∩ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐶 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∨ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | ordssun 6466 | Property of a subclass of the maximum (i.e. union) of two ordinals. (Contributed by NM, 28-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐵 ∧ Ord 𝐶) → (𝐴 ⊆ (𝐵 ∪ 𝐶) ↔ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | ordequn 6467 | The maximum (i.e. union) of two ordinals is either one or the other. Similar to Exercise 14 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 40. (Contributed by NM, 28-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐵 ∧ Ord 𝐶) → (𝐴 = (𝐵 ∪ 𝐶) → (𝐴 = 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | ordun 6468 | The maximum (i.e., union) of two ordinals is ordinal. Exercise 12 of [TakeutiZaring] p. 40. (Contributed by NM, 28-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((Ord 𝐴 ∧ Ord 𝐵) → Ord (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | onunel 6469 | The union of two ordinals is in a third iff both of the first two are. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 10-Sep-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On ∧ 𝐶 ∈ On) → ((𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ 𝐶 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐶 ∧ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐶))) | ||
Theorem | ordunisssuc 6470 | A subclass relationship for union and successor of ordinal classes. (Contributed by NM, 28-Nov-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ⊆ On ∧ Ord 𝐵) → (∪ 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 ⊆ suc 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | suc11 6471 | The successor operation behaves like a one-to-one function. Compare Exercise 16 of [Enderton] p. 194. (Contributed by NM, 3-Sep-2003.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (suc 𝐴 = suc 𝐵 ↔ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | onun2 6472 | The union of two ordinals is an ordinal. (Contributed by Scott Fenton, 9-Aug-2024.) |
⊢ ((𝐴 ∈ On ∧ 𝐵 ∈ On) → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ On) | ||
Theorem | ontr 6473 | An ordinal number is a transitive class. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1994.) Put in closed form. (Resised by BJ, 28-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → Tr 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | onunisuc 6474 | An ordinal number is equal to the union of its successor. (Contributed by NM, 12-Jun-1994.) Generalize from onunisuci 6484. (Revised by BJ, 28-Dec-2024.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → ∪ suc 𝐴 = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | onordi 6475 | An ordinal number is an ordinal class. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ Ord 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | ontrciOLD 6476 | Obsolete version of ontr 6473 as of 28-Dec-2024. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1994.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ Tr 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | onirri 6477 | An ordinal number is not a member of itself. Theorem 7M(c) of [Enderton] p. 192. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ ¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | oneli 6478 | A member of an ordinal number is an ordinal number. Theorem 7M(a) of [Enderton] p. 192. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 ∈ On) | ||
Theorem | onelssi 6479 | A member of an ordinal number is a subset of it. (Contributed by NM, 11-Aug-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | onssneli 6480 | An ordering law for ordinal numbers. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 → ¬ 𝐵 ∈ 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | onssnel2i 6481 | An ordering law for ordinal numbers. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴 → ¬ 𝐴 ∈ 𝐵) | ||
Theorem | onelini 6482 | An element of an ordinal number equals the intersection with it. (Contributed by NM, 11-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → 𝐵 = (𝐵 ∩ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | oneluni 6483 | An ordinal number equals its union with any element. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐵 ∈ 𝐴 → (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) = 𝐴) | ||
Theorem | onunisuci 6484 | An ordinal number is equal to the union of its successor. (Contributed by NM, 12-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ ∪ suc 𝐴 = 𝐴 | ||
Theorem | onsseli 6485 | Subset is equivalent to membership or equality for ordinal numbers. (Contributed by NM, 15-Sep-1995.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵 ↔ (𝐴 ∈ 𝐵 ∨ 𝐴 = 𝐵)) | ||
Theorem | onun2i 6486 | The union of two ordinal numbers is an ordinal number. (Contributed by NM, 13-Jun-1994.) |
⊢ 𝐴 ∈ On & ⊢ 𝐵 ∈ On ⇒ ⊢ (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) ∈ On | ||
Theorem | unizlim 6487 | An ordinal equal to its own union is either zero or a limit ordinal. (Contributed by NM, 1-Oct-2003.) |
⊢ (Ord 𝐴 → (𝐴 = ∪ 𝐴 ↔ (𝐴 = ∅ ∨ Lim 𝐴))) | ||
Theorem | on0eqel 6488 | An ordinal number either equals zero or contains zero. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jun-2004.) |
⊢ (𝐴 ∈ On → (𝐴 = ∅ ∨ ∅ ∈ 𝐴)) | ||
Theorem | snsn0non 6489 | The singleton of the singleton of the empty set is not an ordinal (nor a natural number by omsson 7858). It can be used to represent an "undefined" value for a partial operation on natural or ordinal numbers. See also onxpdisj 6490. (Contributed by NM, 21-May-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 12-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ ¬ {{∅}} ∈ On | ||
Theorem | onxpdisj 6490 | Ordinal numbers and ordered pairs are disjoint collections. This theorem can be used if we want to extend a set of ordinal numbers or ordered pairs with disjoint elements. See also snsn0non 6489. (Contributed by NM, 1-Jun-2004.) (Proof shortened by Andrew Salmon, 27-Aug-2011.) |
⊢ (On ∩ (V × V)) = ∅ | ||
Theorem | onnev 6491 | The class of ordinal numbers is not equal to the universe. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jun-2007.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jan-2013.) (Proof shortened by Wolf Lammen, 27-May-2024.) |
⊢ On ≠ V | ||
Theorem | onnevOLD 6492 | Obsolete version of onnev 6491 as of 27-May-2024. (Contributed by NM, 16-Jun-2007.) (Proof shortened by Mario Carneiro, 10-Jan-2013.) (Proof modification is discouraged.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ On ≠ V | ||
Syntax | cio 6493 | Extend class notation with Russell's definition description binder (inverted iota). |
class (℩𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | iotajust 6494* | Soundness justification theorem for df-iota 6495. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 29-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ ∪ {𝑦 ∣ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑦}} = ∪ {𝑧 ∣ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑧}} | ||
Definition | df-iota 6495* |
Define Russell's definition description binder, which can be read as
"the unique 𝑥 such that 𝜑", where 𝜑
ordinarily contains
𝑥 as a free variable. Our definition
is meaningful only when there
is exactly one 𝑥 such that 𝜑 is true (see iotaval 6514);
otherwise, it evaluates to the empty set (see iotanul 6521). Russell used
the inverted iota symbol ℩ to represent
the binder.
Sometimes proofs need to expand an iota-based definition. That is, given "X = the x for which ... x ... x ..." holds, the proof needs to get to "... X ... X ...". A general strategy to do this is to use riotacl2 7381 (or iotacl 6529 for unbounded iota), as demonstrated in the proof of supub 9453. This can be easier than applying riotasbc 7383 or a version that applies an explicit substitution, because substituting an iota into its own property always has a bound variable clash which must be first renamed or else guarded with NF. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 30-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = ∪ {𝑦 ∣ {𝑥 ∣ 𝜑} = {𝑦}} | ||
Theorem | dfiota2 6496* | Alternate definition for descriptions. Definition 8.18 in [Quine] p. 56. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 30-Jun-2011.) |
⊢ (℩𝑥𝜑) = ∪ {𝑦 ∣ ∀𝑥(𝜑 ↔ 𝑥 = 𝑦)} | ||
Theorem | nfiota1 6497 | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the ℩ class. (Contributed by Andrew Salmon, 11-Jul-2011.) (Revised by Mario Carneiro, 15-Oct-2016.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(℩𝑥𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfiotadw 6498* | Deduction version of nfiotaw 6499. Version of nfiotad 6500 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2371. (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2013.) Avoid ax-13 2371. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 26-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(℩𝑦𝜓)) | ||
Theorem | nfiotaw 6499* | Bound-variable hypothesis builder for the ℩ class. Version of nfiota 6501 with a disjoint variable condition, which does not require ax-13 2371. (Contributed by NM, 23-Aug-2011.) Avoid ax-13 2371. (Revised by Gino Giotto, 26-Jan-2024.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑥𝜑 ⇒ ⊢ Ⅎ𝑥(℩𝑦𝜑) | ||
Theorem | nfiotad 6500 | Deduction version of nfiota 6501. Usage of this theorem is discouraged because it depends on ax-13 2371. Use the weaker nfiotadw 6498 when possible. (Contributed by NM, 18-Feb-2013.) (New usage is discouraged.) |
⊢ Ⅎ𝑦𝜑 & ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥𝜓) ⇒ ⊢ (𝜑 → Ⅎ𝑥(℩𝑦𝜓)) |
< Previous Next > |
Copyright terms: Public domain | < Previous Next > |